I.Kant

THE CRITIQUE OF PURE REASON

1781

translated by J. M. D. Meiklejohn

                      

            PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION, 1781



  Human reason, in one sphere of its cognition, is called upon to

consider questions, which it cannot decline, as they are presented

by its own nature, but which it cannot answer, as they transcend every

faculty of the mind.

  It falls into this difficulty without any fault of its own. It

begins with principles, which cannot be dispensed with in the field of

experience, and the truth and sufficiency of which are, at the same

time, insured by experience. With these principles it rises, in

obedience to the laws of its own nature, to ever higher and more

remote conditions. But it quickly discovers that, in this way, its

labours must remain ever incomplete, because new questions never cease

to present themselves; and thus it finds itself compelled to have

recourse to principles which transcend the region of experience, while

they are regarded by common sense without distrust. It thus falls into

confusion and contradictions, from which it conjectures the presence

of latent errors, which, however, it is unable to discover, because

the principles it employs, transcending the limits of experience,

cannot be tested by that criterion. The arena of these endless

contests is called Metaphysic.

  Time was, when she was the queen of all the sciences; and, if we

take the will for the deed, she certainly deserves, so far as

regards the high importance of her object-matter, this title of

honour. Now, it is the fashion of the time to heap contempt and

scorn upon her; and the matron mourns, forlorn and forsaken, like

Hecuba:



                  Modo maxima rerum,

                Tot generis, natisque potens...

                Nunc trahor exul, inops.*



  *Ovid, Metamorphoses. [xiii, "But late on the pinnacle of fame,

strong in my many sons. now exiled, penniless."]



  At first, her government, under the administration of the

dogmatists, was an absolute despotism. But, as the legislative

continued to show traces of the ancient barbaric rule, her empire

gradually broke up, and intestine wars introduced the reign of

anarchy; while the sceptics, like nomadic tribes, who hate a permanent

habitation and settled mode of living, attacked from time to time

those who had organized themselves into civil communities. But their

number was, very happily, small; and thus they could not entirely

put a stop to the exertions of those who persisted in raising new

edifices, although on no settled or uniform plan. In recent times

the hope dawned upon us of seeing those disputes settled, and the

legitimacy of her claims established by a kind of physiology of the

human understanding- that of the celebrated Locke. But it was found

that- although it was affirmed that this so-called queen could not

refer her descent to any higher source than that of common experience,

a circumstance which necessarily brought suspicion on her claims- as

this genealogy was incorrect, she persisted in the advancement of

her claims to sovereignty. Thus metaphysics necessarily fell back into

the antiquated and rotten constitution of dogmatism, and again

became obnoxious to the contempt from which efforts had been made to

save it. At present, as all methods, according to the general

persuasion, have been tried in vain, there reigns nought but weariness

and complete indifferentism- the mother of chaos and night in the

scientific world, but at the same time the source of, or at least

the prelude to, the re-creation and reinstallation of a science,

when it has fallen into confusion, obscurity, and disuse from ill

directed effort.

  For it is in reality vain to profess indifference in regard to

such inquiries, the object of which cannot be indifferent to humanity.

Besides, these pretended indifferentists, however much they may try to

disguise themselves by the assumption of a popular style and by

changes on the language of the schools, unavoidably fall into

metaphysical declarations and propositions, which they profess to

regard with so much contempt. At the same time, this indifference,

which has arisen in the world of science, and which relates to that

kind of knowledge which we should wish to see destroyed the last, is a

phenomenon that well deserves our attention and reflection. It is

plainly not the effect of the levity, but of the matured judgement* of

the age, which refuses to be any longer entertained with illusory

knowledge, It is, in fact, a call to reason, again to undertake the

most laborious of all tasks- that of self-examination- and to

establish a tribunal, which may secure it in its well-grounded claims,

while it pronounces against all baseless assumptions and

pretensions, not in an arbitrary manner, but according to its own

eternal and unchangeable laws. This tribunal is nothing less than

the critical investigation of pure reason.



  *We very often hear complaints of the shallowness of the present

age, and of the decay of profound science. But I do not think that

those which rest upon a secure foundation, such as mathematics,

physical science, etc., in the least deserve this reproach, but that

they rather maintain their ancient fame, and in the latter case,

indeed, far surpass it. The same would be the case with the other

kinds of cognition, if their principles were but firmly established.

In the absence of this security, indifference, doubt, and finally,

severe criticism are rather signs of a profound habit of thought.

Our age is the age of criticism, to which everything must be

subjected. The sacredness of religion, and the authority of

legislation, are by many regarded as grounds of exemption from the

examination of this tribunal. But, if they on they are exempted,

they become the subjects of just suspicion, and cannot lay claim to

sincere respect, which reason accords only to that which has stood the

test of a free and public examination.



  I do not mean by this a criticism of books and systems, but a

critical inquiry into the faculty of reason, with reference to the

cognitions to which it strives to attain without the aid of

experience; in other words, the solution of the question regarding the

possibility or impossibility of metaphysics, and the determination

of the origin, as well as of the extent and limits of this science.

All this must be done on the basis of principles.

  This path- the only one now remaining- has been entered upon by

me; and I flatter myself that I have, in this way, discovered the

cause of- and consequently the mode of removing- all the errors

which have hitherto set reason at variance with itself, in the

sphere of non-empirical thought. I have not returned an evasive answer

to the questions of reason, by alleging the inability and limitation

of the faculties of the mind; I have, on the contrary, examined them

completely in the light of principles, and, after having discovered

the cause of the doubts and contradictions into which reason fell,

have solved them to its perfect satisfaction. It is true, these

questions have not been solved as dogmatism, in its vain fancies and

desires, had expected; for it can only be satisfied by the exercise of

magical arts, and of these I have no knowledge. But neither do these

come within the compass of our mental powers; and it was the duty of

philosophy to destroy the illusions which had their origin in

misconceptions, whatever darling hopes and valued expectations may

be ruined by its explanations. My chief aim in this work has been

thoroughness; and I make bold to say that there is not a single

metaphysical problem that does not find its solution, or at least

the key to its solution, here. Pure reason is a perfect unity; and

therefore, if the if the principle presented by it prove to be

insufficient for the solution of even a single one of those

questions to which the very nature of reason gives birth, we must

reject it, as we could not be perfectly certain of its sufficiency

in the case of the others.

  While I say this, I think I see upon the countenance of the reader

signs of dissatisfaction mingled with contempt, when he hears

declarations which sound so boastful and extravagant; and yet they are

beyond comparison more moderate than those advanced by the commonest

author of the commonest philosophical programme, in which the

dogmatist professes to demonstrate the simple nature of the soul, or

the necessity of a primal being. Such a dogmatist promises to extend

human knowledge beyond the limits of possible experience; while I

humbly confess that this is completely beyond my power. Instead of any

such attempt, I confine myself to the examination of reason alone

and its pure thought; and I do not need to seek far for the

sum-total of its cognition, because it has its seat in my own mind.

Besides, common logic presents me with a complete and systematic

catalogue of all the simple operations of reason; and it is my task to

answer the question how far reason can go, without the material

presented and the aid furnished by experience.

  So much for the completeness and thoroughness necessary in the

execution of the present task. The aims set before us are not

arbitrarily proposed, but are imposed upon us by the nature of

cognition itself.

  The above remarks relate to the matter of our critical inquiry. As

regards the form, there are two indispensable conditions, which any

one who undertakes so difficult a task as that of a critique of pure

reason, is bound to fulfil. These conditions are certitude and

clearness.

  As regards certitude, I have fully convinced myself that, in this

sphere of thought, opinion is perfectly inadmissible, and that

everything which bears the least semblance of an hypothesis must be

excluded, as of no value in such discussions. For it is a necessary

condition of every cognition that is to be established upon a priori

grounds that it shall be held to be absolutely necessary; much more is

this the case with an attempt to determine all pure a priori

cognition, and to furnish the standard- and consequently an example-

of all apodeictic (philosophical) certitude. Whether I have

succeeded in what I professed to do, it is for the reader to

determine; it is the author's business merely to adduce grounds and

reasons, without determining what influence these ought to have on the

mind of his judges. But, lest anything he may have said may become the

innocent cause of doubt in their minds, or tend to weaken the effect

which his arguments might otherwise produce- he may be allowed to

point out those passages which may occasion mistrust or difficulty,

although these do not concern the main purpose of the present work. He

does this solely with the view of removing from the mind of the reader

any doubts which might affect his judgement of the work as a whole,

and in regard to its ultimate aim.

  I know no investigations more necessary for a full insight into

the nature of the faculty which we call understanding, and at the same

time for the determination of the rules and limits of its use, than

those undertaken in the second chapter of the "Transcendental

Analytic," under the title of "Deduction of the Pure Conceptions of

the Understanding"; and they have also cost me by far the greatest

labour- labour which, I hope, will not remain uncompensated. The

view there taken, which goes somewhat deeply into the subject, has two

sides, The one relates to the objects of the pure understanding, and

is intended to demonstrate and to render comprehensible the

objective validity of its a priori conceptions; and it forms for

this reason an essential part of the Critique. The other considers the

pure understanding itself, its possibility and its powers of

cognition- that is, from a subjective point of view; and, although

this exposition is of great importance, it does not belong essentially

to the main purpose of the work, because the grand question is what

and how much can reason and understanding, apart from experience,

cognize, and not, how is the faculty of thought itself possible? As

the latter is an, inquiry into the cause of a given effect, and has

thus in it some semblance of an hypothesis (although, as I shall

show on another occasion, this is really not the fact), it would

seem that, in the present instance, I had allowed myself to enounce

a mere opinion, and that the reader must therefore be at liberty to

hold a different opinion. But I beg to remind him that, if my

subjective deduction does not produce in his mind the conviction of

its certitude at which I aimed, the objective deduction, with which

alone the present work is properly concerned, is in every respect

satisfactory.

  As regards clearness, the reader has a right to demand, in the first

place, discursive or logical clearness, that is, on the basis of

conceptions, and, secondly, intuitive or aesthetic clearness, by means

of intuitions, that is, by examples or other modes of illustration

in concreto. I have done what I could for the first kind of

intelligibility. This was essential to my purpose; and it thus

became the accidental cause of my inability to do complete justice

to the second requirement. I have been almost always at a loss, during

the progress of this work, how to settle this question. Examples and

illustrations always appeared to me necessary, and, in the first

sketch of the Critique, naturally fell into their proper places. But I

very soon became aware of the magnitude of my task, and the numerous

problems with which I should be engaged; and, as I perceived that this

critical investigation would, even if delivered in the driest

scholastic manner, be far from being brief, I found it unadvisable

to enlarge it still more with examples and explanations, which are

necessary only from a popular point of view. I was induced to take

this course from the consideration also that the present work is not

intended for popular use, that those devoted to science do not require

such helps, although they are always acceptable, and that they would

have materially interfered with my present purpose. Abbe Terrasson

remarks with great justice that, if we estimate the size of a work,

not from the number of its pages, but from the time which we require

to make ourselves master of it, it may be said of many a book that

it would be much shorter, if it were not so short. On the other

hand, as regards the comprehensibility of a system of speculative

cognition, connected under a single principle, we may say with equal

justice: many a book would have been much clearer, if it had not

been intended to be so very clear. For explanations and examples,

and other helps to intelligibility, aid us in the comprehension of

parts, but they distract the attention, dissipate the mental power

of the reader, and stand in the way of his forming a clear

conception of the whole; as he cannot attain soon enough to a survey

of the system, and the colouring and embellishments bestowed upon it

prevent his observing its articulation or organization- which is the

most important consideration with him, when he comes to judge of its

unity and stability.

  The reader must naturally have a strong inducement to co-operate

with the present author, if he has formed the intention of erecting

a complete and solid edifice of metaphysical science, according to the

plan now laid before him. Metaphysics, as here represented, is the

only science which admits of completion- and with little labour, if it

is united, in a short time; so that nothing will be left to future

generations except the task of illustrating and applying it

didactically. For this science is nothing more than the inventory of

all that is given us by pure reason, systematically arranged.

Nothing can escape our notice; for what reason produces from itself

cannot lie concealed, but must be brought to the light by reason

itself, so soon as we have discovered the common principle of the

ideas we seek. The perfect unity of this kind of cognitions, which are

based upon pure conceptions, and uninfluenced by any empirical

element, or any peculiar intuition leading to determinate

experience, renders this completeness not only practicable, but also

necessary.



     Tecum habita, et noris quam sit tibi curta supellex.*



  *Persius. [Satirae iv. 52. "Dwell with yourself, and you will know

how short your household stuff is."



  Such a system of pure speculative reason I hope to be able to

publish under the title of Metaphysic of Nature. The content of this

work (which will not be half so long) will be very much richer than

that of the present Critique, which has to discover the sources of

this cognition and expose the conditions of its possibility, and at

the same time to clear and level a fit foundation for the scientific

edifice. In the present work, I look for the patient hearing and the

impartiality of a judge; in the other, for the good-will and

assistance of a co-labourer. For, however complete the list of

principles for this system may be in the Critique, the correctness

of the system requires that no deduced conceptions should be absent.

These cannot be presented a priori, but must be gradually

discovered; and, while the synthesis of conceptions has been fully

exhausted in the Critique, it is necessary that, in the proposed work,

the same should be the case with their analysis. But this will be

rather an amusement than a labour.

             PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION, 1787



  Whether the treatment of that portion of our knowledge which lies

within the province of pure reason advances with that undeviating

certainty which characterizes the progress of science, we shall be

at no loss to determine. If we find those who are engaged in

metaphysical pursuits, unable to come to an understanding as to the

method which they ought to follow; if we find them, after the most

elaborate preparations, invariably brought to a stand before the

goal is reached, and compelled to retrace their steps and strike

into fresh paths, we may then feel quite sure that they are far from

having attained to the certainty of scientific progress and may rather

be said to be merely groping about in the dark. In these circumstances

we shall render an important service to reason if we succeed in simply

indicating the path along which it must travel, in order to arrive

at any results- even if it should be found necessary to abandon many

of those aims which, without reflection, have been proposed for its

attainment.

  That logic has advanced in this sure course, even from the

earliest times, is apparent from the fact that, since Aristotle, it

has been unable to advance a step and, thus, to all appearance has

reached its completion. For, if some of the moderns have thought to

enlarge its domain by introducing psychological discussions on the

mental faculties, such as imagination and wit, metaphysical,

discussions on the origin of knowledge and the different kinds of

certitude, according to the difference of the objects (idealism,

scepticism, and so on), or anthropological discussions on

prejudices, their causes and remedies: this attempt, on the part of

these authors, only shows their ignorance of the peculiar nature of

logical science. We do not enlarge but disfigure the sciences when

we lose sight of their respective limits and allow them to run into

one another. Now logic is enclosed within limits which admit of

perfectly clear definition; it is a science which has for its object

nothing but the exposition and proof of the formal laws of all

thought, whether it be a priori or empirical, whatever be its origin

or its object, and whatever the difficulties- natural or accidental-

which it encounters in the human mind.

  The early success of logic must be attributed exclusively to the

narrowness of its field, in which abstraction may, or rather must,

be made of all the objects of cognition with their characteristic

distinctions, and in which the understanding has only to deal with

itself and with its own forms. It is, obviously, a much more difficult

task for reason to strike into the sure path of science, where it

has to deal not simply with itself, but with objects external to

itself. Hence, logic is properly only a propaedeutic- forms, as it

were, the vestibule of the sciences; and while it is necessary to

enable us to form a correct judgement with regard to the various

branches of knowledge, still the acquisition of real, substantive

knowledge is to be sought only in the sciences properly so called,

that is, in the objective sciences.

  Now these sciences, if they can be termed rational at all, must

contain elements of a priori cognition, and this cognition may stand

in a twofold relation to its object. Either it may have to determine

the conception of the object- which must be supplied extraneously,

or it may have to establish its reality. The former is theoretical,

the latter practical, rational cognition. In both, the pure or a

priori element must be treated first, and must be carefully

distinguished from that which is supplied from other sources. Any

other method can only lead to irremediable confusion.

  Mathematics and physics are the two theoretical sciences which

have to determine their objects a priori. The former is purely a

priori, the latter is partially so, but is also dependent on other

sources of cognition.

  In the earliest times of which history affords us any record,

mathematics had already entered on the sure course of science, among

that wonderful nation, the Greeks. Still it is not to be supposed that

it was as easy for this science to strike into, or rather to construct

for itself, that royal road, as it was for logic, in which reason

has only to deal with itself. On the contrary, I believe that it

must have remained long- chiefly among the Egyptians- in the stage

of blind groping after its true aims and destination, and that it

was revolutionized by the happy idea of one man, who struck out and

determined for all time the path which this science must follow, and

which admits of an indefinite advancement. The history of this

intellectual revolution- much more important in its results than the

discovery of the passage round the celebrated Cape of Good Hope- and

of its author, has not been preserved. But Diogenes Laertius, in

naming the supposed discoverer of some of the simplest elements of

geometrical demonstration- elements which, according to the ordinary

opinion, do not even require to be proved- makes it apparent that

the change introduced by the first indication of this new path, must

have seemed of the utmost importance to the mathematicians of that

age, and it has thus been secured against the chance of oblivion. A

new light must have flashed on the mind of the first man (Thales, or

whatever may have been his name) who demonstrated the properties of

the isosceles triangle. For he found that it was not sufficient to

meditate on the figure, as it lay before his eyes, or the conception

of it, as it existed in his mind, and thus endeavour to get at the

knowledge of its properties, but that it was necessary to produce

these properties, as it were, by a positive a priori construction; and

that, in order to arrive with certainty at a priori cognition, he must

not attribute to the object any other properties than those which

necessarily followed from that which he had himself, in accordance

with his conception, placed in the object.

  A much longer period elapsed before physics entered on the highway

of science. For it is only about a century and a half since the wise

Bacon gave a new direction to physical studies, or rather- as others

were already on the right track- imparted fresh vigour to the

pursuit of this new direction. Here, too, as in the case of

mathematics, we find evidence of a rapid intellectual revolution. In

the remarks which follow I shall confine myself to the empirical

side of natural science.

  When Galilei experimented with balls of a definite weight on the

inclined plane, when Torricelli caused the air to sustain a weight

which he had calculated beforehand to be equal to that of a definite

column of water, or when Stahl, at a later period, converted metals

into lime, and reconverted lime into metal, by the addition and

subtraction of certain elements;* a light broke upon all natural

philosophers. They learned that reason only perceives that which it

produces after its own design; that it must not be content to

follow, as it were, in the leading-strings of nature, but must proceed

in advance with principles of judgement according to unvarying laws,

and compel nature to reply its questions. For accidental observations,

made according to no preconceived plan, cannot be united under a

necessary law. But it is this that reason seeks for and requires. It

is only the principles of reason which can give to concordant

phenomena the validity of laws, and it is only when experiment is

directed by these rational principles that it can have any real

utility. Reason must approach nature with the view, indeed, of

receiving information from it, not, however, in the character of a

pupil, who listens to all that his master chooses to tell him, but

in that of a judge, who compels the witnesses to reply to those

questions which he himself thinks fit to propose. To this single

idea must the revolution be ascribed, by which, after groping in the

dark for so many centuries, natural science was at length conducted

into the path of certain progress.



  *I do not here follow with exactness the history of the experimental

method, of which, indeed, the first steps are involved in some

obscurity.



  We come now to metaphysics, a purely speculative science, which

occupies a completely isolated position and is entirely independent of

the teachings of experience. It deals with mere conceptions- not, like

mathematics, with conceptions applied to intuition- and in it,

reason is the pupil of itself alone. It is the oldest of the sciences,

and would still survive, even if all the rest were swallowed up in the

abyss of an all-destroying barbarism. But it has not yet had the

good fortune to attain to the sure scientific method. This will be

apparent; if we apply the tests which we proposed at the outset. We

find that reason perpetually comes to a stand, when it attempts to

gain a priori the perception even of those laws which the most

common experience confirms. We find it compelled to retrace its

steps in innumerable instances, and to abandon the path on which it

had entered, because this does not lead to the desired result. We

find, too, that those who are engaged in metaphysical pursuits are far

from being able to agree among themselves, but that, on the

contrary, this science appears to furnish an arena specially adapted

for the display of skill or the exercise of strength in mock-contests-

a field in which no combatant ever yet succeeded in gaining an inch of

ground, in which, at least, no victory was ever yet crowned with

permanent possession.

  This leads us to inquire why it is that, in metaphysics, the sure

path of science has not hitherto been found. Shall we suppose that

it is impossible to discover it? Why then should nature have visited

our reason with restless aspirations after it, as if it were one of

our weightiest concerns? Nay, more, how little cause should we have to

place confidence in our reason, if it abandons us in a matter about

which, most of all, we desire to know the truth- and not only so,

but even allures us to the pursuit of vain phantoms, only to betray us

in the end? Or, if the path has only hitherto been missed, what

indications do we possess to guide us in a renewed investigation,

and to enable us to hope for greater success than has fallen to the

lot of our predecessors?

  It appears to me that the examples of mathematics and natural

philosophy, which, as we have seen, were brought into their present

condition by a sudden revolution, are sufficiently remarkable to fix

our attention on the essential circumstances of the change which has

proved so advantageous to them, and to induce us to make the

experiment of imitating them, so far as the analogy which, as rational

sciences, they bear to metaphysics may permit. It has hitherto been

assumed that our cognition must conform to the objects; but all

attempts to ascertain anything about these objects a priori, by

means of conceptions, and thus to extend the range of our knowledge,

have been rendered abortive by this assumption. Let us then make the

experiment whether we may not be more successful in metaphysics, if we

assume that the objects must conform to our cognition. This appears,

at all events, to accord better with the possibility of our gaining

the end we have in view, that is to say, of arriving at the

cognition of objects a priori, of determining something with respect

to these objects, before they are given to us. We here propose to do

just what Copernicus did in attempting to explain the celestial

movements. When he found that he could make no progress by assuming

that all the heavenly bodies revolved round the spectator, he reversed

the process, and tried the experiment of assuming that the spectator

revolved, while the stars remained at rest. We may make the same

experiment with regard to the intuition of objects. If the intuition

must conform to the nature of the objects, I do not see how we can

know anything of them a priori. If, on the other hand, the object

conforms to the nature of our faculty of intuition, I can then

easily conceive the possibility of such an a priori knowledge. Now

as I cannot rest in the mere intuitions, but- if they are to become

cognitions- must refer them, as representations, to something, as

object, and must determine the latter by means of the former, here

again there are two courses open to me. Either, first, I may assume

that the conceptions, by which I effect this determination, conform to

the object- and in this case I am reduced to the same perplexity as

before; or secondly, I may assume that the objects, or, which is the

same thing, that experience, in which alone as given objects they

are cognized, conform to my conceptions- and then I am at no loss

how to proceed. For experience itself is a mode of cognition which

requires understanding. Before objects, are given to me, that is, a

priori, I must presuppose in myself laws of the understanding which

are expressed in conceptions a priori. To these conceptions, then, all

the objects of experience must necessarily conform. Now there are

objects which reason thinks, and that necessarily, but which cannot be

given in experience, or, at least, cannot be given so as reason thinks

them. The attempt to think these objects will hereafter furnish an

excellent test of the new method of thought which we have adopted, and

which is based on the principle that we only cognize in things a

priori that which we ourselves place in them.*



  *This method, accordingly, which we have borrowed from the natural

philosopher, consists in seeking for the elements of pure reason in

that which admits of confirmation or refutation by experiment. Now the

propositions of pure reason, especially when they transcend the limits

of possible experience, do not admit of our making any experiment with

their objects, as in natural science. Hence, with regard to those

conceptions and principles which we assume a priori, our only course

ill be to view them from two different sides. We must regard one and

the same conception, on the one hand, in relation to experience as

an object of the senses and of the understanding, on the other hand,

in relation to reason, isolated and transcending the limits of

experience, as an object of mere thought. Now if we find that, when we

regard things from this double point of view, the result is in harmony

with the principle of pure reason, but that, when we regard them

from a single point of view, reason is involved in self-contradiction,

then the experiment will establish the correctness of this

distinction.



  This attempt succeeds as well as we could desire, and promises to

metaphysics, in its first part- that is, where it is occupied with

conceptions a priori, of which the corresponding objects may be

given in experience- the certain course of science. For by this new

method we are enabled perfectly to explain the possibility of a priori

cognition, and, what is more, to demonstrate satisfactorily the laws

which lie a priori at the foundation of nature, as the sum of the

objects of experience- neither of which was possible according to

the procedure hitherto followed. But from this deduction of the

faculty of a priori cognition in the first part of metaphysics, we

derive a surprising result, and one which, to all appearance,

militates against the great end of metaphysics, as treated in the

second part. For we come to the conclusion that our faculty of

cognition is unable to transcend the limits of possible experience;

and yet this is precisely the most essential object of this science.

The estimate of our rational cognition a priori at which we arrive

is that it has only to do with phenomena, and that things in

themselves, while possessing a real existence, lie beyond its

sphere. Here we are enabled to put the justice of this estimate to the

test. For that which of necessity impels us to transcend the limits of

experience and of all phenomena is the unconditioned, which reason

absolutely requires in things as they are in themselves, in order to

complete the series of conditions. Now, if it appears that when, on

the one hand, we assume that our cognition conforms to its objects

as things in themselves, the unconditioned cannot be thought without

contradiction, and that when, on the other hand, we assume that our

representation of things as they are given to us, does not conform

to these things as they are in themselves, but that these objects,

as phenomena, conform to our mode of representation, the contradiction

disappears: we shall then be convinced of the truth of that which we

began by assuming for the sake of experiment; we may look upon it as

established that the unconditioned does not lie in things as we know

them, or as they are given to us, but in things as they are in

themselves, beyond the range of our cognition.*



  *This experiment of pure reason has a great similarity to that of

the chemists, which they term the experiment of reduction, or, more

usually, the synthetic process. The analysis of the metaphysician

separates pure cognition a priori into two heterogeneous elements,

viz., the cognition of things as phenomena, and of things in

themselves. Dialectic combines these again into harmony with the

necessary rational idea of the unconditioned, and finds that this

harmony never results except through the above distinction, which

is, therefore, concluded to be just.



  But, after we have thus denied the power of speculative reason to

make any progress in the sphere of the supersensible, it still remains

for our consideration whether data do not exist in practical cognition

which may enable us to determine the transcendent conception of the

unconditioned, to rise beyond the limits of all possible experience

from a practical point of view, and thus to satisfy the great ends

of metaphysics. Speculative reason has thus, at least, made room for

such an extension of our knowledge: and, if it must leave this space

vacant, still it does not rob us of the liberty to fill it up, if we

can, by means of practical data- nay, it even challenges us to make

the attempt.*



  *So the central laws of the movements of the heavenly bodies

established the truth of that which Copernicus, first, assumed only as

a hypothesis, and, at the same time, brought to light that invisible

force (Newtonian attraction) which holds the universe together. The

latter would have remained forever undiscovered, if Copernicus had not

ventured on the experiment- contrary to the senses but still just-

of looking for the observed movements not in the heavenly bodies,

but in the spectator. In this Preface I treat the new metaphysical

method as a hypothesis with the view of rendering apparent the first

attempts at such a change of method, which are always hypothetical.

But in the Critique itself it will be demonstrated, not

hypothetically, but apodeictically, from the nature of our

representations of space and time. and from the elementary conceptions

of the understanding.



  This attempt to introduce a complete revolution in the procedure

of metaphysics, after the example of the geometricians and natural

philosophers, constitutes the aim of the Critique of Pure

Speculative Reason. It is a treatise on the method to be followed, not

a system of the science itself. But, at the same time, it marks out

and defines both the external boundaries and the internal structure of

this science. For pure speculative reason has this peculiarity,

that, in choosing the various objects of thought, it is able to define

the limits of its own faculties, and even to give a complete

enumeration of the possible modes of proposing problems to itself, and

thus to sketch out the entire system of metaphysics. For, on the one

hand, in cognition a priori, nothing must be attributed to the objects

but what the thinking subject derives from itself; and, on the other

hand, reason is, in regard to the principles of cognition, a perfectly

distinct, independent unity, in which, as in an organized body,

every member exists for the sake of the others, and all for the sake

of each, so that no principle can be viewed, with safety, in one

relationship, unless it is, at the same time, viewed in relation to

the total use of pure reason. Hence, too, metaphysics has this

singular advantage- an advantage which falls to the lot of no other

science which has to do with objects- that, if once it is conducted

into the sure path of science, by means of this criticism, it can then

take in the whole sphere of its cognitions, and can thus complete

its work, and leave it for the use of posterity, as a capital which

can never receive fresh accessions. For metaphysics has to deal only

with principles and with the limitations of its own employment as

determined by these principles. To this perfection it is, therefore,

bound, as the fundamental science, to attain, and to it the maxim

may justly be applied:



    Nil actum reputans, si quid superesset agendum.*



  *"He considered nothing done, so long as anything remained to be

done."



  But, it will be asked, what kind of a treasure is this that we

propose to bequeath to posterity? What is the real value of this

system of metaphysics, purified by criticism, and thereby reduced to a

permanent condition? A cursory view of the present work will lead to

the supposition that its use is merely negative, that it only serves

to warn us against venturing, with speculative reason, beyond the

limits of experience. This is, in fact, its primary use. But this,

at once, assumes a positive value, when we observe that the principles

with which speculative reason endeavours to transcend its limits

lead inevitably, not to the extension, but to the contraction of the

use of reason, inasmuch as they threaten to extend the limits of

sensibility, which is their proper sphere, over the entire realm of

thought and, thus, to supplant the pure (practical) use of reason.

So far, then, as this criticism is occupied in confining speculative

reason within its proper bounds, it is only negative; but, inasmuch as

it thereby, at the same time, removes an obstacle which impedes and

even threatens to destroy the use of practical reason, it possesses

a positive and very important value. In order to admit this, we have

only to be convinced that there is an absolutely necessary use of pure

reason- the moral use- in which it inevitably transcends the limits of

sensibility, without the aid of speculation, requiring only to be

insured against the effects of a speculation which would involve it in

contradiction with itself. To deny the positive advantage of the

service which this criticism renders us would be as absurd as. to

maintain that the system of police is productive of no positive

benefit, since its main business is to prevent the violence which

citizen has to apprehend from citizen, that so each may pursue his

vocation in peace and security. That space and time are only forms

of sensible intuition, and hence are only conditions of the

existence of things as phenomena; that, moreover, we have no

conceptions of the understanding, and, consequently, no elements for

the cognition of things, except in so far as a corresponding intuition

can be given to these conceptions; that, accordingly, we can have no

cognition of an object, as a thing in itself, but only as an object of

sensible intuition, that is, as phenomenon- all this is proved in

the analytical part of the Critique; and from this the limitation of

all possible speculative cognition to the mere objects of

experience, follows as a necessary result. At the same time, it must

be carefully borne in mind that, while we surrender the power of

cognizing, we still reserve the power of thinking objects, as things

in themselves.* For, otherwise, we should require to affirm the

existence of an appearance, without something that appears- which

would be absurd. Now let us suppose, for a moment, that we had not

undertaken this criticism and, accordingly, had not drawn the

necessary distinction between things as objects of experience and

things as they are in themselves. The principle of causality, and,

by consequence, the mechanism of nature as determined by causality,

would then have absolute validity in relation to all things as

efficient causes. I should then be unable to assert, with regard to

one and the same being, e.g., the human soul, that its will is free,

and yet, at the same time, subject to natural necessity, that is,

not free, without falling into a palpable contradiction, for in both

propositions I should take the soul in the same signification, as a

thing in general, as a thing in itself- as, without previous

criticism, I could not but take it. Suppose now, on the other hand,

that we have undertaken this criticism, and have learnt that an object

may be taken in two senses, first, as a phenomenon, secondly, as a

thing in itself; and that, according to the deduction of the

conceptions of the understanding, the principle of causality has

reference only to things in the first sense. We then see how it does

not involve any contradiction to assert, on the one hand, that the

will, in the phenomenal sphere- in visible action- is necessarily

obedient to the law of nature, and, in so far, not free; and, on the

other hand, that, as belonging to a thing in itself, it is not subject

to that law, and, accordingly, is free. Now, it is true that I cannot,

by means of speculative reason, and still less by empirical

observation, cognize my soul as a thing in itself and consequently,

cannot cognize liberty as the property of a being to which I ascribe

effects in the world of sense. For, to do so, I must cognize this

being as existing, and yet not in time, which- since I cannot

support my conception by any intuition- is impossible. At the same

time, while I cannot cognize, I can quite well think freedom, that

is to say, my representation of it involves at least no contradiction,

if we bear in mind the critical distinction of the two modes of

representation (the sensible and the intellectual) and the

consequent limitation of the conceptions of the pure understanding and

of the principles which flow from them. Suppose now that morality

necessarily presupposed liberty, in the strictest sense, as a property

of our will; suppose that reason contained certain practical, original

principles a priori, which were absolutely impossible without this

presupposition; and suppose, at the same time, that speculative reason

had proved that liberty was incapable of being thought at all. It

would then follow that the moral presupposition must give way to the

speculative affirmation, the opposite of which involves an obvious

contradiction, and that liberty and, with it, morality must yield to

the mechanism of nature; for the negation of morality involves no

contradiction, except on the presupposition of liberty. Now morality

does not require the speculative cognition of liberty; it is enough

that I can think it, that its conception involves no contradiction,

that it does not interfere with the mechanism of nature. But even this

requirement we could not satisfy, if we had not learnt the twofold

sense in which things may be taken; and it is only in this way that

the doctrine of morality and the doctrine of nature are confined

within their proper limits. For this result, then, we are indebted

to a criticism which warns us of our unavoidable ignorance with regard

to things in themselves, and establishes the necessary limitation of

our theoretical cognition to mere phenomena.



  *In order to cognize an object, I must be able to prove its

possibility, either from its reality as attested by experience, or a

priori, by means of reason. But I can think what I please, provided

only I do not contradict myself; that is, provided my conception is

a possible thought, though I may be unable to answer for the existence

of a corresponding object in the sum of possibilities. But something

more is required before I can attribute to such a conception objective

validity, that is real possibility- the other possibility being merely

logical. We are not, however, confined to theoretical sources of

cognition for the means of satisfying this additional requirement, but

may derive them from practical sources.



  The positive value of the critical principles of pure reason in

relation to the conception of God and of the simple nature of the

soul, admits of a similar exemplification; but on this point I shall

not dwell. I cannot even make the assumption- as the practical

interests of morality require- of God, freedom, and immortality, if

I do not deprive speculative reason of its pretensions to transcendent

insight. For to arrive at these, it must make use of principles which,

in fact, extend only to the objects of possible experience, and

which cannot be applied to objects beyond this sphere without

converting them into phenomena, and thus rendering the practical

extension of pure reason impossible. I must, therefore, abolish

knowledge, to make room for belief. The dogmatism of metaphysics, that

is, the presumption that it is possible to advance in metaphysics

without previous criticism, is the true source of the unbelief (always

dogmatic) which militates against morality.

  Thus, while it may be no very difficult task to bequeath a legacy to

posterity, in the shape of a system of metaphysics constructed in

accordance with the Critique of Pure Reason, still the value of such a

bequest is not to be depreciated. It will render an important

service to reason, by substituting the certainty of scientific

method for that random groping after results without the guidance of

principles, which has hitherto characterized the pursuit of

metaphysical studies. It will render an important service to the

inquiring mind of youth, by leading the student to apply his powers to

the cultivation of. genuine science, instead of wasting them, as at

present, on speculations which can never lead to any result, or on the

idle attempt to invent new ideas and opinions. But, above all, it will

confer an inestimable benefit on morality and religion, by showing

that all the objections urged against them may be silenced for ever by

the Socratic method, that is to say, by proving the ignorance of the

objector. For, as the world has never been, and, no doubt, never

will be without a system of metaphysics of one kind or another, it

is the highest and weightiest concern of philosophy to render it

powerless for harm, by closing up the sources of error.

  This important change in the field of the sciences, this loss of its

fancied possessions, to which speculative reason must submit, does not

prove in any way detrimental to the general interests of humanity. The

advantages which the world has derived from the teachings of pure

reason are not at all impaired. The loss falls, in its whole extent,

on the monopoly of the schools, but does not in the slightest degree

touch the interests of mankind. I appeal to the most obstinate

dogmatist, whether the proof of the continued existence of the soul

after death, derived from the simplicity of its substance; of the

freedom of the will in opposition to the general mechanism of

nature, drawn from the subtle but impotent distinction of subjective

and objective practical necessity; or of the existence of God, deduced

from the conception of an ens realissimum- the contingency of the

changeable, and the necessity of a prime mover, has ever been able

to pass beyond the limits of the schools, to penetrate the public

mind, or to exercise the slightest influence on its convictions. It

must be admitted that this has not been the case and that, owing to

the unfitness of the common understanding for such subtle

speculations, it can never be expected to take place. On the contrary,

it is plain that the hope of a future life arises from the feeling,

which exists in the breast of every man, that the temporal is

inadequate to meet and satisfy the demands of his nature. In like

manner, it cannot be doubted that the clear exhibition of duties in

opposition to all the claims of inclination, gives rise to the

consciousness of freedom, and that the glorious order, beauty, and

providential care, everywhere displayed in nature, give rise to the

belief in a wise and great Author of the Universe. Such is the genesis

of these general convictions of mankind, so far as they depend on

rational grounds; and this public property not only remains

undisturbed, but is even raised to greater importance, by the doctrine

that the schools have no right to arrogate to themselves a more

profound insight into a matter of general human concernment than

that to which the great mass of men, ever held by us in the highest

estimation, can without difficulty attain, and that the schools

should, therefore, confine themselves to the elaboration of these

universally comprehensible and, from a moral point of view, amply

satisfactory proofs. The change, therefore, affects only the

arrogant pretensions of the schools, which would gladly retain, in

their own exclusive possession, the key to the truths which they

impart to the public.



          Quod mecum nescit, solus vult scire videri.



At the same time it does not deprive the speculative philosopher of

his just title to be the sole depositor of a science which benefits

the public without its knowledge- I mean, the Critique of Pure Reason.

This can never become popular and, indeed, has no occasion to be so;

for finespun arguments in favour of useful truths make just as

little impression on the public mind as the equally subtle

objections brought against these truths. On the other hand, since both

inevitably force themselves on every man who rises to the height of

speculation, it becomes the manifest duty of the schools to enter upon

a thorough investigation of the rights of speculative reason and,

thus, to prevent the scandal which metaphysical controversies are

sure, sooner or later, to cause even to the masses. It is only by

criticism that metaphysicians (and, as such, theologians too) can be

saved from these controversies and from the consequent perversion of

their doctrines. Criticism alone can strike a blow at the root of

materialism, fatalism, atheism, free-thinking, fanaticism, and

superstition, which are universally injurious- as well as of

idealism and scepticism, which are dangerous to the schools, but can

scarcely pass over to the public. If governments think proper to

interfere with the affairs of the learned, it would be more consistent

with a wise regard for the interests of science, as well as for

those of society, to favour a criticism of this kind, by which alone

the labours of reason can be established on a firm basis, than to

support the ridiculous despotism of the schools, which raise a loud

cry of danger to the public over the destruction of cobwebs, of

which the public has never taken any notice, and the loss of which,

therefore, it can never feel.

  This critical science is not opposed to the dogmatic procedure of

reason in pure cognition; for pure cognition must always be

dogmatic, that is, must rest on strict demonstration from sure

principles a priori- but to dogmatism, that is, to the presumption

that it is possible to make any progress with a pure cognition,

derived from (philosophical) conceptions, according to the

principles which reason has long been in the habit of employing-

without first inquiring in what way and by what right reason has

come into the possession of these principles. Dogmatism is thus the

dogmatic procedure of pure reason without previous criticism of its

own powers, and in opposing this procedure, we must not be supposed to

lend any countenance to that loquacious shallowness which arrogates to

itself the name of popularity, nor yet to scepticism, which makes

short work with the whole science of metaphysics. On the contrary, our

criticism is the necessary preparation for a thoroughly scientific

system of metaphysics which must perform its task entirely a priori,

to the complete satisfaction of speculative reason, and must,

therefore, be treated, not popularly, but scholastically. In

carrying out the plan which the Critique prescribes, that is, in the

future system of metaphysics, we must have recourse to the strict

method of the celebrated Wolf, the greatest of all dogmatic

philosophers. He was the first to point out the necessity of

establishing fixed principles, of clearly defining our conceptions,

and of subjecting our demonstrations to the most severe scrutiny,

instead of rashly jumping at conclusions. The example which he set

served to awaken that spirit of profound and thorough investigation

which is not yet extinct in Germany. He would have been peculiarly

well fitted to give a truly scientific character to metaphysical

studies, had it occurred to him to prepare the field by a criticism of

the organum, that is, of pure reason itself. That be failed to

perceive the necessity of such a procedure must be ascribed to the

dogmatic mode of thought which characterized his age, and on this

point the philosophers of his time, as well as of all previous

times, have nothing to reproach each other with. Those who reject at

once the method of Wolf, and of the Critique of Pure Reason, can

have no other aim but to shake off the fetters of science, to change

labour into sport, certainty into opinion, and philosophy into

philodoxy.

  In this second edition, I have endeavoured, as far as possible, to

remove the difficulties and obscurity which, without fault of mine

perhaps, have given rise to many misconceptions even among acute

thinkers. In the propositions themselves, and in the demonstrations by

which they are supported, as well as in the form and the entire plan

of the work, I have found nothing to alter; which must be attributed

partly to the long examination to which I had subjected the whole

before offering it to the public and partly to the nature of the case.

For pure speculative reason is an organic structure in which there

is nothing isolated or independent, but every Single part is essential

to all the rest; and hence, the slightest imperfection, whether defect

or positive error, could not fail to betray itself in use. I

venture, further, to hope, that this system will maintain the same

unalterable character for the future. I am led to entertain this

confidence, not by vanity, but by the evidence which the equality of

the result affords, when we proceed, first, from the simplest elements

up to the complete whole of pure reason and, and then, backwards

from the whole to each part. We find that the attempt to make the

slightest alteration, in any part, leads inevitably to contradictions,

not merely in this system, but in human reason itself. At the same

time, there is still much room for improvement in the exposition of

the doctrines contained in this work. In the present edition, I have

endeavoured to remove misapprehensions of the aesthetical part,

especially with regard to the conception of time; to clear away the

obscurity which has been found in the deduction of the conceptions

of the understanding; to supply the supposed want of sufficient

evidence in the demonstration of the principles of the pure

understanding; and, lastly, to obviate the misunderstanding of the

paralogisms which immediately precede the rational psychology.

Beyond this point- the end of the second main division of the

"Transcendental Dialectic"- I have not extended my alterations,*

partly from want of time, and partly because I am not aware that any

portion of the remainder has given rise to misconceptions among

intelligent and impartial critics, whom I do not here mention with

that praise which is their due, but who will find that their

suggestions have been attended to in the work itself.



  *The only addition, properly so called- and that only in the

method of proof- which I have made in the present edition, consists of

a new refutation of psychological idealism, and a strict

demonstration- the only one possible, as I believe- of the objective

reality of external intuition. However harmless idealism may be

considered- although in reality it is not so- in regard to the

essential ends of metaphysics, it must still remain a scandal to

philosophy and to the general human reason to be obliged to assume, as

an article of mere belief, the existence of things external to

ourselves (from which, yet, we derive the whole material of

cognition for the internal sense), and not to be able to oppose a

satisfactory proof to any one who may call it in question. As there is

some obscurity of expression in the demonstration as it stands in

the text, I propose to alter the passage in question as follows:

"But this permanent cannot be an intuition in me. For all the

determining grounds of my existence which can be found in me are

representations and, as such, do themselves require a permanent,

distinct from them, which may determine my existence in relation to

their changes, that is, my existence in time, wherein they change." It

may, probably, be urged in opposition to this proof that, after all, I

am only conscious immediately of that which is in me, that is, of my

representation of external things, and that, consequently, it must

always remain uncertain whether anything corresponding to this

representation does or does not exist externally to me. But I am

conscious, through internal experience, of my existence in time

(consequently, also, of the determinability of the former in the

latter), and that is more than the simple consciousness of my

representation. It is, in fact, the same as the empirical

consciousness of my existence, which can only be determined in

relation to something, which, while connected with my existence, is

external to me. This consciousness of my existence in time is,

therefore, identical with the consciousness of a relation to something

external to me, and it is, therefore, experience, not fiction,

sense, not imagination, which inseparably connects the external with

my internal sense. For the external sense is, in itself, the

relation of intuition to something real, external to me; and the

reality of this something, as opposed to the mere imagination of it,

rests solely on its inseparable connection with internal experience as

the condition of its possibility. If with the intellectual

consciousness of my existence, in the representation: I am, which

accompanies all my judgements, and all the operations of my

understanding, I could, at the same time, connect a determination of

my existence by intellectual intuition, then the consciousness of a

relation to something external to me would not be necessary. But the

internal intuition in which alone my existence can be determined,

though preceded by that purely intellectual consciousness, is itself

sensible and attached to the condition of time. Hence this

determination of my existence, and consequently my internal experience

itself, must depend on something permanent which is not in me, which

can be, therefore, only in something external to me, to which I must

look upon myself as being related. Thus the reality of the external

sense is necessarily connected with that of the internal, in order

to the possibility of experience in general; that is, I am just as

certainly conscious that there are things external to me related to my

sense as I am that I myself exist as determined in time. But in

order to ascertain to what given intuitions objects, external me,

really correspond, in other words, what intuitions belong to the

external sense and not to imagination, I must have recourse, in

every particular case, to those rules according to which experience in

general (even internal experience) is distinguished from

imagination, and which are always based on the proposition that

there really is an external experience. We may add the remark that the

representation of something permanent in existence, is not the same

thing as the permanent representation; for a representation may be

very variable and changing- as all our representations, even that of

matter, are- and yet refer to something permanent, which must,

therefore, be distinct from all my representations and external to me,

the existence of which is necessarily included in the determination of

my own existence, and with it constitutes one experience- an

experience which would not even be possible internally, if it were not

also at the same time, in part, external. To the question How? we

are no more able to reply, than we are, in general, to think the

stationary in time, the coexistence of which with the variable,

produces the conception of change.



  In attempting to render the exposition of my views as intelligible

as possible, I have been compelled to leave out or abridge various

passages which were not essential to the completeness of the work, but

which many readers might consider useful in other respects, and

might be unwilling to miss. This trifling loss, which could not be

avoided without swelling the book beyond due limits, may be

supplied, at the pleasure of the reader, by a comparison with the

first edition, and will, I hope, be more than compensated for by the

greater clearness of the exposition as it now stands.

  I have observed, with pleasure and thankfulness, in the pages of

various reviews and treatises, that the spirit of profound and

thorough investigation is not extinct in Germany, though it may have

been overborne and silenced for a time by the fashionable tone of a

licence in thinking, which gives itself the airs of genius, and that

the difficulties which beset the paths of criticism have not prevented

energetic and acute thinkers from making themselves masters of the

science of pure reason to which these paths conduct- a science which

is not popular, but scholastic in its character, and which alone can

hope for a lasting existence or possess an abiding value. To these

deserving men, who so happily combine profundity of view with a talent

for lucid exposition- a talent which I myself am not conscious of

possessing- I leave the task of removing any obscurity which may still

adhere to the statement of my doctrines. For, in this case, the danger

is not that of being refuted, but of being misunderstood. For my own

part, I must henceforward abstain from controversy, although I shall

carefully attend to all suggestions, whether from friends or

adversaries, which may be of use in the future elaboration of the

system of this propaedeutic. As, during these labours, I have advanced

pretty far in years this month I reach my sixty-fourth year- it will

be necessary for me to economize time, if I am to carry out my plan of

elaborating the metaphysics of nature as well as of morals, in

confirmation of the correctness of the principles established in

this Critique of Pure Reason, both speculative and practical; and I

must, therefore, leave the task of clearing up the obscurities of

the present work- inevitable, perhaps, at the outset- as well as,

the defence of the whole, to those deserving men, who have made my

system their own. A philosophical system cannot come forward armed

at all points like a mathematical treatise, and hence it may be

quite possible to take objection to particular passages, while the

organic structure of the system, considered as a unity, has no

danger to apprehend. But few possess the ability, and still fewer

the inclination, to take a comprehensive view of a new system. By

confining the view to particular passages, taking these out of their

connection and comparing them with one another, it is easy to pick out

apparent contradictions, especially in a work written with any freedom

of style. These contradictions place the work in an unfavourable light

in the eyes of those who rely on the judgement of others, but are

easily reconciled by those who have mastered the idea of the whole. If

a theory possesses stability in itself, the action and reaction

which seemed at first to threaten its existence serve only, in the

course of time, to smooth down any superficial roughness or

inequality, and- if men of insight, impartiality, and truly popular

gifts, turn their attention to it- to secure to it, in a short time,

the requisite elegance also.



  Konigsberg, April 1787.

INTRODUCTION

                     INTRODUCTION.



  I. Of the difference between Pure and Empirical Knowledge



  That all our knowledge begins with experience there can be no doubt.

For how is it possible that the faculty of cognition should be

awakened into exercise otherwise than by means of objects which affect

our senses, and partly of themselves produce representations, partly

rouse our powers of understanding into activity, to compare to

connect, or to separate these, and so to convert the raw material of

our sensuous impressions into a knowledge of objects, which is

called experience? In respect of time, therefore, no knowledge of ours

is antecedent to experience, but begins with it.

  But, though all our knowledge begins with experience, it by no means

follows that all arises out of experience. For, on the contrary, it is

quite possible that our empirical knowledge is a compound of that

which we receive through impressions, and that which the faculty of

cognition supplies from itself (sensuous impressions giving merely the

occasion), an addition which we cannot distinguish from the original

element given by sense, till long practice has made us attentive to,

and skilful in separating it. It is, therefore, a question which

requires close investigation, and not to be answered at first sight,

whether there exists a knowledge altogether independent of experience,

and even of all sensuous impressions? Knowledge of this kind is called

a priori, in contradistinction to empirical knowledge, which has its

sources a posteriori, that is, in experience.

  But the expression, "a priori," is not as yet definite enough

adequately to indicate the whole meaning of the question above

started. For, in speaking of knowledge which has its sources in

experience, we are wont to say, that this or that may be known a

priori, because we do not derive this knowledge immediately from

experience, but from a general rule, which, however, we have itself

borrowed from experience. Thus, if a man undermined his house, we say,

"he might know a priori that it would have fallen;" that is, he needed

not to have waited for the experience that it did actually fall. But

still, a priori, he could not know even this much. For, that bodies

are heavy, and, consequently, that they fall when their supports are

taken away, must have been known to him previously, by means of

experience.

  By the term "knowledge a priori," therefore, we shall in the

sequel understand, not such as is independent of this or that kind

of experience, but such as is absolutely so of all experience. Opposed

to this is empirical knowledge, or that which is possible only a

posteriori, that is, through experience. Knowledge a priori is

either pure or impure. Pure knowledge a priori is that with which no

empirical element is mixed up. For example, the proposition, "Every

change has a cause," is a proposition a priori, but impure, because

change is a conception which can only be derived from experience.



  II. The Human Intellect, even in an Unphilosophical State,

      is in Possession of Certain Cognitions "a priori".



  The question now is as to a criterion, by which we may securely

distinguish a pure from an empirical cognition. Experience no doubt

teaches us that this or that object is constituted in such and such

a manner, but not that it could not possibly exist otherwise. Now,

in the first place, if we have a proposition which contains the idea

of necessity in its very conception, it is a if, moreover, it is not

derived from any other proposition, unless from one equally

involving the idea of necessity, it is absolutely priori. Secondly, an

empirical judgement never exhibits strict and absolute, but only

assumed and comparative universality (by induction); therefore, the

most we can say is- so far as we have hitherto observed, there is no

exception to this or that rule. If, on the other hand, a judgement

carries with it strict and absolute universality, that is, admits of

no possible exception, it is not derived from experience, but is valid

absolutely a priori.

  Empirical universality is, therefore, only an arbitrary extension of

validity, from that which may be predicated of a proposition valid

in most cases, to that which is asserted of a proposition which

holds good in all; as, for example, in the affirmation, "All bodies

are heavy." When, on the contrary, strict universality characterizes a

judgement, it necessarily indicates another peculiar source of

knowledge, namely, a faculty of cognition a priori. Necessity and

strict universality, therefore, are infallible tests for

distinguishing pure from empirical knowledge, and are inseparably

connected with each other. But as in the use of these criteria the

empirical limitation is sometimes more easily detected than the

contingency of the judgement, or the unlimited universality which we

attach to a judgement is often a more convincing proof than its

necessity, it may be advisable to use the criteria separately, each

being by itself infallible.

  Now, that in the sphere of human cognition we have judgements

which are necessary, and in the strictest sense universal,

consequently pure a priori, it will be an easy matter to show. If we

desire an example from the sciences, we need only take any proposition

in mathematics. If we cast our eyes upon the commonest operations of

the understanding, the proposition, "Every change must have a

cause," will amply serve our purpose. In the latter case, indeed,

the conception of a cause so plainly involves the conception of a

necessity of connection with an effect, and of a strict universality

of the law, that the very notion of a cause would entirely

disappear, were we to derive it, like Hume, from a frequent

association of what happens with that which precedes; and the habit

thence originating of connecting representations- the necessity

inherent in the judgement being therefore merely subjective.

Besides, without seeking for such examples of principles existing a

priori in cognition, we might easily show that such principles are the

indispensable basis of the possibility of experience itself, and

consequently prove their existence a priori. For whence could our

experience itself acquire certainty, if all the rules on which it

depends were themselves empirical, and consequently fortuitous? No

one, therefore, can admit the validity of the use of such rules as

first principles. But, for the present, we may content ourselves

with having established the fact, that we do possess and exercise a

faculty of pure a priori cognition; and, secondly, with having pointed

out the proper tests of such cognition, namely, universality and

necessity.

  Not only in judgements, however, but even in conceptions, is an a

priori origin manifest. For example, if we take away by degrees from

our conceptions of a body all that can be referred to mere sensuous

experience- colour, hardness or softness, weight, even

impenetrability- the body will then vanish; but the space which it

occupied still remains, and this it is utterly impossible to

annihilate in thought. Again, if we take away, in like manner, from

our empirical conception of any object, corporeal or incorporeal,

all properties which mere experience has taught us to connect with it,

still we cannot think away those through which we cogitate it as

substance, or adhering to substance, although our conception of

substance is more determined than that of an object. Compelled,

therefore, by that necessity with which the conception of substance

forces itself upon us, we must confess that it has its seat in our

faculty of cognition a priori.



  III. Philosophy stands in need of a Science which shall

       Determine the Possibility, Principles, and Extent of

       Human Knowledge "a priori"



  Of far more importance than all that has been above said, is the

consideration that certain of our cognitions rise completely above the

sphere of all possible experience, and by means of conceptions, to

which there exists in the whole extent of experience no

corresponding object, seem to extend the range of our judgements

beyond its bounds. And just in this transcendental or supersensible

sphere, where experience affords us neither instruction nor

guidance, lie the investigations of reason, which, on account of their

importance, we consider far preferable to, and as having a far more

elevated aim than, all that the understanding can achieve within the

sphere of sensuous phenomena. So high a value do we set upon these

investigations, that even at the risk of error, we persist in

following them out, and permit neither doubt nor disregard nor

indifference to restrain us from the pursuit. These unavoidable

problems of mere pure reason are God, freedom (of will), and

immortality. The science which, with all its preliminaries, has for

its especial object the solution of these problems is named

metaphysics- a science which is at the very outset dogmatical, that

is, it confidently takes upon itself the execution of this task

without any previous investigation of the ability or inability of

reason for such an undertaking.

  Now the safe ground of experience being thus abandoned, it seems

nevertheless natural that we should hesitate to erect a building

with the cognitions we possess, without knowing whence they come,

and on the strength of principles, the origin of which is

undiscovered. Instead of thus trying to build without a foundation, it

is rather to be expected that we should long ago have put the

question, how the understanding can arrive at these a priori

cognitions, and what is the extent, validity, and worth which they may

possess? We say, "This is natural enough," meaning by the word

natural, that which is consistent with a just and reasonable way of

thinking; but if we understand by the term, that. which usually

happens, nothing indeed could be more natural and more

comprehensible than that this investigation should be left long

unattempted. For one part of our pure knowledge, the science of

mathematics, has been long firmly established, and thus leads us to

form flattering expectations with regard to others, though these may

be of quite a different nature. Besides, when we get beyond the bounds

of experience, we are of course safe from opposition in that

quarter; and the charm of widening the range of our knowledge is so

great that, unless we are brought to a standstill by some evident

contradiction, we hurry on undoubtingly in our course. This,

however, may be avoided, if we are sufficiently cautious in the

construction of our fictions, which are not the less fictions on

that account.

  Mathematical science affords us a brilliant example, how far,

independently of all experience, we may carry our a priori

knowledge. It is true that the mathematician occupies himself with

objects and cognitions only in so far as they can be represented by

means of intuition. But this circumstance is easily overlooked,

because the said intuition can itself be given a priori, and therefore

is hardly to be distinguished from a mere pure conception. Deceived by

such a proof of the power of reason, we can perceive no limits to

the extension of our knowledge. The light dove cleaving in free flight

the thin air, whose resistance it feels, might imagine that her

movements would be far more free and rapid in airless space. just in

the same way did Plato, abandoning the world of sense because of the

narrow limits it sets to the understanding, venture upon the wings

of ideas beyond it, into the void space of pure intellect. He did

not reflect that he made no real progress by all his efforts; for he

met with no resistance which might serve him for a support, as it

were, whereon to rest, and on which he might apply his powers, in

order to let the intellect acquire momentum for its progress. It is,

indeed, the common fate of human reason in speculation, to finish

the imposing edifice of thought as rapidly as possible, and then for

the first time to begin to examine whether the foundation is a solid

one or no. Arrived at this point, all sorts of excuses are sought

after, in order to console us for its want of stability, or rather,

indeed, to enable Us to dispense altogether with so late and dangerous

an investigation. But what frees us during the process of building

from all apprehension or suspicion, and flatters us into the belief of

its solidity, is this. A great part, perhaps the greatest part, of the

business of our reason consists in the analysation of the

conceptions which we already possess of objects. By this means we gain

a multitude of cognitions, which although really nothing more than

elucidations or explanations of that which (though in a confused

manner) was already thought in our conceptions, are, at least in

respect of their form, prized as new introspections; whilst, so far as

regards their matter or content, we have really made no addition to

our conceptions, but only disinvolved them. But as this process does

furnish a real priori knowledge, which has a sure progress and

useful results, reason, deceived by this, slips in, without being

itself aware of it, assertions of a quite different kind; in which, to

given conceptions it adds others, a priori indeed, but entirely

foreign to them, without our knowing how it arrives at these, and,

indeed, without such a question ever suggesting itself. I shall

therefore at once proceed to examine the difference between these

two modes of knowledge.



  IV. Of the Difference Between Analytical and Synthetical Judgements.



  In all judgements wherein the relation of a subject to the predicate

is cogitated (I mention affirmative judgements only here; the

application to negative will be very easy), this relation is

possible in two different ways. Either the predicate B belongs to

the subject A, as somewhat which is contained (though covertly) in the

conception A; or the predicate B lies completely out of the conception

A, although it stands in connection with it. In the first instance,

I term the judgement analytical, in the second, synthetical.

Analytical judgements (affirmative) are therefore those in which the

connection of the predicate with the subject is cogitated through

identity; those in which this connection is cogitated without

identity, are called synthetical judgements. The former may be

called explicative, the latter augmentative judgements; because the

former add in the predicate nothing to the conception of the

subject, but only analyse it into its constituent conceptions, which

were thought already in the subject, although in a confused manner;

the latter add to our conceptions of the subject a predicate which was

not contained in it, and which no analysis could ever have

discovered therein. For example, when I say, "All bodies are

extended," this is an analytical judgement. For I need not go beyond

the conception of body in order to find extension connected with it,

but merely analyse the conception, that is, become conscious of the

manifold properties which I think in that conception, in order to

discover this predicate in it: it is therefore an analytical

judgement. On the other hand, when I say, "All bodies are heavy,"

the predicate is something totally different from that which I think

in the mere conception of a body. By the addition of such a predicate,

therefore, it becomes a synthetical judgement.

  Judgements of experience, as such, are always synthetical. For it

would be absurd to think of grounding an analytical judgement on

experience, because in forming such a judgement I need not go out of

the sphere of my conceptions, and therefore recourse to the

testimony of experience is quite unnecessary. That "bodies are

extended" is not an empirical judgement, but a proposition which

stands firm a priori. For before addressing myself to experience, I

already have in my conception all the requisite conditions for the

judgement, and I have only to extract the predicate from the

conception, according to the principle of contradiction, and thereby

at the same time become conscious of the necessity of the judgement, a

necessity which I could never learn from experience. On the other

hand, though at first I do not at all include the predicate of

weight in my conception of body in general, that conception still

indicates an object of experience, a part of the totality of

experience, to which I can still add other parts; and this I do when I

recognize by observation that bodies are heavy. I can cognize

beforehand by analysis the conception of body through the

characteristics of extension, impenetrability, shape, etc., all

which are cogitated in this conception. But now I extend my knowledge,

and looking back on experience from which I had derived this

conception of body, I find weight at all times connected with the

above characteristics, and therefore I synthetically add to my

conceptions this as a predicate, and say, "All bodies are heavy." Thus

it is experience upon which rests the possibility of the synthesis

of the predicate of weight with the conception of body, because both

conceptions, although the one is not contained in the other, still

belong to one another (only contingently, however), as parts of a

whole, namely, of experience, which is itself a synthesis of

intuitions.

  But to synthetical judgements a priori, such aid is entirely

wanting. If I go out of and beyond the conception A, in order to

recognize another B as connected with it, what foundation have I to

rest on, whereby to render the synthesis possible? I have here no

longer the advantage of looking out in the sphere of experience for

what I want. Let us take, for example, the proposition, "Everything

that happens has a cause." In the conception of "something that

happens," I indeed think an existence which a certain time

antecedes, and from this I can derive analytical judgements. But the

conception of a cause lies quite out of the above conception, and

indicates something entirely different from "that which happens,"

and is consequently not contained in that conception. How then am I

able to assert concerning the general conception- "that which

happens"- something entirely different from that conception, and to

recognize the conception of cause although not contained in it, yet as

belonging to it, and even necessarily? what is here the unknown = X,

upon which the understanding rests when it believes it has found,

out of the conception A a foreign predicate B, which it nevertheless

considers to be connected with it? It cannot be experience, because

the principle adduced annexes the two representations, cause and

effect, to the representation existence, not only with universality,

which experience cannot give, but also with the expression of

necessity, therefore completely a priori and from pure conceptions.

Upon such synthetical, that is augmentative propositions, depends

the whole aim of our speculative knowledge a priori; for although

analytical judgements are indeed highly important and necessary,

they are so, only to arrive at that clearness of conceptions which

is requisite for a sure and extended synthesis, and this alone is a

real acquisition.



  V. In all Theoretical Sciences of Reason, Synthetical Judgements

     "a priori" are contained as Principles.



  1. Mathematical judgements are always synthetical. Hitherto this

fact, though incontestably true and very important in its

consequences, seems to have escaped the analysts of the human mind,

nay, to be in complete opposition to all their conjectures. For as

it was found that mathematical conclusions all proceed according to

the principle of contradiction (which the nature of every apodeictic

certainty requires), people became persuaded that the fundamental

principles of the science also were recognized and admitted in the

same way. But the notion is fallacious; for although a synthetical

proposition can certainly be discerned by means of the principle of

contradiction, this is possible only when another synthetical

proposition precedes, from which the latter is deduced, but never of

itself which

  Before all, be it observed, that proper mathematical propositions

are always judgements a priori, and not empirical, because they

carry along with them the conception of necessity, which cannot be

given by experience. If this be demurred to, it matters not; I will

then limit my assertion to pure mathematics, the very conception of

which implies that it consists of knowledge altogether non-empirical

and a priori.

  We might, indeed at first suppose that the proposition 7 + 5 = 12 is

a merely analytical proposition, following (according to the principle

of contradiction) from the conception of a sum of seven and five.

But if we regard it more narrowly, we find that our conception of

the sum of seven and five contains nothing more than the uniting of

both sums into one, whereby it cannot at all be cogitated what this

single number is which embraces both. The conception of twelve is by

no means obtained by merely cogitating the union of seven and five;

and we may analyse our conception of such a possible sum as long as we

will, still we shall never discover in it the notion of twelve. We

must go beyond these conceptions, and have recourse to an intuition

which corresponds to one of the two- our five fingers, for example, or

like Segner in his Arithmetic five points, and so by degrees, add

the units contained in the five given in the intuition, to the

conception of seven. For I first take the number 7, and, for the

conception of 5 calling in the aid of the fingers of my hand as

objects of intuition, I add the units, which I before took together to

make up the number 5, gradually now by means of the material image

my hand, to the number 7, and by this process, I at length see the

number 12 arise. That 7 should be added to 5, I have certainly

cogitated in my conception of a sum = 7 + 5, but not that this sum was

equal to 12. Arithmetical propositions are therefore always

synthetical, of which we may become more clearly convinced by trying

large numbers. For it will thus become quite evident that, turn and

twist our conceptions as we may, it is impossible, without having

recourse to intuition, to arrive at the sum total or product by

means of the mere analysis of our conceptions. just as little is any

principle of pure geometry analytical. "A straight line between two

points is the shortest," is a synthetical proposition. For my

conception of straight contains no notion of quantity, but is merely

qualitative. The conception of the shortest is therefore fore wholly

an addition, and by no analysis can it be extracted from our

conception of a straight line. Intuition must therefore here lend

its aid, by means of which, and thus only, our synthesis is possible.

  Some few principles preposited by geometricians are, indeed,

really analytical, and depend on the principle of contradiction.

They serve, however, like identical propositions, as links in the

chain of method, not as principles- for example, a = a, the whole is

equal to itself, or (a+b) > a, the whole is greater than its part. And

yet even these principles themselves, though they derive their

validity from pure conceptions, are only admitted in mathematics

because they can be presented in intuition. What causes us here

commonly to believe that the predicate of such apodeictic judgements

is already contained in our conception, and that the judgement is

therefore analytical, is merely the equivocal nature of the

expression. We must join in thought a certain predicate to a given

conception, and this necessity cleaves already to the conception.

But the question is, not what we must join in thought to the given

conception, but what we really think therein, though only obscurely,

and then it becomes manifest that the predicate pertains to these

conceptions, necessarily indeed, yet not as thought in the

conception itself, but by virtue of an intuition, which must be

added to the conception.

  2. The science of natural philosophy (physics) contains in itself

synthetical judgements a priori, as principles. I shall adduce two

propositions. For instance, the proposition, "In all changes of the

material world, the quantity of matter remains unchanged"; or, that,

"In all communication of motion, action and reaction must always be

equal." In both of these, not only is the necessity, and therefore

their origin a priori clear, but also that they are synthetical

propositions. For in the conception of matter, I do not cogitate its

permanency, but merely its presence in space, which it fills. I

therefore really go out of and beyond the conception of matter, in

order to think on to it something a priori, which I did not think in

it. The proposition is therefore not analytical, but synthetical,

and nevertheless conceived a priori; and so it is with regard to the

other propositions of the pure part of natural philosophy.

  3. As to metaphysics, even if we look upon it merely as an attempted

science, yet, from the nature of human reason, an indispensable one,

we find that it must contain synthetical propositions a priori. It

is not merely the duty of metaphysics to dissect, and thereby

analytically to illustrate the conceptions which we form a priori of

things; but we seek to widen the range of our a priori knowledge.

For this purpose, we must avail ourselves of such principles as add

something to the original conception- something not identical with,

nor contained in it, and by means of synthetical judgements a

priori, leave far behind us the limits of experience; for example,

in the proposition, "the world must have a beginning," and such

like. Thus metaphysics, according to the proper aim of the science,

consists merely of synthetical propositions a priori.



  VI. The Universal Problem of Pure Reason.



  It is extremely advantageous to be able to bring a number of

investigations under the formula of a single problem. For in this

manner, we not only facilitate our own labour, inasmuch as we define

it clearly to ourselves, but also render it more easy for others to

decide whether we have done justice to our undertaking. The proper

problem of pure reason, then, is contained in the question: "How are

synthetical judgements a priori possible?"

  That metaphysical science has hitherto remained in so vacillating

a state of uncertainty and contradiction, is only to be attributed

to the fact that this great problem, and perhaps even the difference

between analytical and synthetical judgements, did not sooner

suggest itself to philosophers. Upon the solution of this problem,

or upon sufficient proof of the impossibility of synthetical knowledge

a priori, depends the existence or downfall of the science of

metaphysics. Among philosophers, David Hume came the nearest of all to

this problem; yet it never acquired in his mind sufficient

precision, nor did he regard the question in its universality. On

the contrary, he stopped short at the synthetical proposition of the

connection of an effect with its cause (principium causalitatis),

insisting that such proposition a priori was impossible. According

to his conclusions, then, all that we term metaphysical science is a

mere delusion, arising from the fancied insight of reason into that

which is in truth borrowed from experience, and to which habit has

given the appearance of necessity. Against this assertion, destructive

to all pure philosophy, he would have been guarded, had he had our

problem before his eyes in its universality. For he would then have

perceived that, according to his own argument, there likewise could

not be any pure mathematical science, which assuredly cannot exist

without synthetical propositions a priori- an absurdity from which his

good understanding must have saved him.

  In the solution of the above problem is at the same time

comprehended the possibility of the use of pure reason in the

foundation and construction of all sciences which contain

theoretical knowledge a priori of objects, that is to say, the

answer to the following questions:

  How is pure mathematical science possible?

  How is pure natural science possible?

  Respecting these sciences, as they do certainly exist, it may with

propriety be asked, how they are possible?- for that they must be

possible is shown by the fact of their really existing.* But as to

metaphysics, the miserable progress it has hitherto made, and the fact

that of no one system yet brought forward, far as regards its true

aim, can it be said that this science really exists, leaves any one at

liberty to doubt with reason the very possibility of its existence.



  *As to the existence of pure natural science, or physics, perhaps

many may still express doubts. But we have only to look at the

different propositions which are commonly treated of at the

commencement of proper (empirical) physical science- those, for

example, relating to the permanence of the same quantity of matter,

the vis inertiae, the equality of action and reaction, etc.- to be

soon convinced that they form a science of pure physics (physica pura,

or rationalis), which well deserves to be separately exposed as a

special science, in its whole extent, whether that be great or

confined.



  Yet, in a certain sense, this kind of knowledge must

unquestionably be looked upon as given; in other words, metaphysics

must be considered as really existing, if not as a science,

nevertheless as a natural disposition of the human mind (metaphysica

naturalis). For human reason, without any instigations imputable to

the mere vanity of great knowledge, unceasingly progresses, urged on

by its own feeling of need, towards such questions as cannot be

answered by any empirical application of reason, or principles derived

therefrom; and so there has ever really existed in every man some

system of metaphysics. It will always exist, so soon as reason

awakes to the exercise of its power of speculation. And now the

question arises: "How is metaphysics, as a natural disposition,

possible?" In other words, how, from the nature of universal human

reason, do those questions arise which pure reason proposes to itself,

and which it is impelled by its own feeling of need to answer as

well as it can?

  But as in all the attempts hitherto made to answer the questions

which reason is prompted by its very nature to propose to itself,

for example, whether the world had a beginning, or has existed from

eternity, it has always met with unavoidable contradictions, we must

not rest satisfied with the mere natural disposition of the mind to

metaphysics, that is, with the existence of the faculty of pure

reason, whence, indeed, some sort of metaphysical system always

arises; but it must be possible to arrive at certainty in regard to

the question whether we know or do not know the things of which

metaphysics treats. We must be able to arrive at a decision on the

subjects of its questions, or on the ability or inability of reason to

form any judgement respecting them; and therefore either to extend

with confidence the bounds of our pure reason, or to set strictly

defined and safe limits to its action. This last question, which

arises out of the above universal problem, would properly run thus:

"How is metaphysics possible as a science?"

  Thus, the critique of reason leads at last, naturally and

necessarily, to science; and, on the other hand, the dogmatical use of

reason without criticism leads to groundless assertions, against which

others equally specious can always be set, thus ending unavoidably

in scepticism.

  Besides, this science cannot be of great and formidable prolixity,

because it has not to do with objects of reason, the variety of

which is inexhaustible, but merely with Reason herself and her

problems; problems which arise out of her own bosom, and are not

proposed to her by the nature of outward things, but by her own

nature. And when once Reason has previously become able completely

to understand her own power in regard to objects which she meets

with in experience, it will be easy to determine securely the extent

and limits of her attempted application to objects beyond the confines

of experience.

  We may and must, therefore, regard the attempts hitherto made to

establish metaphysical science dogmatically as non-existent. For

what of analysis, that is, mere dissection of conceptions, is

contained in one or other, is not the aim of, but only a preparation

for metaphysics proper, which has for its object the extension, by

means of synthesis, of our a priori knowledge. And for this purpose,

mere analysis is of course useless, because it only shows what is

contained in these conceptions, but not how we arrive, a priori, at

them; and this it is her duty to show, in order to be able

afterwards to determine their valid use in regard to all objects of

experience, to all knowledge in general. But little self-denial,

indeed, is needed to give up these pretensions, seeing the undeniable,

and in the dogmatic mode of procedure, inevitable contradictions of

Reason with herself, have long since ruined the reputation of every

system of metaphysics that has appeared up to this time. It will

require more firmness to remain undeterred by difficulty from

within, and opposition from without, from endeavouring, by a method

quite opposed to all those hitherto followed, to further the growth

and fruitfulness of a science indispensable to human reason- a science

from which every branch it has borne may be cut away, but whose

roots remain indestructible.



  VII. Idea and Division of a Particular Science, under the

       Name of a Critique of Pure Reason.



  From all that has been said, there results the idea of a

particular science, which may be called the Critique of Pure Reason.

For reason is the faculty which furnishes us with the principles of

knowledge a priori. Hence, pure reason is the faculty which contains

the principles of cognizing anything absolutely a priori. An organon

of pure reason would be a compendium of those principles according

to which alone all pure cognitions a priori can be obtained. The

completely extended application of such an organon would afford us a

system of pure reason. As this, however, is demanding a great deal,

and it is yet doubtful whether any extension of our knowledge be

here possible, or, if so, in what cases; we can regard a science of

the mere criticism of pure reason, its sources and limits, as the

propaedeutic to a system of pure reason. Such a science must not be

called a doctrine, but only a critique of pure reason; and its use, in

regard to speculation, would be only negative, not to enlarge the

bounds of, but to purify, our reason, and to shield it against

error- which alone is no little gain. I apply the term

transcendental to all knowledge which is not so much occupied with

objects as with the mode of our cognition of these objects, so far

as this mode of cognition is possible a priori. A system of such

conceptions would be called transcendental philosophy. But this,

again, is still beyond the bounds of our present essay. For as such

a science must contain a complete exposition not only of our

synthetical a priori, but of our analytical a priori knowledge, it

is of too wide a range for our present purpose, because we do not

require to carry our analysis any farther than is necessary to

understand, in their full extent, the principles of synthesis a

priori, with which alone we have to do. This investigation, which we

cannot properly call a doctrine, but only a transcendental critique,

because it aims not at the enlargement, but at the correction and

guidance, of our knowledge, and is to serve as a touchstone of the

worth or worthlessness of all knowledge a priori, is the sole object

of our present essay. Such a critique is consequently, as far as

possible, a preparation for an organon; and if this new organon should

be found to fail, at least for a canon of pure reason, according to

which the complete system of the philosophy of pure reason, whether it

extend or limit the bounds of that reason, might one day be set

forth both analytically and synthetically. For that this is

possible, nay, that such a system is not of so great extent as to

preclude the hope of its ever being completed, is evident. For we have

not here to do with the nature of outward objects, which is

infinite, but solely with the mind, which judges of the nature of

objects, and, again, with the mind only in respect of its cognition

a priori. And the object of our investigations, as it is not to be

sought without, but, altogether within, ourselves, cannot remain

concealed, and in all probability is limited enough to be completely

surveyed and fairly estimated, according to its worth or

worthlessness. Still less let the reader here expect a critique of

books and systems of pure reason; our present object is exclusively

a critique of the faculty of pure reason itself. Only when we make

this critique our foundation, do we possess a pure touchstone for

estimating the philosophical value of ancient and modern writings on

this subject; and without this criterion, the incompetent historian or

judge decides upon and corrects the groundless assertions of others

with his own, which have themselves just as little foundation.

  Transcendental philosophy is the idea of a science, for which the

Critique of Pure Reason must sketch the whole plan

architectonically, that is, from principles, with a full guarantee for

the validity and stability of all the parts which enter into the

building. It is the system of all the principles of pure reason. If

this Critique itself does not assume the title of transcendental

philosophy, it is only because, to be a complete system, it ought to

contain a full analysis of all human knowledge a priori. Our

critique must, indeed, lay before us a complete enumeration of all the

radical conceptions which constitute the said pure knowledge. But from

the complete analysis of these conceptions themselves, as also from

a complete investigation of those derived from them, it abstains

with reason; partly because it would be deviating from the end in view

to occupy itself with this analysis, since this process is not

attended with the difficulty and insecurity to be found in the

synthesis, to which our critique is entirely devoted, and partly

because it would be inconsistent with the unity of our plan to

burden this essay with the vindication of the completeness of such

an analysis and deduction, with which, after all, we have at present

nothing to do. This completeness of the analysis of these radical

conceptions, as well as of the deduction from the conceptions a priori

which may be given by the analysis, we can, however, easily attain,

provided only that we are in possession of all these radical

conceptions, which are to serve as principles of the synthesis, and

that in respect of this main purpose nothing is wanting.

  To the Critique of Pure Reason, therefore, belongs all that

constitutes transcendental philosophy; and it is the complete idea

of transcendental philosophy, but still not the science itself;

because it only proceeds so far with the analysis as is necessary to

the power of judging completely of our synthetical knowledge a priori.

  The principal thing we must attend to, in the division of the

parts of a science like this, is that no conceptions must enter it

which contain aught empirical; in other words, that the knowledge a

priori must be completely pure. Hence, although the highest principles

and fundamental conceptions of morality are certainly cognitions a

priori, yet they do not belong to transcendental philosophy;

because, though they certainly do not lay the conceptions of pain,

pleasure, desires, inclinations, etc. (which are all of empirical

origin), at the foundation of its precepts, yet still into the

conception of duty- as an obstacle to be overcome, or as an incitement

which should not be made into a motive- these empirical conceptions

must necessarily enter, in the construction of a system of pure

morality. Transcendental philosophy is consequently a philosophy of

the pure and merely speculative reason. For all that is practical,

so far as it contains motives, relates to feelings, and these belong

to empirical sources of cognition.

  If we wish to divide this science from the universal point of view

of a science in general, it ought to comprehend, first, a Doctrine

of the Elements, and, secondly, a Doctrine of the Method of pure

reason. Each of these main divisions will have its subdivisions, the

separate reasons for which we cannot here particularize. Only so

much seems necessary, by way of introduction of premonition, that

there are two sources of human knowledge (which probably spring from a

common, but to us unknown root), namely, sense and understanding. By

the former, objects are given to us; by the latter, thought. So far as

the faculty of sense may contain representations a priori, which

form the conditions under which objects are given, in so far it

belongs to transcendental philosophy. The transcendental doctrine of

sense must form the first part of our science of elements, because the

conditions under which alone the objects of human knowledge are

given must precede those under which they are thought.

                               I.



              TRANSCENDENTAL DOCTRINE OF ELEMENTS.



              FIRST PART. TRANSCENDENTAL AESTHETIC.



                    SS I. Introductory.



  In whatsoever mode, or by whatsoever means, our knowledge may relate

to objects, it is at least quite clear that the only manner in which

it immediately relates to them is by means of an intuition. To this as

the indispensable groundwork, all thought points. But an intuition can

take place only in so far as the object is given to us. This, again,

is only possible, to man at least, on condition that the object affect

the mind in a certain manner. The capacity for receiving

representations (receptivity) through the mode in which we are

affected by objects, objects, is called sensibility. By means of

sensibility, therefore, objects are given to us, and it alone

furnishes us with intuitions; by the understanding they are thought,

and from it arise conceptions. But an thought must directly, or

indirectly, by means of certain signs, relate ultimately to

intuitions; consequently, with us, to sensibility, because in no other

way can an object be given to us.

  The effect of an object upon the faculty of representation, so far

as we are affected by the said object, is sensation. That sort of

intuition which relates to an object by means of sensation is called

an empirical intuition. The undetermined object of an empirical

intuition is called phenomenon. That which in the phenomenon

corresponds to the sensation, I term its matter; but that which

effects that the content of the phenomenon can be arranged under

certain relations, I call its form. But that in which our sensations

are merely arranged, and by which they are susceptible of assuming a

certain form, cannot be itself sensation. It is, then, the matter of

all phenomena that is given to us a posteriori; the form must lie

ready a priori for them in the mind, and consequently can be

regarded separately from all sensation.

  I call all representations pure, in the transcendental meaning of

the word, wherein nothing is met with that belongs to sensation. And

accordingly we find existing in the mind a priori, the pure form of

sensuous intuitions in general, in which all the manifold content of

the phenomenal world is arranged and viewed under certain relations.

This pure form of sensibility I shall call pure intuition. Thus, if

I take away from our representation of a body all that the

understanding thinks as belonging to it, as substance, force,

divisibility, etc., and also whatever belongs to sensation, as

impenetrability, hardness, colour, etc.; yet there is still

something left us from this empirical intuition, namely, extension and

shape. These belong to pure intuition, which exists a priori in the

mind, as a mere form of sensibility, and without any real object of

the senses or any sensation.

  The science of all the principles of sensibility a priori, I call

transcendental aesthetic.* There must, then, be such a science forming

the first part of the transcendental doctrine of elements, in

contradistinction to that part which contains the principles of pure

thought, and which is called transcendental logic.



  *The Germans are the only people who at present use this word to

indicate what others call the critique of taste. At the foundation

of this term lies the disappointed hope, which the eminent analyst,

Baumgarten, conceived, of subjecting the criticism of the beautiful to

principles of reason, and so of elevating its rules into a science.

But his endeavours were vain. For the said rules or criteria are, in

respect to their chief sources, merely empirical, consequently never

can serve as determinate laws a priori, by which our judgement in

matters of taste is to be directed. It is rather our judgement which

forms the proper test as to the correctness of the principles. On this

account it is advisable to give up the use of the term as

designating the critique of taste, and to apply it solely to that

doctrine, which is true science- the science of the laws of

sensibility- and thus come nearer to the language and the sense of the

ancients in their well-known division of the objects of cognition into

aiotheta kai noeta, or to share it with speculative philosophy, and

employ it partly in a transcendental, partly in a psychological

signification.



  In the science of transcendental aesthetic accordingly, we shall

first isolate sensibility or the sensuous faculty, by separating

from it all that is annexed to its perceptions by the conceptions of

understanding, so that nothing be left but empirical intuition. In the

next place we shall take away from this intuition all that belongs

to sensation, so that nothing may remain but pure intuition, and the

mere form of phenomena, which is all that the sensibility can afford a

priori. From this investigation it will be found that there are two

pure forms of sensuous intuition, as principles of knowledge a priori,

namely, space and time. To the consideration of these we shall now

proceed.



                   SECTION I. Of Space.



     SS 2. Metaphysical Exposition of this Conception.



  By means of the external sense (a property of the mind), we

represent to ourselves objects as without us, and these all in

space. Herein alone are their shape, dimensions, and relations to each

other determined or determinable. The internal sense, by means of

which the mind contemplates itself or its internal state, gives,

indeed, no intuition of the soul as an object; yet there is

nevertheless a determinate form, under which alone the contemplation

of our internal state is possible, so that all which relates to the

inward determinations of the mind is represented in relations of time.

Of time we cannot have any external intuition, any more than we can

have an internal intuition of space. What then are time and space? Are

they real existences? Or, are they merely relations or

determinations of things, such, however, as would equally belong to

these things in themselves, though they should never become objects of

intuition; or, are they such as belong only to the form of

intuition, and consequently to the subjective constitution of the

mind, without which these predicates of time and space could not be

attached to any object? In order to become informed on these points,

we shall first give an exposition of the conception of space. By

exposition, I mean the clear, though not detailed, representation of

that which belongs to a conception; and an exposition is

metaphysical when it contains that which represents the conception

as given a priori.

  1. Space is not a conception which has been derived from outward

experiences. For, in order that certain sensations may relate to

something without me (that is, to something which occupies a different

part of space from that in which I am); in like manner, in order

that I may represent them not merely as without, of, and near to

each other, but also in separate places, the representation of space

must already exist as a foundation. Consequently, the representation

of space cannot be borrowed from the relations of external phenomena

through experience; but, on the contrary, this external experience

is itself only possible through the said antecedent representation.

  2. Space then is a necessary representation a priori, which serves

for the foundation of all external intuitions. We never can imagine or

make a representation to ourselves of the non-existence of space,

though we may easily enough think that no objects are found in it.

It must, therefore, be considered as the condition of the

possibility of phenomena, and by no means as a determination dependent

on them, and is a representation a priori, which necessarily

supplies the basis for external phenomena.

  3. Space is no discursive, or as we say, general conception of the

relations of things, but a pure intuition. For, in the first place, we

can only represent to ourselves one space, and, when we talk of divers

spaces, we mean only parts of one and the same space. Moreover,

these parts cannot antecede this one all-embracing space, as the

component parts from which the aggregate can be made up, but can be

cogitated only as existing in it. Space is essentially one, and

multiplicity in it, consequently the general notion of spaces, of this

or that space, depends solely upon limitations. Hence it follows

that an a priori intuition (which is not empirical) lies at the root

of all our conceptions of space. Thus, moreover, the principles of

geometry- for example, that "in a triangle, two sides together are

greater than the third," are never deduced from general conceptions of

line and triangle, but from intuition, and this a priori, with

apodeictic certainty.

  4. Space is represented as an infinite given quantity. Now every

conception must indeed be considered as a representation which is

contained in an infinite multitude of different possible

representations, which, therefore, comprises these under itself; but

no conception, as such, can be so conceived, as if it contained within

itself an infinite multitude of representations. Nevertheless, space

is so conceived of, for all parts of space are equally capable of

being produced to infinity. Consequently, the original

representation of space is an intuition a priori, and not a

conception.



  SS 3. Transcendental Exposition of the Conception of Space.



  By a transcendental exposition, I mean the explanation of a

conception, as a principle, whence can be discerned the possibility of

other synthetical a priori cognitions. For this purpose, it is

requisite, firstly, that such cognitions do really flow from the given

conception; and, secondly, that the said cognitions are only

possible under the presupposition of a given mode of explaining this

conception.

  Geometry is a science which determines the properties of space

synthetically, and yet a priori. What, then, must be our

representation of space, in order that such a cognition of it may be

possible? It must be originally intuition, for from a mere conception,

no propositions can be deduced which go out beyond the conception, and

yet this happens in geometry. (Introd. V.) But this intuition must

be found in the mind a priori, that is, before any perception of

objects, consequently must be pure, not empirical, intuition. For

geometrical principles are always apodeictic, that is, united with the

consciousness of their necessity, as: "Space has only three

dimensions." But propositions of this kind cannot be empirical

judgements, nor conclusions from them. (Introd. II.) Now, how can an

external intuition anterior to objects themselves, and in which our

conception of objects can be determined a priori, exist in the human

mind? Obviously not otherwise than in so far as it has its seat in the

subject only, as the formal capacity of the subject's being affected

by objects, and thereby of obtaining immediate representation, that

is, intuition; consequently, only as the form of the external sense in

general.

  Thus it is only by means of our explanation that the possibility

of geometry, as a synthetical science a priori, becomes

comprehensible. Every mode of explanation which does not show us

this possibility, although in appearance it may be similar to ours,

can with the utmost certainty be distinguished from it by these marks.



      SS 4. Conclusions from the foregoing Conceptions.



  (a) Space does Space does not represent any property of objects as

things in themselves, nor does it represent them in their relations to

each other; in other words, space does not represent to us any

determination of objects such as attaches to the objects themselves,

and would remain, even though all subjective conditions of the

intuition were abstracted. For neither absolute nor relative

determinations of objects can be intuited prior to the existence of

the things to which they belong, and therefore not a priori.

  (b) Space is nothing else than the form of all phenomena of the

external sense, that is, the subjective condition of the

sensibility, under which alone external intuition is possible. Now,

because the receptivity or capacity of the subject to be affected by

objects necessarily antecedes all intuitions of these objects, it is

easily understood how the form of all phenomena can be given in the

mind previous to all actual perceptions, therefore a priori, and how

it, as a pure intuition, in which all objects must be determined,

can contain principles of the relations of these objects prior to

all experience.

  It is therefore from the human point of view only that we can

speak of space, extended objects, etc. If we depart from the

subjective condition, under which alone we can obtain external

intuition, or, in other words, by means of which we are affected by

objects, the representation of space has no meaning whatsoever. This

predicate is only applicable to things in so far as they appear to us,

that is, are objects of sensibility. The constant form of this

receptivity, which we call sensibility, is a necessary condition of

all relations in which objects can be intuited as existing without us,

and when abstraction of these objects is made, is a pure intuition, to

which we give the name of space. It is clear that we cannot make the

special conditions of sensibility into conditions of the possibility

of things, but only of the possibility of their existence as far as

they are phenomena. And so we may correctly say that space contains

all which can appear to us externally, but not all things considered

as things in themselves, be they intuited or not, or by whatsoever

subject one will. As to the intuitions of other thinking beings, we

cannot judge whether they are or are not bound by the same

conditions which limit our own intuition, and which for us are

universally valid. If we join the limitation of a judgement to the

conception of the subject, then the judgement will possess

unconditioned validity. For example, the proposition, "All objects are

beside each other in space," is valid only under the limitation that

these things are taken as objects of our sensuous intuition. But if

I join the condition to the conception and say, "All things, as

external phenomena, are beside each other in space," then the rule

is valid universally, and without any limitation. Our expositions,

consequently, teach the reality (i.e., the objective validity) of

space in regard of all which can be presented to us externally as

object, and at the same time also the ideality of space in regard to

objects when they are considered by means of reason as things in

themselves, that is, without reference to the constitution of our

sensibility. We maintain, therefore, the empirical reality of space in

regard to all possible external experience, although we must admit its

transcendental ideality; in other words, that it is nothing, so soon

as we withdraw the condition upon which the possibility of all

experience depends and look upon space as something that belongs to

things in themselves.

  But, with the exception of space, there is no representation,

subjective and ref erring to something external to us, which could

be called objective a priori. For there are no other subjective

representations from which we can deduce synthetical propositions a

priori, as we can from the intuition of space. (See SS 3.)

Therefore, to speak accurately, no ideality whatever belongs to these,

although they agree in this respect with the representation of

space, that they belong merely to the subjective nature of the mode of

sensuous perception; such a mode, for example, as that of sight, of

hearing, and of feeling, by means of the sensations of colour,

sound, and heat, but which, because they are only sensations and not

intuitions, do not of themselves give us the cognition of any

object, least of all, an a priori cognition. My purpose, in the

above remark, is merely this: to guard any one against illustrating

the asserted ideality of space by examples quite insufficient, for

example, by colour, taste, etc.; for these must be contemplated not as

properties of things, but only as changes in the subject, changes

which may be different in different men. For, in such a case, that

which is originally a mere phenomenon, a rose, for example, is taken

by the empirical understanding for a thing in itself, though to

every different eye, in respect of its colour, it may appear

different. On the contrary, the transcendental conception of phenomena

in space is a critical admonition, that, in general, nothing which

is intuited in space is a thing in itself, and that space is not a

form which belongs as a property to things; but that objects are quite

unknown to us in themselves, and what we call outward objects, are

nothing else but mere representations of our sensibility, whose form

is space, but whose real correlate, the thing in itself, is not

known by means of these representations, nor ever can be, but

respecting which, in experience, no inquiry is ever made.



                  SECTION II. Of Time.



     SS 5 Metaphysical Exposition of this Conception.



  1. Time is not an empirical conception. For neither coexistence

nor succession would be perceived by us, if the representation of time

did not exist as a foundation a priori. Without this presupposition we

could not represent to ourselves that things exist together at one and

the same time, or at different times, that is, contemporaneously, or

in succession.

  2. Time is a necessary representation, lying at the foundation of

all our intuitions. With regard to phenomena in general, we cannot

think away time from them, and represent them to ourselves as out of

and unconnected with time, but we can quite well represent to

ourselves time void of phenomena. Time is therefore given a priori. In

it alone is all reality of phenomena possible. These may all be

annihilated in thought, but time itself, as the universal condition of

their possibility, cannot be so annulled.

  3. On this necessity a priori is also founded the possibility of

apodeictic principles of the relations of time, or axioms of time in

general, such as: "Time has only one dimension," "Different times

are not coexistent but successive" (as different spaces are not

successive but coexistent). These principles cannot be derived from

experience, for it would give neither strict universality, nor

apodeictic certainty. We should only be able to say, "so common

experience teaches us," but not "it must be so." They are valid as

rules, through which, in general, experience is possible; and they

instruct us respecting experience, and not by means of it.

  4. Time is not a discursive, or as it is called, general conception,

but a pure form of the sensuous intuition. Different times are

merely parts of one and the same time. But the representation which

can only be given by a single object is an intuition. Besides, the

proposition that different times cannot be coexistent could not be

derived from a general conception. For this proposition is

synthetical, and therefore cannot spring out of conceptions alone.

It is therefore contained immediately in the intuition and

representation of time.

  5. The infinity of time signifies nothing more than that every

determined quantity of time is possible only through limitations of

one time lying at the foundation. Consequently, the original

representation, time, must be given as unlimited. But as the

determinate representation of the parts of time and of every

quantity of an object can only be obtained by limitation, the complete

representation of time must not be furnished by means of

conceptions, for these contain only partial representations.

Conceptions, on the contrary, must have immediate intuition for

their basis.



   SS 6 Transcendental Exposition of the Conception of Time.



  I may here refer to what is said above (SS 5, 3), where, for or sake

of brevity, I have placed under the head of metaphysical exposition,

that which is properly transcendental. Here I shall add that the

conception of change, and with it the conception of motion, as

change of place, is possible only through and in the representation of

time; that if this representation were not an intuition (internal) a

priori, no conception, of whatever kind, could render comprehensible

the possibility of change, in other words, of a conjunction of

contradictorily opposed predicates in one and the same object, for

example, the presence of a thing in a place and the non-presence of

the same thing in the same place. It is only in time that it is

possible to meet with two contradictorily opposed determinations in

one thing, that is, after each other. thus our conception of time

explains the possibility of so much synthetical knowledge a priori, as

is exhibited in the general doctrine of motion, which is not a

little fruitful.



         SS 7 Conclusions from the above Conceptions.



  (a) Time is not something which subsists of itself, or which inheres

in things as an objective determination, and therefore remains, when

abstraction is made of the subjective conditions of the intuition of

things. For in the former case, it would be something real, yet

without presenting to any power of perception any real object. In

the latter case, as an order or determination inherent in things

themselves, it could not be antecedent to things, as their

condition, nor discerned or intuited by means of synthetical

propositions a priori. But all this is quite possible when we regard

time as merely the subjective condition under which all our intuitions

take place. For in that case, this form of the inward intuition can be

represented prior to the objects, and consequently a priori.

  (b) Time is nothing else than the form of the internal sense, that

is, of the intuitions of self and of our internal state. For time

cannot be any determination of outward phenomena. It has to do neither

with shape nor position; on the contrary, it determines the relation

of representations in our internal state. And precisely because this

internal intuition presents to us no shape or form, we endeavour to

supply this want by analogies, and represent the course of time by a

line progressing to infinity, the content of which constitutes a

series which is only of one dimension; and we conclude from the

properties of this line as to all the properties of time, with this

single exception, that the parts of the line are coexistent, whilst

those of time are successive. From this it is clear also that the

representation of time is itself an intuition, because all its

relations can be expressed in an external intuition.

  (c) Time is the formal condition a priori of all phenomena

whatsoever. Space, as the pure form of external intuition, is

limited as a condition a priori to external phenomena alone. On the

other hand, because all representations, whether they have or have not

external things for their objects, still in themselves, as

determinations of the mind, belong to our internal state; and

because this internal state is subject to the formal condition of

the internal intuition, that is, to time- time is a condition a priori

of all phenomena whatsoever- the immediate condition of all

internal, and thereby the mediate condition of all external phenomena.

If I can say a priori, "All outward phenomena are in space, and

determined a priori according to the relations of space," I can

also, from the principle of the internal sense, affirm universally,

"All phenomena in general, that is, all objects of the senses, are

in time and stand necessarily in relations of time."

  If we abstract our internal intuition of ourselves and all

external intuitions, possible only by virtue of this internal

intuition and presented to us by our faculty of representation, and

consequently take objects as they are in themselves, then time is

nothing. It is only of objective validity in regard to phenomena,

because these are things which we regard as objects of our senses.

It no longer objective we, make abstraction of the sensuousness of our

intuition, in other words, of that mode of representation which is

peculiar to us, and speak of things in general. Time is therefore

merely a subjective condition of our (human) intuition (which is

always sensuous, that is, so far as we are affected by objects), and

in itself, independently of the mind or subject, is nothing.

Nevertheless, in respect of all phenomena, consequently of all

things which come within the sphere of our experience, it is

necessarily objective. We cannot say, "All things are in time,"

because in this conception of things in general, we abstract and

make no mention of any sort of intuition of things. But this is the

proper condition under which time belongs to our representation of

objects. If we add the condition to the conception, and say, "All

things, as phenomena, that is, objects of sensuous intuition, are in

time," then the proposition has its sound objective validity and

universality a priori.

  What we have now set forth teaches, therefore, the empirical reality

of time; that is, its objective validity in reference to all objects

which can ever be presented to our senses. And as our intuition is

always sensuous, no object ever can be presented to us in

experience, which does not come under the conditions of time. On the

other hand, we deny to time all claim to absolute reality; that is, we

deny that it, without having regard to the form of our sensuous

intuition, absolutely inheres in things as a condition or property.

Such properties as belong to objects as things in themselves never can

be presented to us through the medium of the senses. Herein

consists, therefore, the transcendental ideality of time, according to

which, if we abstract the subjective conditions of sensuous intuition,

it is nothing, and cannot be reckoned as subsisting or inhering in

objects as things in themselves, independently of its relation to

our intuition. this ideality, like that of space, is not to be

proved or illustrated by fallacious analogies with sensations, for

this reason- that in such arguments or illustrations, we make the

presupposition that the phenomenon, in which such and such

predicates inhere, has objective reality, while in this case we can

only find such an objective reality as is itself empirical, that is,

regards the object as a mere phenomenon. In reference to this subject,

see the remark in Section I (SS 4)



                    SS 8 Elucidation.



  Against this theory, which grants empirical reality to time, but

denies to it absolute and transcendental reality, I have heard from

intelligent men an objection so unanimously urged that I conclude that

it must naturally present itself to every reader to whom these

considerations are novel. It runs thus: "Changes are real" (this the

continual change in our own representations demonstrates, even

though the existence of all external phenomena, together with their

changes, is denied). Now, changes are only possible in time, and

therefore time must be something real. But there is no difficulty in

answering this. I grant the whole argument. Time, no doubt, is

something real, that is, it is the real form of our internal

intuition. It therefore has subjective reality, in reference to our

internal experience, that is, I have really the representation of time

and of my determinations therein. Time, therefore, is not to be

regarded as an object, but as the mode of representation of myself

as an object. But if I could intuite myself, or be intuited by another

being, without this condition of sensibility, then those very

determinations which we now represent to ourselves as changes, would

present to us a knowledge in which the representation of time, and

consequently of change, would not appear. The empirical reality of

time, therefore, remains, as the condition of all our experience.

But absolute reality, according to what has been said above, cannot be

granted it. Time is nothing but the form of our internal intuition.*

If we take away from it the special condition of our sensibility,

the conception of time also vanishes; and it inheres not in the

objects themselves, but solely in the subject (or mind) which intuites

them.



  *I can indeed say "my representations follow one another, or are

successive"; but this means only that we are conscious of them as in a

succession, that is, according to the form of the internal sense.

Time, therefore, is not a thing in itself, nor is it any objective

determination pertaining to, or inherent in things.



  But the reason why this objection is so unanimously brought

against our doctrine of time, and that too by disputants who cannot

start any intelligible arguments against the doctrine of the

ideality of space, is this- they have no hope of demonstrating

apodeictically the absolute reality of space, because the doctrine

of idealism is against them, according to which the reality of

external objects is not capable of any strict proof. On the other

hand, the reality of the object of our internal sense (that is, myself

and my internal state) is clear immediately through consciousness. The

former- external objects in space- might be a mere delusion, but the

latter- the object of my internal perception- is undeniably real. They

do not, however, reflect that both, without question of their

reality as representations, belong only to the genus phenomenon, which

has always two aspects, the one, the object considered as a thing in

itself, without regard to the mode of intuiting it, and the nature

of which remains for this very reason problematical, the other, the

form of our intuition of the object, which must be sought not in the

object as a thing in itself, but in the subject to which it appears-

which form of intuition nevertheless belongs really and necessarily to

the phenomenal object.

  Time and space are, therefore, two sources of knowledge, from which,

a priori, various synthetical cognitions can be drawn. Of this we find

a striking example in the cognitions of space and its relations, which

form the foundation of pure mathematics. They are the two pure forms

of all intuitions, and thereby make synthetical propositions a

priori possible. But these sources of knowledge being merely

conditions of our sensibility, do therefore, and as such, strictly

determine their own range and purpose, in that they do not and

cannot present objects as things in themselves, but are applicable

to them solely in so far as they are considered as sensuous phenomena.

The sphere of phenomena is the only sphere of their validity, and if

we venture out of this, no further objective use can be made of

them. For the rest, this formal reality of time and space leaves the

validity of our empirical knowledge unshaken; for our certainty in

that respect is equally firm, whether these forms necessarily inhere

in the things themselves, or only in our intuitions of them. On the

other hand, those who maintain the absolute reality of time and space,

whether as essentially subsisting, or only inhering, as modifications,

in things, must find themselves at utter variance with the

principles of experience itself. For, if they decide for the first

view, and make space and time into substances, this being the side

taken by mathematical natural philosophers, they must admit two

self-subsisting nonentities, infinite and eternal, which exist (yet

without there being anything real) for the purpose of containing in

themselves everything that is real. If they adopt the second view of

inherence, which is preferred by some metaphysical natural

philosophers, and regard space and time as relations (contiguity in

space or succession in time), abstracted from experience, though

represented confusedly in this state of separation, they find

themselves in that case necessitated to deny the validity of

mathematical doctrines a priori in reference to real things (for

example, in space)- at all events their apodeictic certainty. For such

certainty cannot be found in an a posteriori proposition; and the

conceptions a priori of space and time are, according to this opinion,

mere creations of the imagination, having their source really in

experience, inasmuch as, out of relations abstracted from

experience, imagination has made up something which contains,

indeed, general statements of these relations, yet of which no

application can be made without the restrictions attached thereto by

nature. The former of these parties gains this advantage, that they

keep the sphere of phenomena free for mathematical science. On the

other hand, these very conditions (space and time) embarrass them

greatly, when the understanding endeavours to pass the limits of

that sphere. The latter has, indeed, this advantage, that the

representations of space and time do not come in their way when they

wish to judge of objects, not as phenomena, but merely in their

relation to the understanding. Devoid, however, of a true and

objectively valid a priori intuition, they can neither furnish any

basis for the possibility of mathematical cognitions a priori, nor

bring the propositions of experience into necessary accordance with

those of mathematics. In our theory of the true nature of these two

original forms of the sensibility, both difficulties are surmounted.

  In conclusion, that transcendental aesthetic cannot contain any more

than these two elements- space and time, is sufficiently obvious

from the fact that all other conceptions appertaining to

sensibility, even that of motion, which unites in itself both

elements, presuppose something empirical. Motion, for example,

presupposes the perception of something movable. But space

considered in itself contains nothing movable, consequently motion

must be something which is found in space only through experience-

in other words, an empirical datum. In like manner, transcendental

aesthetic cannot number the conception of change among its data a

priori; for time itself does not change, but only something which is

in time. To acquire the conception of change, therefore, the

perception of some existing object and of the succession of its

determinations, in one word, experience, is necessary.



      SS 9 General Remarks on Transcendental Aesthetic.



  I. In order to prevent any misunderstanding, it will be requisite,

in the first place, to recapitulate, as clearly as possible, what

our opinion is with respect to the fundamental nature of our

sensuous cognition in general. We have intended, then, to say that all

our intuition is nothing but the representation of phenomena; that the

things which we intuite, are not in themselves the same as our

representations of them in intuition, nor are their relations in

themselves so constituted as they appear to us; and that if we take

away the subject, or even only the subjective constitution of our

senses in general, then not only the nature and relations of objects

in space and time, but even space and time themselves disappear; and

that these, as phenomena, cannot exist in themselves, but only in

us. What may be the nature of objects considered as things in

themselves and without reference to the receptivity of our sensibility

is quite unknown to us. We know nothing more than our mode of

perceiving them, which is peculiar to us, and which, though not of

necessity pertaining to every animated being, is so to the whole human

race. With this alone we have to do. Space and time are the pure forms

thereof; sensation the matter. The former alone can we cognize a

priori, that is, antecedent to all actual perception; and for this

reason such cognition is called pure intuition. The latter is that

in our cognition which is called cognition a posteriori, that is,

empirical intuition. The former appertain absolutely and necessarily

to our sensibility, of whatsoever kind our sensations may be; the

latter may be of very diversified character. Supposing that we

should carry our empirical intuition even to the very highest degree

of clearness, we should not thereby advance one step nearer to a

knowledge of the constitution of objects as things in themselves.

For we could only, at best, arrive at a complete cognition of our

own mode of intuition, that is of our sensibility, and this always

under the conditions originally attaching to the subject, namely,

the conditions of space and time; while the question: "What are

objects considered as things in themselves?" remains unanswerable even

after the most thorough examination of the phenomenal world.

  To say, then, that all our sensibility is nothing but the confused

representation of things containing exclusively that which belongs

to them as things in themselves, and this under an accumulation of

characteristic marks and partial representations which we cannot

distinguish in consciousness, is a falsification of the conception

of sensibility and phenomenization, which renders our whole doctrine

thereof empty and useless. The difference between a confused and a

clear representation is merely logical and has nothing to do with

content. No doubt the conception of right, as employed by a sound

understanding, contains all that the most subtle investigation could

unfold from it, although, in the ordinary practical use of the word,

we are not conscious of the manifold representations comprised in

the conception. But we cannot for this reason assert that the ordinary

conception is a sensuous one, containing a mere phenomenon, for

right cannot appear as a phenomenon; but the conception of it lies

in the understanding, and represents a property (the moral property)

of actions, which belongs to them in themselves. On the other hand,

the representation in intuition of a body contains nothing which could

belong to an object considered as a thing in itself, but merely the

phenomenon or appearance of something, and the mode in which we are

affected by that appearance; and this receptivity of our faculty of

cognition is called sensibility, and remains toto caelo different from

the cognition of an object in itself, even though we should examine

the content of the phenomenon to the very bottom.

  It must be admitted that the Leibnitz-Wolfian philosophy has

assigned an entirely erroneous point of view to all investigations

into the nature and origin of our cognitions, inasmuch as it regards

the distinction between the sensuous and the intellectual as merely

logical, whereas it is plainly transcendental, and concerns not merely

the clearness or obscurity, but the content and origin of both. For

the faculty of sensibility not only does not present us with an

indistinct and confused cognition of objects as things in

themselves, but, in fact, gives us no knowledge of these at all. On

the contrary, so soon as we abstract in thought our own subjective

nature, the object represented, with the properties ascribed to it

by sensuous intuition, entirely disappears, because it was only this

subjective nature that determined the form of the object as a

phenomenon.

  In phenomena, we commonly, indeed, distinguish that which

essentially belongs to the intuition of them, and is valid for the

sensuous faculty of every human being, from that which belongs to

the same intuition accidentally, as valid not for the sensuous faculty

in general, but for a particular state or organization of this or that

sense. Accordingly, we are accustomed to say that the former is a

cognition which represents the object itself, whilst the latter

presents only a particular appearance or phenomenon thereof. This

distinction, however, is only empirical. If we stop here (as is

usual), and do not regard the empirical intuition as itself a mere

phenomenon (as we ought to do), in which nothing that can appertain to

a thing in itself is to be found, our transcendental distinction is

lost, and we believe that we cognize objects as things in

themselves, although in the whole range of the sensuous world,

investigate the nature of its objects as profoundly as we may, we have

to do with nothing but phenomena. Thus, we call the rainbow a mere

appearance of phenomenon in a sunny shower, and the rain, the

reality or thing in itself; and this is right enough, if we understand

the latter conception in a merely physical sense, that is, as that

which in universal experience, and under whatever conditions of

sensuous perception, is known in intuition to be so and so determined,

and not otherwise. But if we consider this empirical datum

generally, and inquire, without reference to its accordance with all

our senses, whether there can be discovered in it aught which

represents an object as a thing in itself (the raindrops of course are

not such, for they are, as phenomena, empirical objects), the question

of the relation of the representation to the object is transcendental;

and not only are the raindrops mere phenomena, but even their circular

form, nay, the space itself through which they fall, is nothing in

itself, but both are mere modifications or fundamental dispositions of

our sensuous intuition, whilst the transcendental object remains for

us utterly unknown.

  The second important concern of our aesthetic is that it does not

obtain favour merely as a plausible hypothesis, but possess as

undoubted a character of certainty as can be demanded of any theory

which is to serve for an organon. In order fully to convince the

reader of this certainty, we shall select a case which will serve to

make its validity apparent, and also to illustrate what has been

said in SS 3.

  Suppose, then, that space and time are in themselves objective,

and conditions of the- possibility of objects as things in themselves.

In the first place, it is evident that both present us, with very many

apodeictic and synthetic propositions a priori, but especially

space- and for this reason we shall prefer it for investigation at

present. As the propositions of geometry are cognized synthetically

a priori, and with apodeictic certainty, I inquire: Whence do you

obtain propositions of this kind, and on what basis does the

understanding rest, in order to arrive at such absolutely necessary

and universally valid truths?

  There is no other way than through intuitions or conceptions, as

such; and these are given either a priori or a posteriori. The latter,

namely, empirical conceptions, together with the empirical intuition

on which they are founded, cannot afford any synthetical

proposition, except such as is itself also empirical, that is, a

proposition of experience. But an empirical proposition cannot possess

the qualities of necessity and absolute universality, which,

nevertheless, are the characteristics of all geometrical propositions.

As to the first and only means to arrive at such cognitions, namely,

through mere conceptions or intuitions a priori, it is quite clear

that from mere conceptions no synthetical cognitions, but only

analytical ones, can be obtained. Take, for example, the

proposition: "Two straight lines cannot enclose a space, and with

these alone no figure is possible," and try to deduce it from the

conception of a straight line and the number two; or take the

proposition: "It is possible to construct a figure with three straight

lines," and endeavour, in like manner, to deduce it from the mere

conception of a straight line and the number three. All your

endeavours are in vain, and you find yourself forced to have

recourse to intuition, as, in fact, geometry always does. You

therefore give yourself an object in intuition. But of what kind is

this intuition? Is it a pure a priori, or is it an empirical

intuition? If the latter, then neither an universally valid, much less

an apodeictic proposition can arise from it, for experience never

can give us any such proposition. You must, therefore, give yourself

an object a priori in intuition, and upon that ground your synthetical

proposition. Now if there did not exist within you a faculty of

intuition a priori; if this subjective condition were not in respect

to its form also the universal condition a priori under which alone

the object of this external intuition is itself possible; if the

object (that is, the triangle) were something in itself, without

relation to you the subject; how could you affirm that that which lies

necessarily in your subjective conditions in order to construct a

triangle, must also necessarily belong to the triangle in itself?

For to your conceptions of three lines, you could not add anything new

(that is, the figure); which, therefore, must necessarily be found

in the object, because the object is given before your cognition,

and not by means of it. If, therefore, space (and time also) were

not a mere form of your intuition, which contains conditions a priori,

under which alone things can become external objects for you, and

without which subjective conditions the objects are in themselves

nothing, you could not construct any synthetical proposition

whatsoever regarding external objects. It is therefore not merely

possible or probable, but indubitably certain, that space and time, as

the necessary conditions of all our external and internal

experience, are merely subjective conditions of all our intuitions, in

relation to which all objects are therefore mere phenomena, and not

things in themselves, presented to us in this particular manner. And

for this reason, in respect to the form of phenomena, much may be said

a priori, whilst of the thing in itself, which may lie at the

foundation of these phenomena, it is impossible to say anything.

  II. In confirmation of this theory of the ideality of the external

as well as internal sense, consequently of all objects of sense, as

mere phenomena, we may especially remark that all in our cognition

that belongs to intuition contains nothing more than mere relations.

(The feelings of pain and pleasure, and the will, which are not

cognitions, are excepted.) The relations, to wit, of place in an

intuition (extension), change of place (motion), and laws according to

which this change is determined (moving forces). That, however,

which is present in this or that place, or any operation going on,

or result taking place in the things themselves, with the exception of

change of place, is not given to us by intuition. Now by means of mere

relations, a thing cannot be known in itself; and it may therefore

be fairly concluded, that, as through the external sense nothing but

mere representations of relations are given us, the said external

sense in its representation can contain only the relation of the

object to the subject, but not the essential nature of the object as a

thing in itself.

  The same is the case with the internal intuition, not only

because, in the internal intuition, the representation of the external

senses constitutes the material with which the mind is occupied; but

because time, in which we place, and which itself antecedes the

consciousness of, these representations in experience, and which, as

the formal condition of the mode according to which objects are placed

in the mind, lies at the foundation of them, contains relations of the

successive, the coexistent, and of that which always must be

coexistent with succession, the permanent. Now that which, as

representation, can antecede every exercise of thought (of an object),

is intuition; and when it contains nothing but relations, it is the

form of the intuition, which, as it presents us with no

representation, except in so far as something is placed in the mind,

can be nothing else than the mode in which the mind is affected by its

own activity, to wit- its presenting to itself representations,

consequently the mode in which the mind is affected by itself; that

is, it can be nothing but an internal sense in respect to its form.

Everything that is represented through the medium of sense is so far

phenomenal; consequently, we must either refuse altogether to admit an

internal sense, or the subject, which is the object of that sense,

could only be represented by it as phenomenon, and not as it would

judge of itself, if its intuition were pure spontaneous activity, that

is, were intellectual. The difficulty here lies wholly in the

question: How can the subject have an internal intuition of itself?

But this difficulty is common to every theory. The consciousness of

self (apperception) is the simple representation of the "ego"; and

if by means of that representation alone, all the manifold

representations in the subject were spontaneously given, then our

internal intuition would be intellectual. This consciousness in man

requires an internal perception of the manifold representations

which are previously given in the subject; and the manner in which

these representations are given in the mind without spontaneity, must,

on account of this difference (the want of spontaneity), be called

sensibility. If the faculty of self-consciousness is to apprehend what

lies in the mind, it must all act that and can in this way alone

produce an intuition of self. But the form of this intuition, which

lies in the original constitution of the mind, determines, in the

representation of time, the manner in which the manifold

representations are to combine themselves in the mind; since the

subject intuites itself, not as it would represent itself

immediately and spontaneously, but according to the manner in which

the mind is internally affected, consequently, as it appears, and

not as it is.

  III. When we say that the intuition of external objects, and also

the self-intuition of the subject, represent both, objects and

subject, in space and time, as they affect our senses, that is, as

they appear- this is by no means equivalent to asserting that these

objects are mere illusory appearances. For when we speak of things

as phenomena, the objects, nay, even the properties which we ascribe

to them, are looked upon as really given; only that, in so far as this

or that property depends upon the mode of intuition of the subject, in

the relation of the given object to the subject, the object as

phenomenon is to be distinguished from the object as a thing in

itself. Thus I do not say that bodies seem or appear to be external to

me, or that my soul seems merely to be given in my self-consciousness,

although I maintain that the properties of space and time, in

conformity to which I set both, as the condition of their existence,

abide in my mode of intuition, and not in the objects in themselves.

It would be my own fault, if out of that which I should reckon as

phenomenon, I made mere illusory appearance.* But this will not

happen, because of our principle of the ideality of all sensuous

intuitions. On the contrary, if we ascribe objective reality to

these forms of representation, it becomes impossible to avoid changing

everything into mere appearance. For if we regard space and time as

properties, which must be found in objects as things in themselves, as

sine quibus non of the possibility of their existence, and reflect

on the absurdities in which we then find ourselves involved,

inasmuch as we are compelled to admit the existence of two infinite

things, which are nevertheless not substances, nor anything really

inhering in substances, nay, to admit that they are the necessary

conditions of the existence of all things, and moreover, that they

must continue to exist, although all existing things were annihilated-

we cannot blame the good Berkeley for degrading bodies to mere

illusory appearances. Nay, even our own existence, which would in this

case depend upon the self-existent reality of such a mere nonentity as

time, would necessarily be changed with it into mere appearance- an

absurdity which no one has as yet been guilty of.



  *The predicates of the phenomenon can be affixed to the object

itself in relation to our sensuous faculty; for example, the red

colour or the perfume to the rose. But (illusory) appearance never can

be attributed as a predicate to an object, for this very reason,

that it attributes to this object in itself that which belongs to it

only in relation to our sensuous faculty, or to the subject in

general, e.g., the two handles which were formerly ascribed to Saturn.

That which is never to be found in the object itself, but always in

the relation of the object to the subject, and which moreover is

inseparable from our representation of the object, we denominate

phenomenon. Thus the predicates of space and time are rightly

attributed to objects of the senses as such, and in this there is no

illusion. On the contrary, if I ascribe redness of the rose as a thing

in itself, or to Saturn his handles, or extension to all external

objects, considered as things in themselves, without regarding the

determinate relation of these objects to the subject, and without

limiting my judgement to that relation- then, and then only, arises

illusion.



  IV. In natural theology, where we think of an object- God- which

never can be an object of intuition to us, and even to himself can

never be an object of sensuous intuition, we carefully avoid

attributing to his intuition the conditions of space and time- and

intuition all his cognition must be, and not thought, which always

includes limitation. But with what right can we do this if we make

them forms of objects as things in themselves, and such, moreover,

as would continue to exist as a priori conditions of the existence

of things, even though the things themselves were annihilated? For

as conditions of all existence in general, space and time must be

conditions of the existence of the Supreme Being also. But if we do

not thus make them objective forms of all things, there is no other

way left than to make them subjective forms of our mode of

intuition- external and internal; which is called sensuous, because it

is not primitive, that is, is not such as gives in itself the

existence of the object of the intuition (a mode of intuition which,

so far as we can judge, can belong only to the Creator), but is

dependent on the existence of the object, is possible, therefore, only

on condition that the representative faculty of the subject is

affected by the object.

  It is, moreover, not necessary that we should limit the mode of

intuition in space and time to the sensuous faculty of man. It may

well be that all finite thinking beings must necessarily in this

respect agree with man (though as to this we cannot decide), but

sensibility does not on account of this universality cease to be

sensibility, for this very reason, that it is a deduced (intuitus

derivativus), and not an original (intuitus originarius), consequently

not an intellectual intuition, and this intuition, as such, for

reasons above mentioned, seems to belong solely to the Supreme

Being, but never to a being dependent, quoad its existence, as well as

its intuition (which its existence determines and limits relatively to

given objects). This latter remark, however, must be taken only as

an illustration, and not as any proof of the truth of our

aesthetical theory.



    SS 10 Conclusion of the Transcendental Aesthetic.



  We have now completely before us one part of the solution of the

grand general problem of transcendental philosophy, namely, the

question: "How are synthetical propositions a priori possible?" That

is to say, we have shown that we are in possession of pure a priori

intuitions, namely, space and time, in which we find, when in a

judgement a priori we pass out beyond the given conception,

something which is not discoverable in that conception, but is

certainly found a priori in the intuition which corresponds to the

conception, and can be united synthetically with it. But the

judgements which these pure intuitions enable us to make, never

reach farther than to objects of the senses, and are valid only for

objects of possible experience.

INTRO

            SECOND PART. TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC.



       INTRODUCTION. Idea of a Transcendental Logic.



                 I. Of Logic in General.



  Our knowledge springs from two main sources in the mind, first of

which is the faculty or power of receiving representations

(receptivity for impressions); the second is the power of cognizing by

means of these representations (spontaneity in the production of

conceptions). Through the first an object is given to us; through

the second, it is, in relation to the representation (which is a

mere determination of the mind), thought. Intuition and conceptions

constitute, therefore, the elements of all our knowledge, so that

neither conceptions without an intuition in some way corresponding

to them, nor intuition without conceptions, can afford us a cognition.

Both are either pure or empirical. They are. empirical, when sensation

(which presupposes the actual presence of the object) is contained

in them; and pure, when no sensation is mixed with the representation.

Sensations we may call the matter of sensuous cognition. Pure

intuition consequently contains merely the form under which

something is intuited, and pure conception only the form of the

thought of an object. Only pure intuitions and pure conceptions are

possible a priori; the empirical only a posteriori.

  We apply the term sensibility to the receptivity of the mind for

impressions, in so far as it is in some way affected; and, on the

other hand, we call the faculty of spontaneously producing

representations, or the spontaneity of cognition, understanding. Our

nature is so constituted that intuition with us never can be other

than sensuous, that is, it contains only the mode in which we are

affected by objects. On the other hand, the faculty of thinking the

object of sensuous intuition is the understanding. Neither of these

faculties has a preference over the other. Without the sensuous

faculty no object would be given to us, and without the

understanding no object would be thought. Thoughts without content are

void; intuitions without conceptions, blind. Hence it is as

necessary for the mind to make its conceptions sensuous (that is, to

join to them the object in intuition), as to make its intuitions

intelligible (that is, to bring them under conceptions). Neither of

these faculties can exchange its proper function. Understanding cannot

intuite, and the sensuous faculty cannot think. in no other way than

from the united operation of both, can knowledge arise. But no one

ought, on this account, to overlook the difference of the elements

contributed by each; we have rather great reason carefully to separate

and distinguish them. We therefore distinguish the science of the laws

of sensibility, that is, aesthetic, from the science of the laws of

the understanding, that is, logic.

  Now, logic in its turn may be considered as twofold- namely, as

logic of the general, or of the particular use of the understanding.

The first contains the absolutely necessary laws of thought, without

which no use whatsoever of the understanding is possible, and gives

laws therefore to the understanding, without regard to the

difference of objects on which it may be employed. The logic of the

particular use of the understanding contains the laws of correct

thinking upon a particular class of objects. The former may be

called elemental logic- the latter, the organon of this or that

particular science. The latter is for the most part employed in the

schools, as a propaedeutic to the sciences, although, indeed,

according to the course of human reason, it is the last thing we

arrive at, when the science has been already matured, and needs only

the finishing touches towards its correction and completion; for our

knowledge of the objects of our attempted science must be tolerably

extensive and complete before we can indicate the laws by which a

science of these objects can be established.

  General logic is again either pure or applied. In the former, we

abstract all the empirical conditions under which the understanding is

exercised; for example, the influence of the senses, the play of the

fantasy or imagination, the laws of the memory, the force of habit, of

inclination, etc., consequently also, the sources of prejudice- in a

word, we abstract all causes from which particular cognitions arise,

because these causes regard the understanding under certain

circumstances of its application, and, to the knowledge of them

experience is required. Pure general logic has to do, therefore,

merely with pure a priori principles, and is a canon of

understanding and reason, but only in respect of the formal part of

their use, be the content what it may, empirical or transcendental.

General logic is called applied, when it is directed to the laws of

the use of the understanding, under the subjective empirical

conditions which psychology teaches us. It has therefore empirical

principles, although, at the same time, it is in so far general,

that it applies to the exercise of the understanding, without regard

to the difference of objects. On this account, moreover, it is neither

a canon of the understanding in general, nor an organon of a

particular science, but merely a cathartic of the human understanding.

  In general logic, therefore, that part which constitutes pure

logic must be carefully distinguished from that which constitutes

applied (though still general) logic. The former alone is properly

science, although short and dry, as the methodical exposition of an

elemental doctrine of the understanding ought to be. In this,

therefore, logicians must always bear in mind two rules:

  1. As general logic, it makes abstraction of all content of the

cognition of the understanding, and of the difference of objects,

and has to do with nothing but the mere form of thought.

  2. As pure logic, it has no empirical principles, and consequently

draws nothing (contrary to the common persuasion) from psychology,

which therefore has no influence on the canon of the understanding. It

is a demonstrated doctrine, and everything in it must be certain

completely a priori.

  What I called applied logic (contrary to the common acceptation of

this term, according to which it should contain certain exercises

for the scholar, for which pure logic gives the rules), is a

representation of the understanding, and of the rules of its necessary

employment in concreto, that is to say, under the accidental

conditions of the subject, which may either hinder or promote this

employment, and which are all given only empirically. Thus applied

logic treats of attention, its impediments and consequences, of the

origin of error, of the state of doubt, hesitation, conviction,

etc., and to it is related pure general logic in the same way that

pure morality, which contains only the necessary moral laws of a

free will, is related to practical ethics, which considers these

laws under all the impediments of feelings, inclinations, and passions

to which men are more or less subjected, and which never can furnish

us with a true and demonstrated science, because it, as well as

applied logic, requires empirical and psychological principles.



               II. Of Transcendental Logic.



  General logic, as we have seen, makes abstraction of all content

of cognition, that is, of all relation of cognition to its object, and

regards only the logical form in the relation of cognitions to each

other, that is, the form of thought in general. But as we have both

pure and empirical intuitions (as transcendental aesthetic proves), in

like manner a distinction might be drawn between pure and empirical

thought (of objects). In this case, there would exist a kind of logic,

in which we should not make abstraction of all content of cognition;

for or logic which should comprise merely the laws of pure thought (of

an object), would of course exclude all those cognitions which were of

empirical content. This kind of logic would also examine the origin of

our cognitions of objects, so far as that origin cannot be ascribed to

the objects themselves; while, on the contrary, general logic has

nothing to do with the origin of our cognitions, but contemplates

our representations, be they given primitively a priori in

ourselves, or be they only of empirical origin, solely according to

the laws which the understanding observes in employing them in the

process of thought, in relation to each other. Consequently, general

logic treats of the form of the understanding only, which can be

applied to representations, from whatever source they may have arisen.

  And here I shall make a remark, which the reader must bear well in

mind in the course of the following considerations, to wit, that not

every cognition a priori, but only those through which we cognize that

and how certain representations (intuitions or conceptions) are

applied or are possible only a priori; that is to say, the a priori

possibility of cognition and the a priori use of it are

transcendental. Therefore neither is space, nor any a priori

geometrical determination of space, a transcendental Representation,

but only the knowledge that such a representation is not of

empirical origin, and the possibility of its relating to objects of

experience, although itself a priori, can be called transcendental. So

also, the application of space to objects in general would be

transcendental; but if it be limited to objects of sense it is

empirical. Thus, the distinction of the transcendental and empirical

belongs only to the critique of cognitions, and does not concern the

relation of these to their object.

  Accordingly, in the expectation that there may perhaps be

conceptions which relate a priori to objects, not as pure or

sensuous intuitions, but merely as acts of pure thought (which are

therefore conceptions, but neither of empirical nor aesthetical

origin)- in this expectation, I say, we form to ourselves, by

anticipation, the idea of a science of pure understanding and rational

cognition, by means of which we may cogitate objects entirely a

priori. A science of this kind, which should determine the origin, the

extent, and the objective validity of such cognitions, must be

called transcendental logic, because it has not, like general logic,

to do with the laws of understanding and reason in relation to

empirical as well as pure rational cognitions without distinction, but

concerns itself with these only in an a priori relation to objects.



  III. Of the Division of General Logic into Analytic and Dialectic.



  The old question with which people sought to push logicians into a

corner, so that they must either have recourse to pitiful sophisms

or confess their ignorance, and consequently the vanity of their whole

art, is this: "What is truth?" The definition of the word truth, to

wit, "the accordance of the cognition with its object," is presupposed

in the question; but we desire to be told, in the answer to it, what

is the universal and secure criterion of the truth of every cognition.

  To know what questions we may reasonably propose is in itself a

strong evidence of sagacity and intelligence. For if a question be

in itself absurd and unsusceptible of a rational answer, it is

attended with the danger- not to mention the shame that falls upon the

person who proposes it- of seducing the unguarded listener into making

absurd answers, and we are presented with the ridiculous spectacle

of one (as the ancients said) "milking the he-goat, and the other

holding a sieve."

  If truth consists in the accordance of a cognition with its

object, this object must be, ipso facto, distinguished from all

others; for a cognition is false if it does not accord with the object

to which it relates, although it contains something which may be

affirmed of other objects. Now an universal criterion of truth would

be that which is valid for all cognitions, without distinction of

their objects. But it is evident that since, in the case of such a

criterion, we make abstraction of all the content of a cognition (that

is, of all relation to its object), and truth relates precisely to

this content, it must be utterly absurd to ask for a mark of the truth

of this content of cognition; and that, accordingly, a sufficient, and

at the same time universal, test of truth cannot possibly be found. As

we have already termed the content of a cognition its matter, we shall

say: "Of the truth of our cognitions in respect of their matter, no

universal test can be demanded, because such a demand is

self-contradictory."

  On the other hand, with regard to our cognition in respect of its

mere form (excluding all content), it is equally manifest that

logic, in so far as it exhibits the universal and necessary laws of

the understanding, must in these very laws present us with criteria of

truth. Whatever contradicts these rules is false, because thereby

the understanding is made to contradict its own universal laws of

thought; that is, to contradict itself. These criteria, however, apply

solely to the form of truth, that is, of thought in general, and in so

far they are perfectly accurate, yet not sufficient. For although a

cognition may be perfectly accurate as to logical form, that is, not

self-contradictory, it is notwithstanding quite possible that it may

not stand in agreement with its object. Consequently, the merely

logical criterion of truth, namely, the accordance of a cognition with

the universal and formal laws of understanding and reason, is

nothing more than the conditio sine qua non, or negative condition

of all truth. Farther than this logic cannot go, and the error which

depends not on the form, but on the content of the cognition, it has

no test to discover.

  General logic, then, resolves the whole formal business of

understanding and reason into its elements, and exhibits them as

principles of all logical judging of our cognitions. This part of

logic may, therefore, be called analytic, and is at least the negative

test of truth, because all cognitions must first of an be estimated

and tried according to these laws before we proceed to investigate

them in respect of their content, in order to discover whether they

contain positive truth in regard to their object. Because, however,

the mere form of a cognition, accurately as it may accord with logical

laws, is insufficient to supply us with material (objective) truth, no

one, by means of logic alone, can venture to predicate anything of

or decide concerning objects, unless he has obtained, independently of

logic, well-grounded information about them, in order afterwards to

examine, according to logical laws, into the use and connection, in

a cohering whole, of that information, or, what is still better,

merely to test it by them. Notwithstanding, there lies so seductive

a charm in the possession of a specious art like this- an art which

gives to all our cognitions the form of the understanding, although

with respect to the content thereof we may be sadly deficient- that

general logic, which is merely a canon of judgement, has been employed

as an organon for the actual production, or rather for the semblance

of production, of objective assertions, and has thus been grossly

misapplied. Now general logic, in its assumed character of organon, is

called dialectic.

  Different as are the significations in which the ancients used

this term for a science or an art, we may safely infer, from their

actual employment of it, that with them it was nothing else than a

logic of illusion- a sophistical art for giving ignorance, nay, even

intentional sophistries, the colouring of truth, in which the

thoroughness of procedure which logic requires was imitated, and their

topic employed to cloak the empty pretensions. Now it may be taken

as a safe and useful warning, that general logic, considered as an

organon, must always be a logic of illusion, that is, be

dialectical, for, as it teaches us nothing whatever respecting the

content of our cognitions, but merely the formal conditions of their

accordance with the understanding, which do not relate to and are

quite indifferent in respect of objects, any attempt to employ it as

an instrument (organon) in order to extend and enlarge the range of

our knowledge must end in mere prating; any one being able to maintain

or oppose, with some appearance of truth, any single assertion

whatever.

  Such instruction is quite unbecoming the dignity of philosophy.

For these reasons we have chosen to denominate this part of logic

dialectic, in the sense of a critique of dialectical illusion, and

we wish the term to be so understood in this place.



  IV. Of the Division of Transcendental Logic into Transcendental

      Analytic and Dialectic.



  In transcendental logic we isolate the understanding (as in

transcendental aesthetic the sensibility) and select from our

cognition merely that part of thought which has its origin in the

understanding alone. The exercise of this pure cognition, however,

depends upon this as its condition, that objects to which it may be

applied be given to us in intuition, for without intuition the whole

of our cognition is without objects, and is therefore quite void. That

part of transcendental logic, then, which treats of the elements of

pure cognition of the understanding, and of the principles without

which no object at all can be thought, is transcendental analytic, and

at the same time a logic of truth. For no cognition can contradict it,

without losing at the same time all content, that is, losing all

reference to an object, and therefore all truth. But because we are

very easily seduced into employing these pure cognitions and

principles of the understanding by themselves, and that even beyond

the boundaries of experience, which yet is the only source whence we

can obtain matter (objects) on which those pure conceptions may be

employed- understanding runs the risk of making, by means of empty

sophisms, a material and objective use of the mere formal principles

of the pure understanding, and of passing judgements on objects

without distinction- objects which are not given to us, nay, perhaps

cannot be given to us in any way. Now, as it ought properly to be only

a canon for judging of the empirical use of the understanding, this

kind of logic is misused when we seek to employ it as an organon of

the universal and unlimited exercise of the understanding, and attempt

with the pure understanding alone to judge synthetically, affirm,

and determine respecting objects in general. In this case the exercise

of the pure understanding becomes dialectical. The second part of

our transcendental logic must therefore be a critique of dialectical

illusion, and this critique we shall term transcendental dialectic-

not meaning it as an art of producing dogmatically such illusion (an

art which is unfortunately too current among the practitioners of

metaphysical juggling), but as a critique of understanding and

reason in regard to their hyperphysical use. This critique will expose

the groundless nature of the pretensions of these two faculties, and

invalidate their claims to the discovery and enlargement of our

cognitions merely by means of transcendental principles, and show that

the proper employment of these faculties is to test the judgements

made by the pure understanding, and to guard it from sophistical

delusion.

             Transcendental Logic. FIRST DIVISION.



                  TRANSCENDENTAL ANALYTIC.



                            SS I.



  Transcendental analytic is the dissection of the whole of our a

priori knowledge into the elements of the pure cognition of the

understanding. In order to effect our purpose, it is necessary: (1)

That the conceptions be pure and not empirical; (2) That they belong

not to intuition and sensibility, but to thought and understanding;

(3) That they be elementary conceptions, and as such, quite

different from deduced or compound conceptions; (4) That our table

of these elementary conceptions be complete, and fill up the whole

sphere of the pure understanding. Now this completeness of a science

cannot be accepted with confidence on the guarantee of a mere estimate

of its existence in an aggregate formed only by means of repeated

experiments and attempts. The completeness which we require is

possible only by means of an idea of the totality of the a priori

cognition of the understanding, and through the thereby determined

division of the conceptions which form the said whole; consequently,

only by means of their connection in a system. Pure understanding

distinguishes itself not merely from everything empirical, but also

completely from all sensibility. It is a unity self-subsistent,

self-sufficient, and not to be enlarged by any additions from without.

Hence the sum of its cognition constitutes a system to be determined

by and comprised under an idea; and the completeness and

articulation of this system can at the same time serve as a test of

the correctness and genuineness of all the parts of cognition that

belong to it. The whole of this part of transcendental logic

consists of two books, of which the one contains the conceptions,

and the other the principles of pure understanding.

                          BOOK I.



                  Analytic of Conceptions. SS 2



  By the term Analytic of Conceptions, I do not understand the

analysis of these, or the usual process in philosophical

investigations of dissecting the conceptions which present themselves,

according to their content, and so making them clear; but I mean the

hitherto little attempted dissection of the faculty of understanding

itself, in order to investigate the possibility of conceptions a

priori, by looking for them in the understanding alone, as their

birthplace, and analysing the pure use of this faculty. For this is

the proper duty of a transcendental philosophy; what remains is the

logical treatment of the conceptions in philosophy in general. We

shall therefore follow up the pure conceptions even to their germs and

beginnings in the human understanding, in which they lie, until they

are developed on occasions presented by experience, and, freed by

the same understanding from the empirical conditions attaching to

them, are set forth in their unalloyed purity.

  CHAPTER I. Of the Transcendental Clue to the Discovery of all Pure

             Conceptions of the Understanding.



                    Introductory. SS 3



  When we call into play a faculty of cognition, different conceptions

manifest themselves according to the different circumstances, and make

known this faculty, and assemble themselves into a more or less

extensive collection, according to the time or penetration that has

been applied to the consideration of them. Where this process,

conducted as it is mechanically, so to speak, will end, cannot be

determined with certainty. Besides, the conceptions which we

discover in this haphazard manner present themselves by no means in

order and systematic unity, but are at last coupled together only

according to resemblances to each other, and arranged in series,

according to the quantity of their content, from the simpler to the

more complex- series which are anything but systematic, though not

altogether without a certain kind of method in their construction.

  Transcendental philosophy has the advantage, and moreover the

duty, of searching for its conceptions according to a principle;

because these conceptions spring pure and unmixed out of the

understanding as an absolute unity, and therefore must be connected

with each other according to one conception or idea. A connection of

this kind, however, furnishes us with a ready prepared rule, by

which its proper place may be assigned to every pure conception of the

understanding, and the completeness of the system of all be determined

a priori- both which would otherwise have been dependent on mere

choice or chance.



  SECTION 1. Of defined above Use of understanding in General. SS 4



  The understanding was defined above only negatively, as a

non-sensuous faculty of cognition. Now, independently of

sensibility, we cannot possibly have any intuition; consequently,

the understanding is no faculty of intuition. But besides intuition

there is no other mode of cognition, except through conceptions;

consequently, the cognition of every, at least of every human,

understanding is a cognition through conceptions- not intuitive, but

discursive. All intuitions, as sensuous, depend on affections;

conceptions, therefore, upon functions. By the word function I

understand the unity of the act of arranging diverse representations

under one common representation. Conceptions, then, are based on the

spontaneity of thought, as sensuous intuitions are on the

receptivity of impressions. Now, the understanding cannot make any

other use of these conceptions than to judge by means of them. As no

representation, except an intuition, relates immediately to its

object, a conception never relates immediately to an object, but

only to some other representation thereof, be that an intuition or

itself a conception. A judgement, therefore, is the mediate

cognition of an object, consequently the representation of a

representation of it. In every judgement there is a conception which

applies to, and is valid for many other conceptions, and which among

these comprehends also a given representation, this last being

immediately connected with an object. For example, in the judgement-

"All bodies are divisible," our conception of divisible applies to

various other conceptions; among these, however, it is here

particularly applied to the conception of body, and this conception of

body relates to certain phenomena which occur to us. These objects,

therefore, are mediately represented by the conception of

divisibility. All judgements, accordingly, are functions of unity in

our representations, inasmuch as, instead of an immediate, a higher

representation, which comprises this and various others, is used for

our cognition of the object, and thereby many possible cognitions

are collected into one. But we can reduce all acts of the

understanding to judgements, so that understanding may be

represented as the faculty of judging. For it is, according to what

has been said above, a faculty of thought. Now thought is cognition by

means of conceptions. But conceptions, as predicates of possible

judgements, relate to some representation of a yet undetermined

object. Thus the conception of body indicates something- for

example, metal- which can be cognized by means of that conception.

It is therefore a conception, for the reason alone that other

representations are contained under it, by means of which it can

relate to objects. It is therefore the predicate to a possible

judgement; for example: "Every metal is a body." All the functions

of the understanding therefore can be discovered, when we can

completely exhibit the functions of unity in judgements. And that this

may be effected very easily, the following section will show.



  SECTION II. Of the Logical Function of the Understanding in

              Judgements. SS 5



  If we abstract all the content of a judgement, and consider only the

intellectual form thereof, we find that the function of thought in a

judgement can be brought under four heads, of which each contains

three momenta. These may be conveniently represented in the

following table:



                                    1

                         Quantity of judgements

                                Universal

                                Particular

                                Singular



                      2                           3

                    Quality                   Relation

                  Affirmative                Categorical

                  Negative                   Hypothetical

                  Infinite                   Disjunctive



                                    4

                                 Modality

                               Problematical

                               Assertorical

                               Apodeictical



  As this division appears to differ in some, though not essential

points, from the usual technique of logicians, the following

observations, for the prevention of otherwise possible

misunderstanding, will not be without their use.

  1. Logicians say, with justice, that in the use of judgements in

syllogisms, singular judgements may be treated like universal ones.

For, precisely because a singular judgement has no extent at all,

its predicate cannot refer to a part of that which is contained in the

conception of the subject and be excluded from the rest. The predicate

is valid for the whole conception just as if it were a general

conception, and had extent, to the whole of which the predicate

applied. On the other hand, let us compare a singular with a general

judgement, merely as a cognition, in regard to quantity. The

singular judgement relates to the general one, as unity to infinity,

and is therefore in itself essentially different. Thus, if we estimate

a singular judgement (judicium singulare) not merely according to

its intrinsic validity as a judgement, but also as a cognition

generally, according to its quantity in comparison with that of

other cognitions, it is then entirely different from a general

judgement (judicium commune), and in a complete table of the momenta

of thought deserves a separate place- though, indeed, this would not

be necessary in a logic limited merely to the consideration of the use

of judgements in reference to each other.

  2. In like manner, in transcendental logic, infinite must be

distinguished from affirmative judgements, although in general logic

they are rightly enough classed under affirmative. General logic

abstracts all content of the predicate (though it be negative), and

only considers whether the said predicate be affirmed or denied of the

subject. But transcendental logic considers also the worth or

content of this logical affirmation- an affirmation by means of a

merely negative predicate, and inquires how much the sum total of

our cognition gains by this affirmation. For example, if I say of

the soul, "It is not mortal"- by this negative judgement I should at

least ward off error. Now, by the proposition, "The soul is not

mortal," I have, in respect of the logical form, really affirmed,

inasmuch as I thereby place the soul in the unlimited sphere of

immortal beings. Now, because of the whole sphere of possible

existences, the mortal occupies one part, and the immortal the

other, neither more nor less is affirmed by the proposition than

that the soul is one among the infinite multitude of things which

remain over, when I take away the whole mortal part. But by this

proceeding we accomplish only this much, that the infinite sphere of

all possible existences is in so far limited that the mortal is

excluded from it, and the soul is placed in the remaining part of

the extent of this sphere. But this part remains, notwithstanding this

exception, infinite, and more and more parts may be taken away from

the whole sphere, without in the slightest degree thereby augmenting

or affirmatively determining our conception of the soul. These

judgements, therefore, infinite in respect of their logical extent,

are, in respect of the content of their cognition, merely

limitative; and are consequently entitled to a place in our

transcendental table of all the momenta of thought in judgements,

because the function of the understanding exercised by them may

perhaps be of importance in the field of its pure a priori cognition.

  3. All relations of thought in judgements are those (a) of the

predicate to the subject; (b) of the principle to its consequence; (c)

of the divided cognition and all the members of the division to each

other. In the first of these three classes, we consider only two

conceptions; in the second, two judgements; in the third, several

judgements in relation to each other. The hypothetical proposition,

"If perfect justice exists, the obstinately wicked are punished,"

contains properly the relation to each other of two propositions,

namely, "Perfect justice exists," and "The obstinately wicked are

punished." Whether these propositions are in themselves true is a

question not here decided. Nothing is cogitated by means of this

judgement except a certain consequence. Finally, the disjunctive

judgement contains a relation of two or more propositions to each

other- a relation not of consequence, but of logical opposition, in so

far as the sphere of the one proposition excludes that of the other.

But it contains at the same time a relation of community, in so far as

all the propositions taken together fill up the sphere of the

cognition. The disjunctive judgement contains, therefore, the relation

of the parts of the whole sphere of a cognition, since the sphere of

each part is a complemental part of the sphere of the other, each

contributing to form the sum total of the divided cognition. Take, for

example, the proposition, "The world exists either through blind

chance, or through internal necessity, or through an external

cause." Each of these propositions embraces a part of the sphere of

our possible cognition as to the existence of a world; all of them

taken together, the whole sphere. To take the cognition out of one

of these spheres, is equivalent to placing it in one of the others;

and, on the other hand, to place it in one sphere is equivalent to

taking it out of the rest. There is, therefore, in a disjunctive

judgement a certain community of cognitions, which consists in this,

that they mutually exclude each other, yet thereby determine, as a

whole, the true cognition, inasmuch as, taken together, they make up

the complete content of a particular given cognition. And this is

all that I find necessary, for the sake of what follows, to remark

in this place.

  4. The modality of judgements is a quite peculiar function, with

this distinguishing characteristic, that it contributes nothing to the

content of a judgement (for besides quantity, quality, and relation,

there is nothing more that constitutes the content of a judgement),

but concerns itself only with the value of the copula in relation to

thought in general. Problematical judgements are those in which the

affirmation or negation is accepted as merely possible (ad libitum).

In the assertorical, we regard the proposition as real (true); in

the apodeictical, we look on it as necessary.* Thus the two judgements

(antecedens et consequens), the relation of which constitutes a

hypothetical judgement, likewise those (the members of the division)

in whose reciprocity the disjunctive consists, are only problematical.

In the example above given the proposition, "There exists perfect

justice," is not stated assertorically, but as an ad libitum

judgement, which someone may choose to adopt, and the consequence

alone is assertorical. Hence such judgements may be obviously false,

and yet, taken problematically, be conditions of our cognition of

the truth. Thus the proposition, "The world exists only by blind

chance," is in the disjunctive judgement of problematical import only:

that is to say, one may accept it for the moment, and it helps us

(like the indication of the wrong road among all the roads that one

can take) to find out the true proposition. The problematical

proposition is, therefore, that which expresses only logical

possibility (which is not objective); that is, it expresses a free

choice to admit the validity of such a proposition- a merely arbitrary

reception of it into the understanding. The assertorical speaks of

logical reality or truth; as, for example, in a hypothetical

syllogism, the antecedens presents itself in a problematical form in

the major, in an assertorical form in the minor, and it shows that the

proposition is in harmony with the laws of the understanding. The

apodeictical proposition cogitates the assertorical as determined by

these very laws of the understanding, consequently as affirming a

priori, and in this manner it expresses logical necessity. Now because

all is here gradually incorporated with the understanding- inasmuch as

in the first place we judge problematically; then accept

assertorically our judgement as true; lastly, affirm it as inseparably

united with the understanding, that is, as necessary and apodeictical-

we may safely reckon these three functions of modality as so many

momenta of thought.



  *Just as if thought were in the first instance a function of the

understanding; in the second, of judgement; in the third, of reason. A

remark which will be explained in the sequel.



  SECTION III. Of the Pure Conceptions of the Understanding, or

               Categories. SS 6



  General logic, as has been repeatedly said, makes abstraction of all

content of cognition, and expects to receive representations from some

other quarter, in order, by means of analysis, to convert them into

conceptions. On the contrary, transcendental logic has lying before it

the manifold content of a priori sensibility, which transcendental

aesthetic presents to it in order to give matter to the pure

conceptions of the understanding, without which transcendental logic

would have no content, and be therefore utterly void. Now space and

time contain an infinite diversity of determinations of pure a

priori intuition, but are nevertheless the condition of the mind's

receptivity, under which alone it can obtain representations of

objects, and which, consequently, must always affect the conception of

these objects. But the spontaneity of thought requires that this

diversity be examined after a certain manner, received into the

mind, and connected, in order afterwards to form a cognition out of

it. This Process I call synthesis.

  By the word synthesis, in its most general signification, I

understand the process of joining different representations to each

other and of comprehending their diversity in one cognition. This

synthesis is pure when the diversity is not given empirically but a

priori (as that in space and time). Our representations must be

given previously to any analysis of them; and no conceptions can

arise, quoad their content, analytically. But the synthesis of a

diversity (be it given a priori or empirically) is the first requisite

for the production of a cognition, which in its beginning, indeed, may

be crude and confused, and therefore in need of analysis- still,

synthesis is that by which alone the elements of our cognitions are

collected and united into a certain content, consequently it is the

first thing on which we must fix our attention, if we wish to

investigate the origin of our knowledge.

  Synthesis, generally speaking, is, as we shall afterwards see, the

mere operation of the imagination- a blind but indispensable

function of the soul, without which we should have no cognition

whatever, but of the working of which we are seldom even conscious.

But to reduce this synthesis to conceptions is a function of the

understanding, by means of which we attain to cognition, in the proper

meaning of the term.

  Pure synthesis, represented generally, gives us the pure

conception of the understanding. But by this pure synthesis, I mean

that which rests upon a basis of a priori synthetical unity. Thus, our

numeration (and this is more observable in large numbers) is a

synthesis according to conceptions, because it takes place according

to a common basis of unity (for example, the decade). By means of this

conception, therefore, the unity in the synthesis of the manifold

becomes necessary.

  By means of analysis different representations are brought under one

conception- an operation of which general logic treats. On the other

hand, the duty of transcendental logic is to reduce to conceptions,

not representations, but the pure synthesis of representations. The

first thing which must be given to us for the sake of the a priori

cognition of all objects, is the diversity of the pure intuition;

the synthesis of this diversity by means of the imagination is the

second; but this gives, as yet, no cognition. The conceptions which

give unity to this pure synthesis, and which consist solely in the

representation of this necessary synthetical unity, furnish the

third requisite for the cognition of an object, and these

conceptions are given by the understanding.

  The same function which gives unity to the different

representation in a judgement, gives also unity to the mere

synthesis of different representations in an intuition; and this unity

we call the pure conception of the understanding. Thus, the same

understanding, and by the same operations, whereby in conceptions,

by means of analytical unity, it produced the logical form of a

judgement, introduces, by means of the synthetical unity of the

manifold in intuition, a transcendental content into its

representations, on which account they are called pure conceptions

of the understanding, and they apply a priori to objects, a result not

within the power of general logic.

  In this manner, there arise exactly so many pure conceptions of

the understanding, applying a priori to objects of intuition in

general, as there are logical functions in all possible judgements.

For there is no other function or faculty existing in the

understanding besides those enumerated in that table. These

conceptions we shall, with Aristotle, call categories, our purpose

being originally identical with his, notwithstanding the great

difference in the execution.



                     TABLE OF THE CATEGORIES



                    1                         2



              Of Quantity                Of Quality

              Unity                      Reality

              Plurality                  Negation

              Totality                   Limitation



                           3

                      Of Relation

   Of Inherence and Subsistence (substantia et accidens)

   Of Causality and Dependence (cause and effect)

   Of Community (reciprocity between the agent and patient)



                           4

                     Of Modality

              Possibility - Impossibility

              Existence - Non-existence

              Necessity - Contingence



  This, then, is a catalogue of all the originally pure conceptions of

the synthesis which the understanding contains a priori, and these

conceptions alone entitle it to be called a pure understanding;

inasmuch as only by them it can render the manifold of intuition

conceivable, in other words, think an object of intuition. This

division is made systematically from a common principle, namely the

faculty of judgement (which is just the same as the power of thought),

and has not arisen rhapsodically from a search at haphazard after pure

conceptions, respecting the full number of which we never could be

certain, inasmuch as we employ induction alone in our search,

without considering that in this way we can never understand wherefore

precisely these conceptions, and none others, abide in the pure

understanding. It was a design worthy of an acute thinker like

Aristotle, to search for these fundamental conceptions. Destitute,

however, of any guiding principle, he picked them up just as they

occurred to him, and at first hunted out ten, which he called

categories (predicaments). Afterwards be believed that he had

discovered five others, which were added under the name of post

predicaments. But his catalogue still remained defective. Besides,

there are to be found among them some of the modes of pure sensibility

(quando, ubi, situs, also prius, simul), and likewise an empirical

conception (motus)- which can by no means belong to this

genealogical register of the pure understanding. Moreover, there are

deduced conceptions (actio, passio) enumerated among the original

conceptions, and, of the latter, some are entirely wanting.

  With regard to these, it is to be remarked, that the categories,

as the true primitive conceptions of the pure understanding, have also

their pure deduced conceptions, which, in a complete system of

transcendental philosophy, must by no means be passed over; though

in a merely critical essay we must be contented with the simple

mention of the fact.

  Let it be allowed me to call these pure, but deduced conceptions

of the understanding, the predicables of the pure understanding, in

contradistinction to predicaments. If we are in possession of the

original and primitive, the deduced and subsidiary conceptions can

easily be added, and the genealogical tree of the understanding

completely delineated. As my present aim is not to set forth a

complete system, but merely the principles of one, I reserve this task

for another time. It may be easily executed by any one who will

refer to the ontological manuals, and subordinate to the category of

causality, for example, the predicables of force, action, passion;

to that of community, those of presence and resistance; to the

categories of modality, those of origination, extinction, change;

and so with the rest. The categories combined with the modes of pure

sensibility, or with one another, afford a great number of deduced a

priori conceptions; a complete enumeration of which would be a

useful and not unpleasant, but in this place a perfectly

dispensable, occupation.

  I purposely omit the definitions of the categories in this treatise.

I shall analyse these conceptions only so far as is necessary for

the doctrine of method, which is to form a part of this critique. In a

system of pure reason, definitions of them would be with justice

demanded of me, but to give them here would only bide from our view

the main aim of our investigation, at the same time raising doubts and

objections, the consideration of which, without injustice to our

main purpose, may be very well postponed till another opportunity.

Meanwhile, it ought to be sufficiently clear, from the little we

have already said on this subject, that the formation of a complete

vocabulary of pure conceptions, accompanied by all the requisite

explanations, is not only a possible, but an easy undertaking. The

compartments already exist; it is only necessary to fill them up;

and a systematic topic like the present, indicates with perfect

precision the proper place to which each conception belongs, while

it readily points out any that have not yet been filled up.



                           SS 7



  Our table of the categories suggests considerations of some

importance, which may perhaps have significant results in regard to

the scientific form of all rational cognitions. For, that this table

is useful in the theoretical part of philosophy, nay, indispensable

for the sketching of the complete plan of a science, so far as that

science rests upon conceptions a priori, and for dividing it

mathematically, according to fixed principles, is most manifest from

the fact that it contains all the elementary conceptions of the

understanding, nay, even the form of a system of these in the

understanding itself, and consequently indicates all the momenta,

and also the internal arrangement of a projected speculative

science, as I have elsewhere shown.* Here follow some of these

observations.



  *In the Metaphysical Principles of Natural Science.



  I. This table, which contains four classes of conceptions of the

understanding, may, in the first instance, be divided into two

classes, the first of which relates to objects of intuition- pure as

well as empirical; the second, to the existence of these objects,

either in relation to one another, or to the understanding.

  The former of these classes of categories I would entitle the

mathematical, and the latter the dynamical categories. The former,

as we see, has no correlates; these are only to be found in the second

class. This difference must have a ground in the nature of the human

understanding.

  II. The number of the categories in each class is always the same,

namely, three- a fact which also demands some consideration, because

in all other cases division a priori through conceptions is

necessarily dichotomy. It is to be added, that the third category in

each triad always arises from the combination of the second with the

first.

  Thus totality is nothing else but plurality contemplated as unity;

limitation is merely reality conjoined with negation; community is the

causality of a substance, reciprocally determining, and determined

by other substances; and finally, necessity is nothing but

existence, which is given through the possibility itself. Let it not

be supposed, however, that the third category is merely a deduced, and

not a primitive conception of the pure understanding. For the

conjunction of the first and second, in order to produce the third

conception, requires a particular function of the understanding, which

is by no means identical with those which are exercised in the first

and second. Thus, the conception of a number (which belongs to the

category of totality) is not always possible, where the conceptions of

multitude and unity exist (for example, in the representation of the

infinite). Or, if I conjoin the conception of a cause with that of a

substance, it does not follow that the conception of influence, that

is, how one substance can be the cause of something in another

substance, will be understood from that. Thus it is evident that a

particular act of the understanding is here necessary; and so in the

other instances.

  III. With respect to one category, namely, that of community,

which is found in the third class, it is not so easy as with the

others to detect its accordance with the form of the disjunctive

judgement which corresponds to it in the table of the logical

functions.

  In order to assure ourselves of this accordance, we must observe

that in every disjunctive judgement, the sphere of the judgement (that

is, the complex of all that is contained in it) is represented as a

whole divided into parts; and, since one part cannot be contained in

the other, they are cogitated as co-ordinated with, not subordinated

to each other, so that they do not determine each other

unilaterally, as in a linear series, but reciprocally, as in an

aggregate- (if one member of the division is posited, all the rest are

excluded; and conversely).

  Now a like connection is cogitated in a whole of things; for one

thing is not subordinated, as effect, to another as cause of its

existence, but, on the contrary, is co-ordinated contemporaneously and

reciprocally, as a cause in relation to the determination of the

others (for example, in a body- the parts of which mutually attract

and repel each other). And this is an entirely different kind of

connection from that which we find in the mere relation of the cause

to the effect (the principle to the consequence), for in such a

connection the consequence does not in its turn determine the

principle, and therefore does not constitute, with the latter, a

whole- just as the Creator does not with the world make up a whole.

The process of understanding by which it represents to itself the

sphere of a divided conception, is employed also when we think of a

thing as divisible; and in the same manner as the members of the

division in the former exclude one another, and yet are connected in

one sphere, so the understanding represents to itself the parts of the

latter, as having- each of them- an existence (as substances),

independently of the others, and yet as united in one whole.



                          SS 8



  In the transcendental philosophy of the ancients there exists one

more leading division, which contains pure conceptions of the

understanding, and which, although not numbered among the

categories, ought, according to them, as conceptions a priori, to be

valid of objects. But in this case they would augment the number of

the categories; which cannot be. These are set forth in the

proposition, so renowned among the schoolmen- "Quodlibet ens est UNUM,

VERUM, BONUM." Now, though the inferences from this principle were

mere tautological propositions, and though it is allowed only by

courtesy to retain a place in modern metaphysics, yet a thought

which maintained itself for such a length of time, however empty it

seems to be, deserves an investigation of its origin, and justifies

the conjecture that it must be grounded in some law of the

understanding, which, as is often the case, has only been

erroneously interpreted. These pretended transcendental predicates

are, in fact, nothing but logical requisites and criteria of all

cognition of objects, and they employ, as the basis for this

cognition, the categories of quantity, namely, unity, plurality, and

totality. But these, which must be taken as material conditions,

that is, as belonging to the possibility of things themselves, they

employed merely in a formal signification, as belonging to the logical

requisites of all cognition, and yet most unguardedly changed these

criteria of thought into properties of objects, as things in

themselves. Now, in every cognition of an object, there is unity of

conception, which may be called qualitative unity, so far as by this

term we understand only the unity in our connection of the manifold;

for example, unity of the theme in a play, an oration, or a story.

Secondly, there is truth in respect of the deductions from it. The

more true deductions we have from a given conception, the more

criteria of its objective reality. This we might call the

qualitative plurality of characteristic marks, which belong to a

conception as to a common foundation, but are not cogitated as a

quantity in it. Thirdly, there is perfection- which consists in

this, that the plurality falls back upon the unity of the

conception, and accords completely with that conception and with no

other. This we may denominate qualitative completeness. Hence it is

evident that these logical criteria of the possibility of cognition

are merely the three categories of quantity modified and transformed

to suit an unauthorized manner of applying them. That is to say, the

three categories, in which the unity in the production of the

quantum must be homogeneous throughout, are transformed solely with

a view to the connection of heterogeneous parts of cognition in one

act of consciousness, by means of the quality of the cognition,

which is the principle of that connection. Thus the criterion of the

possibility of a conception (not of its object) is the definition of

it, in which the unity of the conception, the truth of all that may be

immediately deduced from it, and finally, the completeness of what has

been thus deduced, constitute the requisites for the reproduction of

the whole conception. Thus also, the criterion or test of an

hypothesis is the intelligibility of the received principle of

explanation, or its unity (without help from any subsidiary

hypothesis)- the truth of our deductions from it (consistency with

each other and with experience)- and lastly, the completeness of the

principle of the explanation of these deductions, which refer to

neither more nor less than what was admitted in the hypothesis,

restoring analytically and a posteriori, what was cogitated

synthetically and a priori. By the conceptions, therefore, of unity,

truth, and perfection, we have made no addition to the

transcendental table of the categories, which is complete without

them. We have, on the contrary, merely employed the three categories

of quantity, setting aside their application to objects of experience,

as general logical laws of the consistency of cognition with itself.

   CHAPTER II Of the Deduction of the Pure Conceptions of the

                      Understanding.



   SECTION I Of the Principles of a Transcendental Deduction

                     in general. SS 9



  Teachers of jurisprudence, when speaking of rights and claims,

distinguish in a cause the question of right (quid juris) from the

question of fact (quid facti), and while they demand proof of both,

they give to the proof of the former, which goes to establish right or

claim in law, the name of deduction. Now we make use of a great number

of empirical conceptions, without opposition from any one; and

consider ourselves, even without any attempt at deduction, justified

in attaching to them a sense, and a supposititious signification,

because we have always experience at hand to demonstrate their

objective reality. There exist also, however, usurped conceptions,

such as fortune, fate, which circulate with almost universal

indulgence, and yet are occasionally challenged by the question, "quid

juris?" In such cases, we have great difficulty in discovering any

deduction for these terms, inasmuch as we cannot produce any

manifest ground of right, either from experience or from reason, on

which the claim to employ them can be founded.

  Among the many conceptions, which make up the very variegated web of

human cognition, some are destined for pure use a priori,

independent of all experience; and their title to be so employed

always requires a deduction, inasmuch as, to justify such use of them,

proofs from experience are not sufficient; but it is necessary to know

how these conceptions can apply to objects without being derived

from experience. I term, therefore, an examination of the manner in

which conceptions can apply a priori to objects, the transcendental

deduction of conceptions, and I distinguish it from the empirical

deduction, which indicates the mode in which conception is obtained

through experience and reflection thereon; consequently, does not

concern itself with the right, but only with the fact of our obtaining

conceptions in such and such a manner. We have already seen that we

are in possession of two perfectly different kinds of conceptions,

which nevertheless agree with each other in this, that they both apply

to objects completely a priori. These are the conceptions of space and

time as forms of sensibility, and the categories as pure conceptions

of the understanding. To attempt an empirical deduction of either of

these classes would be labour in vain, because the distinguishing

characteristic of their nature consists in this, that they apply to

their objects, without having borrowed anything from experience

towards the representation of them. Consequently, if a deduction of

these conceptions is necessary, it must always be transcendental.

  Meanwhile, with respect to these conceptions, as with respect to all

our cognition, we certainly may discover in experience, if not the

principle of their possibility, yet the occasioning causes of their

production. It will be found that the impressions of sense give the

first occasion for bringing into action the whole faculty of

cognition, and for the production of experience, which contains two

very dissimilar elements, namely, a matter for cognition, given by the

senses, and a certain form for the arrangement of this matter, arising

out of the inner fountain of pure intuition and thought; and these, on

occasion given by sensuous impressions, are called into exercise and

produce conceptions. Such an investigation into the first efforts of

our faculty of cognition to mount from particular perceptions to

general conceptions is undoubtedly of great utility; and we have to

thank the celebrated Locke for having first opened the way for this

inquiry. But a deduction of the pure a priori conceptions of course

never can be made in this way, seeing that, in regard to their

future employment, which must be entirely independent of experience,

they must have a far different certificate of birth to show from

that of a descent from experience. This attempted physiological

derivation, which cannot properly be called deduction, because it

relates merely to a quaestio facti, I shall entitle an explanation

of the possession of a pure cognition. It is therefore manifest that

there can only be a transcendental deduction of these conceptions

and by no means an empirical one; also, that all attempts at an

empirical deduction, in regard to pure a priori conceptions, are vain,

and can only be made by one who does not understand the altogether

peculiar nature of these cognitions.

  But although it is admitted that the only possible deduction of pure

a priori cognition is a transcendental deduction, it is not, for

that reason, perfectly manifest that such a deduction is absolutely

necessary. We have already traced to their sources the conceptions

of space and time, by means of a transcendental deduction, and we have

explained and determined their objective validity a priori.

Geometry, nevertheless, advances steadily and securely in the province

of pure a priori cognitions, without needing to ask from philosophy

any certificate as to the pure and legitimate origin of its

fundamental conception of space. But the use of the conception in this

science extends only to the external world of sense, the pure form

of the intuition of which is space; and in this world, therefore,

all geometrical cognition, because it is founded upon a priori

intuition, possesses immediate evidence, and the objects of this

cognition are given a priori (as regards their form) in intuition by

and through the cognition itself. With the pure conceptions of

understanding, on the contrary, commences the absolute necessity of

seeking a transcendental deduction, not only of these conceptions

themselves, but likewise of space, because, inasmuch as they make

affirmations concerning objects not by means of the predicates of

intuition and sensibility, but of pure thought a priori, they apply to

objects without any of the conditions of sensibility. Besides, not

being founded on experience, they are not presented with any object in

a priori intuition upon which, antecedently to experience, they

might base their synthesis. Hence results, not only doubt as to the

objective validity and proper limits of their use, but that even our

conception of space is rendered equivocal; inasmuch as we are very

ready with the aid of the categories, to carry the use of this

conception beyond the conditions of sensuous intuition- and, for

this reason, we have already found a transcendental deduction of it

needful. The reader, then, must be quite convinced of the absolute

necessity of a transcendental deduction, before taking a single step

in the field of pure reason; because otherwise he goes to work

blindly, and after he has wondered about in all directions, returns to

the state of utter ignorance from which he started. He ought,

moreover, clearly to recognize beforehand the unavoidable difficulties

in his undertaking, so that he may not afterwards complain of the

obscurity in which the subject itself is deeply involved, or become

too soon impatient of the obstacles in his path; because we have a

choice of only two things- either at once to give up all pretensions

to knowledge beyond the limits of possible experience, or to bring

this critical investigation to completion.

  We have been able, with very little trouble, to make it

comprehensible how the conceptions of space and time, although a

priori cognitions, must necessarily apply to external objects, and

render a synthetical cognition of these possible, independently of all

experience. For inasmuch as only by means of such pure form of

sensibility an object can appear to us, that is, be an object of

empirical intuition, space and time are pure intuitions, which contain

a priori the condition of the possibility of objects as phenomena, and

an a priori synthesis in these intuitions possesses objective

validity.

  On the other hand, the categories of the understanding do not

represent the conditions under which objects are given to us in

intuition; objects can consequently appear to us without necessarily

connecting themselves with these, and consequently without any

necessity binding on the understanding to contain a priori the

conditions of these objects. Thus we find ourselves involved in a

difficulty which did not present itself in the sphere of

sensibility, that is to say, we cannot discover how the subjective

conditions of thought can have objective validity, in other words, can

become conditions of the possibility of all cognition of objects;

for phenomena may certainly be given to us in intuition without any

help from the functions of the understanding. Let us take, for

example, the conception of cause, which indicates a peculiar kind of

synthesis, namely, that with something, A, something entirely

different, B, is connected according to a law. It is not a priori

manifest why phenomena should contain anything of this kind (we are of

course debarred from appealing for proof to experience, for the

objective validity of this conception must be demonstrated a

priori), and it hence remains doubtful a priori, whether such a

conception be not quite void and without any corresponding object

among phenomena. For that objects of sensuous intuition must

correspond to the formal conditions of sensibility existing a priori

in the mind is quite evident, from the fact that without these they

could not be objects for us; but that they must also correspond to the

conditions which understanding requires for the synthetical unity of

thought is an assertion, the grounds for which are not so easily to be

discovered. For phenomena might be so constituted as not to correspond

to the conditions of the unity of thought; and all things might lie in

such confusion that, for example, nothing could be met with in the

sphere of phenomena to suggest a law of synthesis, and so correspond

to the conception of cause and effect; so that this conception would

be quite void, null, and without significance. Phenomena would

nevertheless continue to present objects to our intuition; for mere

intuition  does not in any respect stand in need of the functions of

thought.

  If we thought to free ourselves from the labour of these

investigations by saying: "Experience is constantly offering us

examples of the relation of cause and effect in phenomena, and

presents us with abundant opportunity of abstracting the conception of

cause, and so at the same time of corroborating the objective validity

of this conception"; we should in this case be overlooking the fact,

that the conception of cause cannot arise in this way at all; that, on

the contrary, it must either have an a priori basis in the,

understanding, or be rejected as a mere chimera. For this conception

demands that something, A, should be of such a nature that something

else, B, should follow from it necessarily, and according to an

absolutely universal law. We may certainly collect from phenomena a

law, according to which this or that usually happens, but the

element of necessity is not to be found in it. Hence it is evident

that to the synthesis of cause and effect belongs a dignity, which

is utterly wanting in any empirical synthesis; for it is no mere

mechanical synthesis, by means of addition, but a dynamical one;

that is to say, the effect is not to be cogitated as merely annexed to

the cause, but as posited by and through the cause, and resulting from

it. The strict universality of this law never can be a

characteristic of empirical laws, which obtain through induction

only a comparative universality, that is, an extended range of

practical application. But the pure conceptions of the understanding

would entirely lose all their peculiar character, if we treated them

merely as the productions of experience.



     Transition to the Transcendental Deduction of the

                    Categories. SS 10



  There are only two possible ways in which synthetical representation

and its objects can coincide with and relate necessarily to each

other, and, as it were, meet together. Either the object alone makes

the representation possible, or the representation alone makes the

object possible. In the former case, the relation between them is only

empirical, and an a priori representation is impossible. And this is

the case with phenomena, as regards that in them which is referable to

mere sensation. In the latter case- although representation alone (for

of its causality, by means of the will, we do not here speak) does not

produce the object as to its existence, it must nevertheless be a

priori determinative in regard to the object, if it is only by means

of the representation that we can cognize anything as an object. Now

there are only two conditions of the possibility of a cognition of

objects; firstly, intuition, by means of which the object, though only

as phenomenon, is given; secondly, conception, by means of which the

object which corresponds to this intuition is thought. But it is

evident from what has been said on aesthetic that the first condition,

under which alone objects can be intuited, must in fact exist, as a

formal basis for them, a priori in the mind. With this formal

condition of sensibility, therefore, all phenomena necessarily

correspond, because it is only through it that they can be phenomena

at all; that is, can be empirically intuited and given. Now the

question is whether there do not exist, a priori in the mind,

conceptions of understanding also, as conditions under which alone

something, if not intuited, is yet thought as object. If this question

be answered in the affirmative, it follows that all empirical

cognition of objects is necessarily conformable to such conceptions,

since, if they are not presupposed, it is impossible that anything can

be an object of experience. Now all experience contains, besides the

intuition of the senses through which an object is given, a conception

also of an object that is given in intuition. Accordingly, conceptions

of objects in general must lie as a priori conditions at the

foundation of all empirical cognition; and consequently, the objective

validity of the categories, as a priori conceptions, will rest upon

this, that experience (as far as regards the form of thought) is

possible only by their means. For in that case they apply

necessarily and a priori to objects of experience, because only

through them can an object of experience be thought.

  The whole aim of the transcendental deduction of all a priori

conceptions is to show that these conceptions are a priori

conditions of the possibility of all experience. Conceptions which

afford us the objective foundation of the possibility of experience

are for that very reason necessary. But the analysis of the

experiences in which they are met with is not deduction, but only an

illustration of them, because from experience they could never

derive the attribute of necessity. Without their original

applicability and relation to all possible experience, in which all

objects of cognition present themselves, the relation of the

categories to objects, of whatever nature, would be quite

incomprehensible.

  The celebrated Locke, for want of due reflection on these points,

and because he met with pure conceptions of the understanding in

experience, sought also to deduce them from experience, and yet

proceeded so inconsequently as to attempt, with their aid, to arrive

it cognitions which lie far beyond the limits of all experience. David

Hume perceived that, to render this possible, it was necessary that

the conceptions should have an a priori origin. But as he could not

explain how it was possible that conceptions which are not connected

with each other in the understanding must nevertheless be thought as

necessarily connected in the object- and it never occurred to him that

the understanding itself might, perhaps, by means of these

conceptions, be the author of the experience in which its objects were

presented to it- he was forced to drive these conceptions from

experience, that is, from a subjective necessity arising from repeated

association of experiences erroneously considered to be objective-

in one word, from habit. But he proceeded with perfect consequence and

declared it to be impossible, with such conceptions and the principles

arising from them, to overstep the limits of experience. The empirical

derivation, however, which both of these philosophers attributed to

these conceptions, cannot possibly be reconciled with the fact that we

do possess scientific a priori cognitions, namely, those of pure

mathematics and general physics.

  The former of these two celebrated men opened a wide door to

extravagance- (for if reason has once undoubted right on its side,

it will not allow itself to be confined to set limits, by vague

recommendations of moderation); the latter gave himself up entirely to

scepticism- a natural consequence, after having discovered, as he

thought, that the faculty of cognition was not trustworthy. We now

intend to make a trial whether it be not possible safely to conduct

reason between these two rocks, to assign her determinate limits,

and yet leave open for her the entire sphere of her legitimate

activity.

  I shall merely premise an explanation of what the categories are.

They are conceptions of an object in general, by means of which its

intuition is contemplated as determined in relation to one of the

logical functions of judgement. The following will make this plain.

The function of the categorical judgement is that of the relation of

subject to predicate; for example, in the proposition: "All bodies are

divisible." But in regard to the merely logical use of the

understanding, it still remains undetermined to which Of these two

conceptions belongs the function Of subject and to which that of

predicate. For we could also say: "Some divisible is a body." But

the category of substance, when the conception of a body is brought

under it, determines that; and its empirical intuition in experience

must be contemplated always as subject and never as mere predicate.

And so with all the other categories.



  SECTION II Transcendental Deduction of the pure Conceptions of

                   the Understanding. SS 11



  Of the Possibility of a Conjunction of the manifold representations

                       given by Sense.



  The manifold content in our representations can be given in an

intuition which is merely sensuous- in other words, is nothing but

susceptibility; and the form of this intuition can exist a priori in

our faculty of representation, without being anything else but the

mode in which the subject is affected. But the conjunction

(conjunctio) of a manifold in intuition never can be given us by the

senses; it cannot therefore be contained in the pure form of

sensuous intuition, for it is a spontaneous act of the faculty of

representation. And as we must, to distinguish it from sensibility,

entitle this faculty understanding; so all conjunction whether

conscious or unconscious, be it of the manifold in intuition, sensuous

or non-sensuous, or of several conceptions- is an act of the

understanding. To this act we shall give the general appellation of

synthesis, thereby to indicate, at the same time, that we cannot

represent anything as conjoined in the object without having

previously conjoined it ourselves. Of all mental notions, that of

conjunction is the only one which cannot be given through objects, but

can be originated only by the subject itself, because it is an act

of its purely spontaneous activity. The reader will easily enough

perceive that the possibility of conjunction must be grounded in the

very nature of this act, and that it must be equally valid for all

conjunction, and that analysis, which appears to be its contrary,

must, nevertheless, always presuppose it; for where the

understanding has not previously conjoined, it cannot dissect or

analyse, because only as conjoined by it, must that which is to be

analysed have been given to our faculty of representation.

  But the conception of conjunction includes, besides the conception

of the manifold and of the synthesis of it, that of the unity of it

also. Conjunction is the representation of the synthetical unity of

the manifold.* This idea of unity, therefore, cannot arise out of that

of conjunction; much rather does that idea, by combining itself with

the representation of the manifold, render the conception of

conjunction possible. This unity, which a priori precedes all

conceptions of conjunction, is not the category of unity (SS 6); for

all the categories are based upon logical functions of judgement,

and in these functions we already have conjunction, and consequently

unity of given conceptions. It is therefore evident that the

category of unity presupposes conjunction. We must therefore look

still higher for this unity (as qualitative, SS 8), in that, namely,

which contains the ground of the unity of diverse conceptions in

judgements, the ground, consequently, of the possibility of the

existence of the understanding, even in regard to its logical use.



  *Whether the representations are in themselves identical, and

consequently whether one can be thought analytically by means of and

through the other, is a question which we need not at present

consider. Our Consciousness of the one, when we speak of the manifold,

is always distinguishable from our consciousness of the other; and

it is only respecting the synthesis of this (possible) consciousness

that we here treat.



    Of the Originally Synthetical Unity of Apperception. SS 12



  The "I think" must accompany all my representations, for otherwise

something would be represented in me which could not be thought; in

other words, the representation would either be impossible, or at

least be, in relation to me, nothing. That representation which can be

given previously to all thought is called intuition. All the diversity

or manifold content of intuition, has, therefore, a necessary relation

to the 'I think," in the subject in which this diversity is found. But

this representation, "I think," is an act of spontaneity; that is to

say, it cannot be regarded as belonging to mere sensibility. I call it

pure apperception, in order to distinguish it from empirical; or

primitive apperception, because it is self-consciousness which, whilst

it gives birth to the representation" I think," must necessarily be

capable of accompanying all our representations. It is in all acts

of consciousness one and the same, and unaccompanied by it, no

representation can exist for me. The unity of this apperception I call

the transcendental unity of self-consciousness, in order to indicate

the possibility of a priori cognition arising from it. For the

manifold representations which are given in an intuition would not all

of them be my representations, if they did not all belong to one

self-consciousness, that is, as my representations (even although I am

not conscious of them as such), they must conform to the condition

under which alone they can exist together in a common

self-consciousness, because otherwise they would not all without

exception belong to me. From this primitive conjunction follow many

important results.

  For example, this universal identity of the apperception of the

manifold given in intuition contains a synthesis of representations

and is possible only by means of the consciousness of this

synthesis. For the empirical consciousness which accompanies different

representations is in itself fragmentary and disunited, and without

relation to the identity of the subject. This relation, then, does not

exist because I accompany every representation with consciousness, but

because I join one representation to another, and am conscious of

the synthesis of them. Consequently, only because I can connect a

variety of given representations in one consciousness, is it

possible that I can represent to myself the identity of

consciousness in these representations; in other words, the analytical

unity of apperception is possible only under the presupposition of a

synthetical unity.* The thought, "These representations given in

intuition belong all of them to me," is accordingly just the same

as, "I unite them in one self-consciousness, or can at least so

unite them"; and although this thought is not itself the consciousness

of the synthesis of representations, it presupposes the possibility of

it; that is to say, for the reason alone that I can comprehend the

variety of my representations in one consciousness, do I call them

my representations, for otherwise I must have as many-coloured and

various a self as are the representations of which I am conscious.

Synthetical unity of the manifold in intuitions, as given a priori, is

therefore the foundation of the identity of apperception itself, which

antecedes a priori all determinate thought. But the conjunction of

representations into a conception is not to be found in objects

themselves, nor can it be, as it were, borrowed from them and taken up

into the understanding by perception, but it is on the contrary an

operation of the understanding itself, which is nothing more than

the faculty of conjoining a priori and of bringing the variety of

given representations under the unity of apperception. This

principle is the highest in all human cognition.



  *All general conceptions- as such- depend, for their existence, on

the analytical unity of consciousness. For example, when I think of

red in general, I thereby think to myself a property which (as a

characteristic mark) can be discovered somewhere, or can be united

with other representations; consequently, it is only by means of a

forethought possible synthetical unity that I can think to myself

the analytical. A representation which is cogitated as common to

different representations, is regarded as belonging to such as,

besides this common representation, contain something different;

consequently it must be previously thought in synthetical unity with

other although only possible representations, before I can think in it

the analytical unity of consciousness which makes it a conceptas

communis. And thus the synthetical unity of apperception is the

highest point with which we must connect every operation of the

understanding, even the whole of logic, and after it our

transcendental philosophy; indeed, this faculty is the understanding

itself.



  This fundamental principle of the necessary unity of apperception is

indeed an identical, and therefore analytical, proposition; but it

nevertheless explains the necessity for a synthesis of the manifold

given in an intuition, without which the identity of

self-consciousness would be incogitable. For the ego, as a simple

representation, presents us with no manifold content; only in

intuition, which is quite different from the representation ego, can

it be given us, and by means of conjunction it is cogitated in one

self-consciousness. An understanding, in which all the manifold should

be given by means of consciousness itself, would be intuitive; our

understanding can only think and must look for its intuition to sense.

I am, therefore, conscious of my identical self, in relation to all

the variety of representations given to me in an intuition, because

I call all of them my representations. In other words, I am

conscious myself of a necessary a priori synthesis of my

representations, which is called the original synthetical unity of

apperception, under which rank all the representations presented to

me, but that only by means of a synthesis.



    The Principle of the Synthetical Unity of Apperception

         is the highest Principle of all exercise of

                  the Understanding. SS 13



  The supreme principle of the possibility of all intuition in

relation to sensibility was, according to our transcendental

aesthetic, that all the manifold in intuition be subject to the formal

conditions of space and time. The supreme principle of the possibility

of it in relation to the understanding is that all the manifold in

it be subject to conditions of the originally synthetical unity or

apperception.* To the former of these two principles are subject all

the various representations of intuition, in so far as they are

given to us; to the latter, in so far as they must be capable of

conjunction in one consciousness; for without this nothing can be

thought or cognized, because the given representations would not

have in common the act Of the apperception "I think" and therefore

could not be connected in one self-consciousness.



  *Space and time, and all portions thereof, are intuitions;

consequently are, with a manifold for their content, single

representations. (See the Transcendental Aesthetic.) Consequently,

they are not pure conceptions, by means of which the same

consciousness is found in a great number of representations; but, on

the contrary, they are many representations contained in one, the

consciousness of which is, so to speak, compounded. The unity of

consciousness is nevertheless synthetical and, therefore, primitive.

From this peculiar character of consciousness follow many important

consequences. (See SS 21.)



  Understanding is, to speak generally, the faculty Of cognitions.

These consist in the determined relation of given representation to an

object. But an object is that, in the conception of which the manifold

in a given intuition is united. Now all union of representations

requires unity of consciousness in the synthesis of them.

Consequently, it is the unity of consciousness alone that

constitutes the possibility of representations relating to an

object, and therefore of their objective validity, and of their

becoming cognitions, and consequently, the possibility of the

existence of the understanding itself.

  The first pure cognition of understanding, then, upon which is

founded all its other exercise, and which is at the same time

perfectly independent of all conditions of mere sensuous intuition, is

the principle of the original synthetical unity of apperception.

Thus the mere form of external sensuous intuition, namely, space,

affords us, per se, no cognition; it merely contributes the manifold

in a priori intuition to a possible cognition. But, in order to

cognize something in space (for example, a line), I must draw it,

and thus produce synthetically a determined conjunction of the given

manifold, so that the unity of this act is at the same time the

unity of consciousness (in the conception of a line), and by this

means alone is an object (a determinate space) cognized. The

synthetical unity of consciousness is, therefore, an objective

condition of all cognition, which I do not merely require in order

to cognize an object, but to which every intuition must necessarily be

subject, in order to become an object for me; because in any other

way, and without this synthesis, the manifold in intuition could not

be united in one consciousness.

  This proposition is, as already said, itself analytical, although it

constitutes the synthetical unity, the condition of all thought; for

it states nothing more than that all my representations in any given

intuition must be subject to the condition which alone enables me to

connect them, as my representation with the identical self, and so

to unite them synthetically in one apperception, by means of the

general expression, "I think."

  But this principle is not to be regarded as a principle for every

possible understanding, but only for the understanding by means of

whose pure apperception in the thought I am, no manifold content is

given. The understanding or mind which contained the manifold in

intuition, in and through the act itself of its own

self-consciousness, in other words, an understanding by and in the

representation of which the objects of the representation should at

the same time exist, would not require a special act of synthesis of

the manifold as the condition of the unity of its consciousness, an

act of which the human understanding, which thinks only and cannot

intuite, has absolute need. But this principle is the first

principle of all the operations of our understanding, so that we

cannot form the least conception of any other possible

understanding, either of one such as should be itself intuition, or

possess a sensuous intuition, but with forms different from those of

space and time.



      What Objective Unity of Self-consciousness is. SS 14



  It is by means of the transcendental unity of apperception that

all the manifold, given in an intuition is united into a conception of

the object. On this account it is called objective, and must be

distinguished from the subjective unity of consciousness, which is a

determination of the internal sense, by means of which the said

manifold in intuition is given empirically to be so united. Whether

I can be empirically conscious of the manifold as coexistent or as

successive, depends upon circumstances, or empirical conditions. Hence

the empirical unity of consciousness by means of association of

representations, itself relates to a phenomenal world and is wholly

contingent. On the contrary, the pure form of intuition in time,

merely as an intuition, which contains a given manifold, is subject to

the original unity of consciousness, and that solely by means of the

necessary relation of the manifold in intuition to the "I think,"

consequently by means of the pure synthesis of the understanding,

which lies a priori at the foundation of all empirical synthesis.

The transcendental unity of apperception is alone objectively valid;

the empirical which we do not consider in this essay, and which is

merely a unity deduced from the former under given conditions in

concreto, possesses only subjective validity. One person connects

the notion conveyed in a word with one thing, another with another

thing; and the unity of consciousness in that which is empirical,

is, in relation to that which is given by experience, not

necessarily and universally valid.



     The Logical Form of all Judgements consists in the Objective

            Unity of Apperception of the Conceptions

                     contained therein. SS 15



  I could never satisfy myself with the definition which logicians

give of a judgement. It is, according to them, the representation of a

relation between two conceptions. I shall not dwell here on the

faultiness of this definition, in that it suits only for categorical

and not for hypothetical or disjunctive judgements, these latter

containing a relation not of conceptions but of judgements themselves-

a blunder from which many evil results have followed.* It is more

important for our present purpose to observe, that this definition

does not determine in what the said relation consists.



  *The tedious doctrine of the four syllogistic figures concerns

only categorical syllogisms; and although it is nothing more than an

artifice by surreptitiously introducing immediate conclusions

(consequentiae immediatae) among the premises of a pure syllogism,

to give ism' give rise to an appearance of more modes of drawing a

conclusion than that in the first figure, the artifice would not

have had much success, had not its authors succeeded in bringing

categorical judgements into exclusive respect, as those to which all

others must be referred- a doctrine, however, which, according to SS

5, is utterly false.



  But if I investigate more closely the relation of given cognitions

in every judgement, and distinguish it, as belonging to the

understanding, from the relation which is produced according to laws

of the reproductive imagination (which has only subjective

validity), I find that judgement is nothing but the mode of bringing

given cognitions under the objective unit of apperception. This is

plain from our use of the term of relation is in judgements, in

order to distinguish the objective unity of given representations from

the subjective unity. For this term indicates the relation of these

representations to the original apperception, and also their necessary

unity, even although the judgement is empirical, therefore contingent,

as in the judgement: "All bodies are heavy." I do not mean by this,

that these representations do necessarily belong to each other in

empirical intuition, but that by means of the necessary unity of

appreciation they belong to each other in the synthesis of intuitions,

that is to say, they belong to each other according to principles of

the objective determination of all our representations, in so far as

cognition can arise from them, these principles being all deduced from

the main principle of the transcendental unity of apperception. In

this way alone can there arise from this relation a judgement, that

is, a relation which has objective validity, and is perfectly distinct

from that relation of the very same representations which has only

subjective validity- a relation, to wit, which is produced according

to laws of association. According to these laws, I could only say:

"When I hold in my hand or carry a body, I feel an impression of

weight"; but I could not say: "It, the body, is heavy"; for this is

tantamount to saying both these representations are conjoined in the

object, that is, without distinction as to the condition of the

subject, and do not merely stand together in my perception, however

frequently the perceptive act may be repeated.



    All Sensuous Intuitions are subject to the Categories, as

      Conditions under which alone the manifold Content of

        them can be united in one Consciousness. SS 16



  The manifold content given in a sensuous intuition comes necessarily

under the original synthetical unity of apperception, because

thereby alone is the unity of intuition possible (SS 13). But that act

of the understanding, by which the manifold content of given

representations (whether intuitions or conceptions) is brought under

one apperception, is the logical function of judgements (SS 15). All

the manifold, therefore, in so far as it is given in one empirical

intuition, is determined in relation to one of the logical functions

of judgement, by means of which it is brought into union in one

consciousness. Now the categories are nothing else than these

functions of judgement so far as the manifold in a given intuition

is determined in relation to them (SS 9). Consequently, the manifold

in a given intuition is necessarily subject to the categories of the

understanding.



                    Observation. SS 17



  The manifold in an intuition, which I call mine, is represented by

means of the synthesis of the understanding, as belonging to the

necessary unity of self-consciousness, and this takes place by means

of the category.* The category indicates accordingly that the

empirical consciousness of a given manifold in an intuition is subject

to a pure self-consciousness a priori, in the same manner as an

empirical intuition is subject to a pure sensuous intuition, which

is also a priori. In the above proposition, then, lies the beginning

of a deduction of the pure conceptions of the understanding. Now, as

the categories have their origin in the understanding alone,

independently of sensibility, I must in my deduction make

abstraction of the mode in which the manifold of an empirical

intuition is given, in order to fix my attention exclusively on the

unity which is brought by the understanding into the intuition by

means of the category. In what follows (SS 22), it will be shown, from

the mode in which the empirical intuition is given in the faculty of

sensibility, that the unity which belongs to it is no other than

that which the category (according to SS 16) imposes on the manifold

in a given intuition, and thus, its a priori validity in regard to all

objects of sense being established, the purpose of our deduction

will be fully attained.



  *The proof of this rests on the represented unity of intuition, by

means of which an object is given, and which always includes in itself

a synthesis of the manifold to be intuited, and also the relation of

this latter to unity of apperception.



  But there is one thing in the above demonstration of which I could

not make abstraction, namely, that the manifold to be intuited must be

given previously to the synthesis of the understanding, and

independently of it. How this takes place remains here undetermined.

For if I cogitate an understanding which was itself intuitive (as, for

example, a divine understanding which should not represent given

objects, but by whose representation the objects themselves should

be given or produced), the categories would possess no significance in

relation to such a faculty of cognition. They are merely rules for

an understanding, whose whole power consists in thought, that is, in

the act of submitting the synthesis of the manifold which is presented

to it in intuition from a very different quarter, to the unity of

apperception; a faculty, therefore, which cognizes nothing per se, but

only connects and arranges the material of cognition, the intuition,

namely, which must be presented to it by means of the object. But to

show reasons for this peculiar character of our understandings, that

it produces unity of apperception a priori only by means of

categories, and a certain kind and number thereof, is as impossible as

to explain why we are endowed with precisely so many functions of

judgement and no more, or why time and space are the only forms of our

intuition.



    In Cognition, its Application to Objects of Experience is

    the only legitimate use of the Category. SS 18



  To think an object and to cognize an object are by no means the same

thing. In cognition there are two elements: firstly, the conception,

whereby an object is cogitated (the category); and, secondly, the

intuition, whereby the object is given. For supposing that to the

conception a corresponding intuition could not be given, it would

still be a thought as regards its form, but without any object, and no

cognition of anything would be possible by means of it, inasmuch as,

so far as I knew, there existed and could exist nothing to which my

thought could be applied. Now all intuition possible to us is

sensuous; consequently, our thought of an object by means of a pure

conception of the understanding, can become cognition for us only in

so far as this conception is applied to objects of the senses.

Sensuous intuition is either pure intuition (space and time) or

empirical intuition- of that which is immediately represented in space

and time by means of sensation as real. Through the determination of

pure intuition we obtain a priori cognitions of objects, as in

mathematics, but only as regards their form as phenomena; whether

there can exist things which must be intuited in this form is not

thereby established. All mathematical conceptions, therefore, are

not per se cognition, except in so far as we presuppose that there

exist things which can only be represented conformably to the form

of our pure sensuous intuition. But things in space and time are given

only in so far as they are perceptions (representations accompanied

with sensation), therefore only by empirical representation.

Consequently the pure conceptions of the understanding, even when they

are applied to intuitions a priori (as in mathematics), produce

cognition only in so far as these (and therefore the conceptions of

the understanding by means of them) can be applied to empirical

intuitions. Consequently the categories do not, even by means of

pure intuition afford us any cognition of things; they can only do

so in so far as they can be applied to empirical intuition. That is to

say, the, categories serve only to render empirical cognition

possible. But this is what we call experience. Consequently, in

cognition, their application to objects of experience is the only

legitimate use of the categories.



                           SS 19



  The foregoing proposition is of the utmost importance, for it

determines the limits of the exercise of the pure conceptions of the

understanding in regard to objects, just as transcendental aesthetic

determined the limits of the exercise of the pure form of our sensuous

intuition. Space and time, as conditions of the possibility of the

presentation of objects to us, are valid no further than for objects

of sense, consequently, only for experience. Beyond these limits

they represent to us nothing, for they belong only to sense, and

have no reality apart from it. The pure conceptions of the

understanding are free from this limitation, and extend to objects

of intuition in general, be the intuition like or unlike to ours,

provided only it be sensuous, and not intellectual. But this extension

of conceptions beyond the range of our intuition is of no advantage;

for they are then mere empty conceptions of objects, as to the

possibility or impossibility of the existence of which they furnish us

with no means of discovery. They are mere forms of thought, without

objective reality, because we have no intuition to which the

synthetical unity of apperception, which alone the categories contain,

could be applied, for the purpose of determining an object. Our

sensuous and empirical intuition can alone give them significance

and meaning.

  If, then, we suppose an object of a non-sensuous intuition to be

given we can in that case represent it by all those predicates which

are implied in the presupposition that nothing appertaining to

sensuous intuition belongs to it; for example, that it is not

extended, or in space; that its duration is not time; that in it no

change (the effect of the determinations in time) is to be met with,

and so on. But it is no proper knowledge if I merely indicate what the

intuition of the object is not, without being able to say what is

contained in it, for I have not shown the possibility of an object

to which my pure conception of understanding could be applicable,

because I have not been able to furnish any intuition corresponding to

it, but am only able to say that our intuition is not valid for it.

But the most important point is this, that to a something of this kind

not one category can be found applicable. Take, for example, the

conception of substance, that is, something that can exist as subject,

but never as mere predicate; in regard to this conception I am quite

ignorant whether there can really be anything to correspond to such

a determination of thought, if empirical intuition did not afford me

the occasion for its application. But of this more in the sequel.



     Of the Application of the Categories to Objects of the

                  Senses in general. SS 20



  The pure conceptions of the understanding apply to objects of

intuition in general, through the understanding alone, whether the

intuition be our own or some other, provided only it be sensuous,

but are, for this very reason, mere forms of thought, by means of

which alone no determined object can be cognized. The synthesis or

conjunction of the manifold in these conceptions relates, we have

said, only to the unity of apperception, and is for this reason the

ground of the possibility of a priori cognition, in so far as this

cognition is dependent on the understanding. This synthesis is,

therefore, not merely transcendental, but also purely intellectual.

But because a certain form of sensuous intuition exists in the mind

a priori which rests on the receptivity of the representative

faculty (sensibility), the understanding, as a spontaneity, is able to

determine the internal sense by means of the diversity of given

representations, conformably to the synthetical unity of apperception,

and thus to cogitate the synthetical unity of the apperception of

the manifold of sensuous intuition a priori, as the condition to which

must necessarily be submitted all objects of human intuition. And in

this manner the categories as mere forms of thought receive

objective reality, that is, application to objects which are given

to us in intuition, but that only as phenomena, for it is only of

phenomena that we are capable of a priori intuition.

  This synthesis of the manifold of sensuous intuition, which is

possible and necessary a priori, may be called figurative (synthesis

speciosa), in contradistinction to that which is cogitated in the mere

category in regard to the manifold of an intuition in general, and

is called connection or conjunction of the understanding (synthesis

intellectualis). Both are transcendental, not merely because they

themselves precede a priori all experience, but also because they form

the basis for the possibility of other cognition a priori.

  But the figurative synthesis, when it has relation only to the

originally synthetical unity of apperception, that is to the

transcendental unity cogitated in the categories, must, to be

distinguished from the purely intellectual conjunction, be entitled

the transcendental synthesis of imagination. Imagination is the

faculty of representing an object even without its presence in

intuition. Now, as all our intuition is sensuous, imagination, by

reason of the subjective condition under which alone it can give a

corresponding intuition to the conceptions of the understanding,

belongs to sensibility. But in so far as the synthesis of the

imagination is an act of spontaneity, which is determinative, and not,

like sense, merely determinable, and which is consequently able to

determine sense a priori, according to its form, conformably to the

unity of apperception, in so far is the imagination a faculty of

determining sensibility a priori, and its synthesis of intuitions

according to the categories must be the transcendental synthesis of

the imagination. It is an operation of the understanding on

sensibility, and the first application of the understanding to objects

of possible intuition, and at the same time the basis for the exercise

of the other functions of that faculty. As figurative, it is

distinguished from the merely intellectual synthesis, which is

produced by the understanding alone, without the aid of imagination.

Now, in so far as imagination is spontaneity, I sometimes call it also

the productive imagination, and distinguish it from the

reproductive, the synthesis of which is subject entirely to

empirical laws, those of association, namely, and which, therefore,

contributes nothing to the explanation of the possibility of a

priori cognition, and for this reason belongs not to transcendental

philosophy, but to psychology.



  We have now arrived at the proper place for explaining the paradox

which must have struck every one in our exposition of the internal

sense (SS 6), namely- how this sense represents us to our own

consciousness, only as we appear to ourselves, not as we are in

ourselves, because, to wit, we intuite ourselves only as we are

inwardly affected. Now this appears to be contradictory, inasmuch as

we thus stand in a passive relation to ourselves; and therefore in the

systems of psychology, the internal sense is commonly held to be one

with the faculty of apperception, while we, on the contrary, carefully

distinguish them.

  That which determines the internal sense is the understanding, and

its original power of conjoining the manifold of intuition, that is,

of bringing this under an apperception (upon which rests the

possibility of the understanding itself). Now, as the human

understanding is not in itself a faculty of intuition, and is unable

to exercise such a power, in order to conjoin, as it were, the

manifold of its own intuition, the synthesis of understanding is,

considered per se, nothing but the unity of action, of which, as such,

it is self-conscious, even apart from sensibility, by which, moreover,

it is able to determine our internal sense in respect of the

manifold which may be presented to it according to the form of

sensuous intuition. Thus, under the name of a transcendental synthesis

of imagination, the understanding exercises an activity upon the

passive subject, whose faculty it is; and so we are right in saying

that the internal sense is affected thereby. Apperception and its

synthetical unity are by no means one and the same with the internal

sense. The former, as the source of all our synthetical conjunction,

applies, under the name of the categories, to the manifold of

intuition in general, prior to all sensuous intuition of objects.

The internal sense, on the contrary, contains merely the form of

intuition, but without any synthetical conjunction of the manifold

therein, and consequently does not contain any determined intuition,

which is possible only through consciousness of the determination of

the manifold by the transcendental act of the imagination (synthetical

influence of the understanding on the internal sense), which I have

named figurative synthesis.

  This we can indeed always perceive in ourselves. We cannot

cogitate a geometrical line without drawing it in thought, nor a

circle without describing it, nor represent the three dimensions of

space without drawing three lines from the same point perpendicular to

one another. We cannot even cogitate time, unless, in drawing a

straight line (which is to serve as the external figurative

representation of time), we fix our attention on the act of the

synthesis of the manifold, whereby we determine successively the

internal sense, and thus attend also to the succession of this

determination. Motion as an act of the subject (not as a determination

of an object),* consequently the synthesis of the manifold in space,

if we make abstraction of space and attend merely to the act by

which we determine the internal sense according to its form, is that

which produces the conception of succession. The understanding,

therefore, does by no means find in the internal sense any such

synthesis of the manifold, but produces it, in that it affects this

sense. At the same time, how "I who think" is distinct from the "I"

which intuites itself (other modes of intuition being cogitable as

at least possible), and yet one and the same with this latter as the

same subject; how, therefore, I am able to say: "I, as an intelligence

and thinking subject, cognize myself as an object thought, so far as I

am, moreover, given to myself in intuition- only, like other

phenomena, not as I am in myself, and as considered by the

understanding, but merely as I appear"- is a question that has in it

neither more nor less difficulty than the question- "How can I be an

object to myself?" or this- "How I can be an object of my own

intuition and internal perceptions?" But that such must be the fact,

if we admit that space is merely a pure form of the phenomena of

external sense, can be clearly proved by the consideration that we

cannot represent time, which is not an object of external intuition,

in any other way than under the image of a line, which we draw in

thought, a mode of representation without which we could not cognize

the unity of its dimension, and also that we are necessitated to

take our determination of periods of time, or of points of time, for

all our internal perceptions from the changes which we perceive in

outward things. It follows that we must arrange the determinations

of the internal sense, as phenomena in time, exactly in the same

manner as we arrange those of the external senses in space. And

consequently, if we grant, respecting this latter, that by means of

them we know objects only in so far as we are affected externally,

we must also confess, with regard to the internal sense, that by means

of it we intuite ourselves only as we are internally affected by

ourselves; in other words, as regards internal intuition, we cognize

our own subject only as phenomenon, and not as it is in itself.*[2]



  *Motion of an object in space does not belong to a pure science,

consequently not to geometry; because, that a thing is movable

cannot be known a priori, but only from experience. But motion,

considered as the description of a space, is a pure act of the

successive synthesis of the manifold in external intuition by means of

productive imagination, and belongs not only to geometry, but even

to transcendental philosophy.

  *[2] I do not see why so much difficulty should be found in

admitting that our internal sense is affected by ourselves. Every

act of attention exemplifies it. In such an act the understanding

determines the internal sense by the synthetical conjunction which

it cogitates, conformably to the internal intuition which

corresponds to the manifold in the synthesis of the understanding. How

much the mind is usually affected thereby every one will be able to

perceive in himself.



                          SS 21



  On the other hand, in the transcendental synthesis of the manifold

content of representations, consequently in the synthetical unity of

apperception, I am conscious of myself, not as I appear to myself, nor

as I am in myself, but only that "I am." This representation is a

thought, not an intuition. Now, as in order to cognize ourselves, in

addition to the act of thinking, which subjects the manifold of

every possible intuition to the unity of apperception, there is

necessary a determinate mode of intuition, whereby this manifold is

given; although my own existence is certainly not mere phenomenon

(much less mere illusion), the determination of my existence* Can only

take place conformably to the form of the internal sense, according to

the particular mode in which the manifold which I conjoin is given

in internal intuition, and I have therefore no knowledge of myself

as I am, but merely as I appear to myself. The consciousness of self

is thus very far from a knowledge of self, in which I do not use the

categories, whereby I cogitate an object, by means of the

conjunction of the manifold in one apperception. In the same way as

I require, for the sake of the cognition of an object distinct from

myself, not only the thought of an object in general (in the

category), but also an intuition by which to determine that general

conception, in the same way do I require, in order to the cognition of

myself, not only the consciousness of myself or the thought that I

think myself, but in addition an intuition of the manifold in

myself, by which to determine this thought. It is true that I exist as

an intelligence which is conscious only of its faculty of

conjunction or synthesis, but subjected in relation to the manifold

which this intelligence has to conjoin to a limitative conjunction

called the internal sense. My intelligence (that is, I) can render

that conjunction or synthesis perceptible only according to the

relations of time, which are quite beyond the proper sphere of the

conceptions of the understanding and consequently cognize itself in

respect to an intuition (which cannot possibly be intellectual, nor

given by the understanding), only as it appears to itself, and not

as it would cognize itself, if its intuition were intellectual.



  *The "I think" expresses the act of determining my own existence. My

existence is thus already given by the act of consciousness; but the

mode in which I must determine my existence, that is, the mode in

which I must place the manifold belonging to my existence, is not

thereby given. For this purpose intuition of self is required, and

this intuition possesses a form given a priori, namely, time, which is

sensuous, and belongs to our receptivity of the determinable. Now,

as I do not possess another intuition of self which gives the

determining in me (of the spontaneity of which I am conscious),

prior to the act of determination, in the same manner as time gives

the determinable, it is clear that I am unable to determine my own

existence as that of a spontaneous being, but I am only able to

represent to myself the spontaneity of my thought, that is, of my

determination, and my existence remains ever determinable in a

purely sensuous manner, that is to say, like the existence of a

phenomenon. But it is because of this spontaneity that I call myself

an intelligence.



      Transcendental Deduction of the universally possible

        employment in experience of the Pure Conceptions

                of the Understanding. SS 22



  In the metaphysical deduction, the a priori origin of categories was

proved by their complete accordance with the general logical of

thought; in the transcendental deduction was exhibited the possibility

of the categories as a priori cognitions of objects of an intuition in

general (SS 16 and 17).At present we are about to explain the

possibility of cognizing, a priori, by means of the categories, all

objects which can possibly be presented to our senses, not, indeed,

according to the form of their intuition, but according to the laws of

their conjunction or synthesis, and thus, as it were, of prescribing

laws to nature and even of rendering nature possible. For if the

categories were inadequate to this task, it would not be evident to us

why everything that is presented to our senses must be subject to

those laws which have an a priori origin in the understanding itself.

  I premise that by the term synthesis of apprehension I understand

the combination of the manifold in an empirical intuition, whereby

perception, that is, empirical consciousness of the intuition (as

phenomenon), is possible.

  We have a priori forms of the external and internal sensuous

intuition in the representations of space and time, and to these

must the synthesis of apprehension of the manifold in a phenomenon

be always comformable, because the synthesis itself can only take

place according to these forms. But space and time are not merely

forms of sensuous intuition, but intuitions themselves (which

contain a manifold), and therefore contain a priori the

determination of the unity of this manifold.* (See the Transcendent

Aesthetic.) Therefore is unity of the synthesis of the manifold

without or within us, consequently also a conjunction to which all

that is to be represented as determined in space or time must

correspond, given a priori along with (not in) these intuitions, as

the condition of the synthesis of all apprehension of them. But this

synthetical unity can be no other than that of the conjunction of

the manifold of a given intuition in general, in a primitive act of

consciousness, according to the categories, but applied to our

sensuous intuition. Consequently all synthesis, whereby alone is

even perception possible, is subject to the categories. And, as

experience is cognition by means of conjoined perceptions, the

categories are conditions of the possibility of experience and are

therefore valid a priori for all objects of experience.



  *Space represented as an object (as geometry really requires it to

be) contains more than the mere form of the intuition; namely, a

combination of the manifold given according to the form of sensibility

into a representation that can be intuited; so that the form of the

intuition gives us merely the manifold, but the formal intuition gives

unity of representation. In the aesthetic, I regarded this unity as

belonging entirely to sensibility, for the purpose of indicating

that it antecedes all conceptions, although it presupposes a synthesis

which does not belong to sense, through which alone, however, all

our conceptions of space and time are possible. For as by means of

this unity alone (the understanding determining the sensibility) space

and time are given as intuitions, it follows that the unity of this

intuition a priori belongs to space and time, and not to the

conception of the understanding (SS 20).



  When, then, for example, I make the empirical intuition of a house

by apprehension of the manifold contained therein into a perception,

the necessary unity of space and of my external sensuous intuition

lies at the foundation of this act, and I, as it were, draw the form

of the house conformably to this synthetical unity of the manifold

in space. But this very synthetical unity remains, even when I

abstract the form of space, and has its seat in the understanding, and

is in fact the category of the synthesis of the homogeneous in an

intuition; that is to say, the category of quantity, to which the

aforesaid synthesis of apprehension, that is, the perception, must

be completely conformable.*



  *In this manner it is proved, that the synthesis of apprehension,

which is empirical, must necessarily be conformable to the synthesis

of apperception, which is intellectual, and contained a priori in

the category. It is one and the same spontaneity which at one time,

under the name of imagination, at another under that of understanding,

produces conjunction in the manifold of intuition.



  To take another example, when I perceive the freezing of water, I

apprehend two states (fluidity and solidity), which, as such, stand

toward each other mutually in a relation of time. But in the time,

which I place as an internal intuition, at the foundation of this

phenomenon, I represent to myself synthetical unity of the manifold,

without which the aforesaid relation could not be given in an

intuition as determined (in regard to the succession of time). Now

this synthetical unity, as the a priori condition under which I

conjoin the manifold of an intuition, is, if I make abstraction of the

permanent form of my internal intuition (that is to say, of time), the

category of cause, by means of which, when applied to my

sensibility, I determine everything that occurs according to relations

of time. Consequently apprehension in such an event, and the event

itself, as far as regards the possibility of its perception, stands

under the conception of the relation of cause and effect: and so in

all other cases.



  Categories are conceptions which prescribe laws a priori to

phenomena, consequently to nature as the complex of all phenomena

(natura materialiter spectata). And now the question arises-

inasmuch as these categories are not derived from nature, and do not

regulate themselves according to her as their model (for in that

case they would be empirical)- how it is conceivable that nature

must regulate herself according to them, in other words, how the

categories can determine a priori the synthesis of the manifold of

nature, and yet not derive their origin from her. The following is the

solution of this enigma.

  It is not in the least more difficult to conceive how the laws of

the phenomena of nature must harmonize with the understanding and with

its a priori form- that is, its faculty of conjoining the manifold-

than it is to understand how the phenomena themselves must

correspond with the a priori form of our sensuous intuition. For

laws do not exist in the phenomena any more than the phenomena exist

as things in themselves. Laws do not exist except by relation to the

subject in which the phenomena inhere, in so far as it possesses

understanding, just as phenomena have no existence except by

relation to the same existing subject in so far as it has senses. To

things as things in themselves, conformability to law must necessarily

belong independently of an understanding to cognize them. But

phenomena are only representations of things which are utterly unknown

in respect to what they are in themselves. But as mere

representations, they stand under no law of conjunction except that

which the conjoining faculty prescribes. Now that which conjoins the

manifold of sensuous intuition is imagination, a mental act to which

understanding contributes unity of intellectual synthesis, and

sensibility, manifoldness of apprehension. Now as all possible

perception depends on the synthesis of apprehension, and this

empirical synthesis itself on the transcendental, consequently on

the categories, it is evident that all possible perceptions, and

therefore everything that can attain to empirical consciousness,

that is, all phenomena of nature, must, as regards their

conjunction, be subject to the categories. And nature (considered

merely as nature in general) is dependent on them. as the original

ground of her necessary conformability to law (as natura formaliter

spectata). But the pure faculty (of the understanding) of

prescribing laws a priori to phenomena by means of mere categories, is

not competent to enounce other or more laws than those on which a

nature in general, as a conformability to law of phenomena of space

and time, depends. Particular laws, inasmuch as they concern

empirically determined phenomena, cannot be entirely deduced from pure

laws, although they all stand under them. Experience must be

superadded in order to know these particular laws; but in regard to

experience in general, and everything that can be cognized as an

object thereof, these a priori laws are our only rule and guide.



       Result of this Deduction of the Conceptions of the

                   Understanding. SS 23



  We cannot think any object except by means of the categories; we

cannot cognize any thought except by means of intuitions corresponding

to these conceptions. Now all our intuitions are sensuous, and our

cognition, in so far as the object of it is given, is empirical. But

empirical cognition is experience; consequently no a priori

cognition is possible for us, except of objects of possible

experience.*



  *Lest my readers should stumble at this assertion, and the

conclusions that may be too rashly drawn from it, I must remind them

that the categories in the act of thought are by no means limited by

the conditions of our sensuous intuition, but have an unbounded sphere

of action. It is only the cognition of the object of thought, the

determining of the object, which requires intuition. In the absence of

intuition, our thought of an object may still have true and useful

consequences in regard to the exercise of reason by the subject. But

as this exercise of reason is not always directed on the determination

of the object, in other words, on cognition thereof, but also on the

determination of the subject and its volition, I do not intend to

treat of it in this place.



  But this cognition, which is limited to objects of experience, is

not for that reason derived entirely, from, experience, but- and

this is asserted of the pure intuitions and the pure conceptions of

the understanding- there are, unquestionably, elements of cognition,

which exist in the mind a priori. Now there are only two ways in which

a necessary harmony of experience with the conceptions of its

objects can be cogitated. Either experience makes these conceptions

possible, or the conceptions make experience possible. The former of

these statements will not bold good with respect to the categories

(nor in regard to pure sensuous intuition), for they are a priori

conceptions, and therefore independent of experience. The assertion of

an empirical origin would attribute to them a sort of generatio

aequivoca. Consequently, nothing remains but to adopt the second

alternative (which presents us with a system, as it were, of the

epigenesis of pure reason), namely, that on the part of the

understanding the categories do contain the grounds of the possibility

of all experience. But with respect to the questions how they make

experience possible, and what are the principles of the possibility

thereof with which they present us in their application to

phenomena, the following section on the transcendental exercise of the

faculty of judgement will inform the reader.

  It is quite possible that someone may propose a species of

preformation-system of pure reason- a middle way between the two- to

wit, that the categories are neither innate and first a priori

principles of cognition, nor derived from experience, but are merely

subjective aptitudes for thought implanted in us contemporaneously

with our existence, which were so ordered and disposed by our Creator,

that their exercise perfectly harmonizes with the laws of nature which

regulate experience. Now, not to mention that with such an

hypothesis it is impossible to say at what point we must stop in the

employment of predetermined aptitudes, the fact that the categories

would in this case entirely lose that character of necessity which

is essentially involved in the very conception of them, is a

conclusive objection to it. The conception of cause, for example,

which expresses the necessity of an effect under a presupposed

condition, would be false, if it rested only upon such an arbitrary

subjective necessity of uniting certain empirical representations

according to such a rule of relation. I could not then say- "The

effect is connected with its cause in the object (that is,

necessarily)," but only, "I am so constituted that I can think this

representation as so connected, and not otherwise." Now this is just

what the sceptic wants. For in this case, all our knowledge, depending

on the supposed objective validity of our judgement, is nothing but

mere illusion; nor would there be wanting people who would deny any

such subjective necessity in respect to themselves, though they must

feel it. At all events, we could not dispute with any one on that

which merely depends on the manner in which his subject is organized.



             Short view of the above Deduction.



  The foregoing deduction is an exposition of the pure conceptions

of the understanding (and with them of all theoretical a priori

cognition), as principles of the possibility of experience, but of

experience as the determination of all phenomena in space and time

in general- of experience, finally, from the principle of the original

synthetical unity of apperception, as the form of the understanding in

relation to time and space as original forms of sensibility.



  I consider the division by paragraphs to be necessary only up to

this point, because we had to treat of the elementary conceptions.

As we now proceed to the exposition of the employment of these, I

shall not designate the chapters in this manner any further.

                         BOOK II.



                 Analytic of Principles.



  General logic is constructed upon a plan which coincides exactly

with the division of the higher faculties of cognition. These are,

understanding, judgement, and reason. This science, accordingly,

treats in its analytic of conceptions, judgements, and conclusions

in exact correspondence with the functions and order of those mental

powers which we include generally under the generic denomination of

understanding.

  As this merely formal logic makes abstraction of all content of

cognition, whether pure or empirical, and occupies itself with the

mere form of thought (discursive cognition), it must contain in its

analytic a canon for reason. For the form of reason has its law,

which, without taking into consideration the particular nature of

the cognition about which it is employed, can be discovered a

priori, by the simple analysis of the action of reason into its

momenta.

  Transcendental logic, limited as it is to a determinate content,

that of pure a priori cognitions, to wit, cannot imitate general logic

in this division. For it is evident that the transcendental employment

of reason is not objectively valid, and therefore does not belong to

the logic of truth (that is, to analytic), but as a logic of illusion,

occupies a particular department in the scholastic system under the

name of transcendental dialectic.

  Understanding and judgement accordingly possess in transcendental

logic a canon of objectively valid, and therefore true exercise, and

are comprehended in the analytical department of that logic. But

reason, in her endeavours to arrive by a priori means at some true

statement concerning objects and to extend cognition beyond the bounds

of possible experience, is altogether dialectic, and her illusory

assertions cannot be constructed into a canon such as an analytic

ought to contain.

  Accordingly, the analytic of principles will be merely a canon for

the faculty of judgement, for the instruction of this faculty in its

application to phenomena of the pure conceptions of the understanding,

which contain the necessary condition for the establishment of a

priori laws. On this account, although the subject of the following

chapters is the especial principles of understanding, I shall make use

of the term Doctrine of the faculty of judgement, in order to define

more particularly my present purpose.



  INTRODUCTION. Of the Transcendental Faculty of judgement in General.



  If understanding in general be defined as the faculty of laws or

rules, the faculty of judgement may be termed the faculty of

subsumption under these rules; that is, of distinguishing whether this

or that does or does not stand under a given rule (casus datae legis).

General logic contains no directions or precepts for the faculty of

judgement, nor can it contain any such. For as it makes abstraction of

all content of cognition, no duty is left for it, except that of

exposing analytically the mere form of cognition in conceptions,

judgements, and conclusions, and of thereby establishing formal

rules for all exercise of the understanding. Now if this logic

wished to give some general direction how we should subsume under

these rules, that is, how we should distinguish whether this or that

did or did not stand under them, this again could not be done

otherwise than by means of a rule. But this rule, precisely because it

is a rule, requires for itself direction from the faculty of

judgement. Thus, it is evident that the understanding is capable of

being instructed by rules, but that the judgement is a peculiar

talent, which does not, and cannot require tuition, but only exercise.

This faculty is therefore the specific quality of the so-called mother

wit, the want of which no scholastic discipline can compensate.

  For although education may furnish, and, as it were, engraft upon

a limited understanding rules borrowed from other minds, yet the power

of employing these rules correctly must belong to the pupil himself;

and no rule which we can prescribe to him with this purpose is, in the

absence or deficiency of this gift of nature, secure from misuse.* A

physician therefore, a judge or a statesman, may have in his head many

admirable pathological, juridical, or political rules, in a degree

that may enable him to be a profound teacher in his particular

science, and yet in the application of these rules he may very

possibly blunder- either because he is wanting in natural judgement

(though not in understanding) and, whilst he can comprehend the

general in abstracto, cannot distinguish whether a particular case

in concreto ought to rank under the former; or because his faculty

of judgement bas not been sufficiently exercised by examples and

real practice. Indeed, the grand and only use of examples, is to

sharpen the judgement. For as regards the correctness and precision of

the insight of the understanding, examples are commonly injurious

rather than otherwise, because, as casus in terminis they seldom

adequately fulfil the conditions of the rule. Besides, they often

weaken the power of our understanding to apprehend rules or laws in

their universality, independently of particular circumstances of

experience; and hence, accustom us to employ them more as formulae

than as principles. Examples are thus the go-cart of the judgement,

which he who is naturally deficient in that faculty cannot afford to

dispense with.



  *Deficiency in judgement is properly that which is called stupidity;

and for such a failing we know no remedy. A dull or narrow-minded

person, to whom nothing is wanting but a proper degree of

understanding, may be improved by tuition, even so far as to deserve

the epithet of learned. But as such persons frequently labour under

a deficiency in the faculty of judgement, it is not uncommon to find

men extremely learned who in the application of their science betray a

lamentable degree this irremediable want.



  But although general logic cannot give directions to the faculty

of judgement, the case is very different as regards transcendental

logic, insomuch that it appears to be the especial duty of the

latter to secure and direct, by means of determinate rules, the

faculty of judgement in the employment of the pure understanding. For,

as a doctrine, that is, as an endeavour to enlarge the sphere of the

understanding in regard to pure a priori cognitions, philosophy is

worse than useless, since from all the attempts hitherto made,

little or no ground has been gained. But, as a critique, in order to

guard against the mistakes of the faculty of judgement (lapsus

judicii) in the employment of the few pure conceptions of the

understanding which we possess, although its use is in this case

purely negative, philosophy is called upon to apply all its

acuteness and penetration.

  But transcendental philosophy has this peculiarity, that besides

indicating the rule, or rather the general condition for rules,

which is given in the pure conception of the understanding, it can, at

the same time, indicate a priori the case to which the rule must be

applied. The cause of the superiority which, in this respect,

transcendental philosophy possesses above all other sciences except

mathematics, lies in this: it treats of conceptions which must

relate a priori to their objects, whose objective validity

consequently cannot be demonstrated a posteriori, and is, at the

same time, under the obligation of presenting in general but

sufficient tests, the conditions under which objects can be given in

harmony with those conceptions; otherwise they would be mere logical

forms, without content, and not pure conceptions of the understanding.

  Our transcendental doctrine of the faculty of judgement will contain

two chapters. The first will treat of the sensuous condition under

which alone pure conceptions of the understanding can be employed-

that is, of the schematism of the pure understanding. The second

will treat of those synthetical judgements which are derived a

priori from pure conceptions of the understanding under those

conditions, and which lie a priori at the foundation of all other

cognitions, that is to say, it will treat of the principles of the

pure understanding.

       TRANSCENDENTAL DOCTRINE OF THE FACULTY OF JUDGEMENT

                   OR, ANALYTIC OF PRINCIPLES.



    CHAPTER I. Of the Schematism at of the Pure Conceptions

                    of the Understanding.



  In all subsumptions of an object under a conception, the

representation of the object must be homogeneous with the

conception; in other words, the conception must contain that which

is represented in the object to be subsumed under it. For this is

the meaning of the expression: "An object is contained under a

conception." Thus the empirical conception of a plate is homogeneous

with the pure geometrical conception of a circle, inasmuch as the

roundness which is cogitated in the former is intuited in the latter.

  But pure conceptions of the understanding, when compared with

empirical intuitions, or even with sensuous intuitions in general, are

quite heterogeneous, and never can be discovered in any intuition. How

then is the subsumption of the latter under the former, and

consequently the application of the categories to phenomena,

possible?- For it is impossible to say, for example: "Causality can be

intuited through the senses and is contained in the phenomenon."- This

natural and important question forms the real cause of the necessity

of a transcendental doctrine of the faculty of judgement, with the

purpose, to wit, of showing how pure conceptions of the

understanding can be applied to phenomena. In all other sciences,

where the conceptions by which the object is thought in the general

are not so different and heterogeneous from those which represent

the object in concreto- as it is given, it is quite unnecessary to

institute any special inquiries concerning the application of the

former to the latter.

  Now it is quite clear that there must be some third thing, which

on the one side is homogeneous with the category, and with the

phenomenon on the other, and so makes the application of the former to

the latter possible. This mediating representation must be pure

(without any empirical content), and yet must on the one side be

intellectual, on the other sensuous. Such a representation is the

transcendental schema.

  The conception of the understanding contains pure synthetical

unity of the manifold in general. Time, as the formal condition of the

manifold of the internal sense, consequently of the conjunction of all

representations, contains a priori a manifold in the pure intuition.

Now a transcendental determination of time is so far homogeneous

with the category, which constitutes the unity thereof, that it is

universal and rests upon a rule a priori. On the other hand, it is

so far homogeneous with the phenomenon, inasmuch as time is

contained in every empirical representation of the manifold. Thus an

application of the category to phenomena becomes possible, by means of

the transcendental determination of time, which, as the schema of

the conceptions of the understanding, mediates the subsumption of

the latter under the former.

  After what has been proved in our deduction of the categories, no

one, it is to be hoped, can hesitate as to the proper decision of

the question, whether the employment of these pure conceptions of

the understanding ought to be merely empirical or also transcendental;

in other words, whether the categories, as conditions of a possible

experience, relate a priori solely to phenomena, or whether, as

conditions of the possibility of things in general, their

application can be extended to objects as things in themselves. For we

have there seen that conceptions are quite impossible, and utterly

without signification, unless either to them, or at least to the

elements of which they consist, an object be given; and that,

consequently, they cannot possibly apply to objects as things in

themselves without regard to the question whether and how these may be

given to us; and, further, that the only manner in which objects can

be given to us is by means of the modification of our sensibility;

and, finally, that pure a priori conceptions, in addition to the

function of the understanding in the category, must contain a priori

formal conditions of sensibility (of the internal sense, namely),

which again contain the general condition under which alone the

category can be applied to any object. This formal and pure

condition of sensibility, to which the conception of the understanding

is restricted in its employment, we shall name the schema of the

conception of the understanding, and the procedure of the

understanding with these schemata we shall call the schematism of

the pure understanding.

  The schema is, in itself, always a mere product of the

imagination. But, as the synthesis of imagination has for its aim no

single intuition, but merely unity in the determination of

sensibility, the schema is clearly distinguishable from the image.

Thus, if I place five points one after another.... this is an image of

the number five. On the other hand, if I only think a number in

general, which may be either five or a hundred, this thought is rather

the representation of a method of representing in an image a sum

(e.g., a thousand) in conformity with a conception, than the image

itself, an image which I should find some little difficulty in

reviewing, and comparing with the conception. Now this

representation of a general procedure of the imagination to present

its image to a conception, I call the schema of this conception.

  In truth, it is not images of objects, but schemata, which lie at

the foundation of our pure sensuous conceptions. No image could ever

be adequate to our conception of a triangle in general. For the

generalness of the conception it never could attain to, as this

includes under itself all triangles, whether right-angled,

acute-angled, etc., whilst the image would always be limited to a

single part of this sphere. The schema of the triangle can exist

nowhere else than in thought, and it indicates a rule of the synthesis

of the imagination in regard to pure figures in space. Still less is

an object of experience, or an image of the object, ever to the

empirical conception. On the contrary, the conception always relates

immediately to the schema of the imagination, as a rule for the

determination of our intuition, in conformity with a certain general

conception. The conception of a dog indicates a rule, according to

which my imagination can delineate the figure of a four-footed

animal in general, without being limited to any particular

individual form which experience presents to me, or indeed to any

possible image that I can represent to myself in concreto. This

schematism of our understanding in regard to phenomena and their

mere form, is an art, hidden in the depths of the human soul, whose

true modes of action we shall only with difficulty discover and

unveil. Thus much only can we say: "The image is a product of the

empirical faculty of the productive imagination- the schema of

sensuous conceptions (of figures in space, for example) is a

product, and, as it were, a monogram of the pure imagination a priori,

whereby and according to which images first become possible, which,

however, can be connected with the conception only mediately by

means of the schema which they indicate, and are in themselves never

fully adequate to it." On the other hand, the schema of a pure

conception of the understanding is something that cannot be reduced

into any image- it is nothing else than the pure synthesis expressed

by the category, conformably, to a rule of unity according to

conceptions. It is a transcendental product of the imagination, a

product which concerns the determination of the internal sense,

according to conditions of its form (time) in respect to all

representations, in so far as these representations must be

conjoined a priori in one conception, conformably to the unity of

apperception.

  Without entering upon a dry and tedious analysis of the essential

requisites of transcendental schemata of the pure conceptions of the

understanding, we shall rather proceed at once to give an

explanation of them according to the order of the categories, and in

connection therewith.

  For the external sense the pure image of all quantities

(quantorum) is space; the pure image of all objects of sense in

general, is time. But the pure schema of quantity (quantitatis) as a

conception of the understanding, is number, a representation which

comprehends the successive addition of one to one (homogeneous

quantities). Thus, number is nothing else than the unity of the

synthesis of the manifold in a homogeneous intuition, by means of my

generating time itself in my apprehension of the intuition.

  Reality, in the pure conception of the understanding, is that

which corresponds to a sensation in general; that, consequently, the

conception of which indicates a being (in time). Negation is that

the conception of which represents a not-being (in time). The

opposition of these two consists therefore in the difference of one

and the same time, as a time filled or a time empty. Now as time is

only the form of intuition, consequently of objects as phenomena, that

which in objects corresponds to sensation is the transcendental matter

of all objects as things in themselves (Sachheit, reality). Now

every sensation has a degree or quantity by which it can fill time,

that is to say, the internal sense in respect of the representation of

an object, more or less, until it vanishes into nothing (= 0 =

negatio). Thus there is a relation and connection between reality

and negation, or rather a transition from the former to the latter,

which makes every reality representable to us as a quantum; and the

schema of a reality as the quantity of something in so far as it fills

time, is exactly this continuous and uniform generation of the reality

in time, as we descend in time from the sensation which has a

certain degree, down to the vanishing thereof, or gradually ascend

from negation to the quantity thereof.

  The schema of substance is the permanence of the real in time;

that is, the representation of it as a substratum of the empirical

determination of time; a substratum which therefore remains, whilst

all else changes. (Time passes not, but in it passes the existence

of the changeable. To time, therefore, which is itself unchangeable

and permanent, corresponds that which in the phenomenon is

unchangeable in existence, that is, substance, and it is only by it

that the succession and coexistence of phenomena can be determined

in regard to time.)

  The schema of cause and of the causality of a thing is the real

which, when posited, is always followed by something else. It

consists, therefore, in the succession of the manifold, in so far as

that succession is subjected to a rule.

  The schema of community (reciprocity of action and reaction), or the

reciprocal causality of substances in respect of their accidents, is

the coexistence of the determinations of the one with those of the

other, according to a general rule.

  The schema of possibility is the accordance of the synthesis of

different representations with the conditions of time in general

(as, for example, opposites cannot exist together at the same time

in the same thing, but only after each other), and is therefore the

determination of the representation of a thing at any time.

  The schema of reality is existence in a determined time.

  The schema of necessity is the existence of an object in all time.

  It is clear, from all this, that the schema of the category of

quantity contains and represents the generation (synthesis) of time

itself, in the successive apprehension of an object; the schema of

quality the synthesis of sensation with the representation of time, or

the filling up of time; the schema of relation the relation of

perceptions to each other in all time (that is, according to a rule of

the determination of time): and finally, the schema of modality and

its categories, time itself, as the correlative of the determination

of an object- whether it does belong to time, and how. The schemata,

therefore, are nothing but a priori determinations of time according

to rules, and these, in regard to all possible objects, following

the arrangement of the categories, relate to the series in time, the

content in time, the order in time, and finally, to the complex or

totality in time.

  Hence it is apparent that the schematism of the understanding, by

means of the transcendental synthesis of the imagination, amounts to

nothing else than the unity of the manifold of intuition in the

internal sense, and thus indirectly to the unity of apperception, as a

function corresponding to the internal sense (a receptivity). Thus,

the schemata of the pure conceptions of the understanding are the true

and only conditions whereby our understanding receives an

application to objects, and consequently significance. Finally,

therefore, the categories are only capable of empirical use,

inasmuch as they serve merely to subject phenomena to the universal

rules of synthesis, by means of an a priori necessary unity (on

account of the necessary union of all consciousness in one original

apperception); and so to render them susceptible of a complete

connection in one experience. But within this whole of possible

experience lie all our cognitions, and in the universal relation to

this experience consists transcendental truth, which antecedes all

empirical truth, and renders the latter possible.

  It is, however, evident at first sight, that although the schemata

of sensibility are the sole agents in realizing the categories, they

do, nevertheless, also restrict them, that is, they limit the

categories by conditions which lie beyond the sphere of understanding-

namely, in sensibility. Hence the schema is properly only the

phenomenon, or the sensuous conception of an object in harmony with

the category. (Numerus est quantitas phaenomenon- sensatio realitas

phaenomenon; constans et perdurabile rerum substantia phaenomenon-

aeternitas, necessitas, phaenomena, etc.) Now, if we remove a

restrictive condition, we thereby amplify, it appears, the formerly

limited conception. In this way, the categories in their pure

signification, free from all conditions of sensibility, ought to be

valid of things as they are, and not, as the schemata represent

them, merely as they appear; and consequently the categories must have

a significance far more extended, and wholly independent of all

schemata. In truth, there does always remain to the pure conceptions

of the understanding, after abstracting every sensuous condition, a

value and significance, which is, however, merely logical. But in this

case, no object is given them, and therefore they have no meaning

sufficient to afford us a conception of an object. The notion of

substance, for example, if we leave out the sensuous determination

of permanence, would mean nothing more than a something which can be

cogitated as subject, without the possibility of becoming a

predicate to anything else. Of this representation I can make nothing,

inasmuch as it does not indicate to me what determinations the thing

possesses which must thus be valid as premier subject. Consequently,

the categories, without schemata are merely functions of the

understanding for the production of conceptions, but do not

represent any object. This significance they derive from

sensibility, which at the same time realizes the understanding and

restricts it.

   CHAPTER II. System of all Principles of the Pure Understanding.



  In the foregoing chapter we have merely considered the general

conditions under which alone the transcendental faculty of judgement

is justified in using the pure conceptions of the understanding for

synthetical judgements. Our duty at present is to exhibit in

systematic connection those judgements which the understanding

really produces a priori. For this purpose, our table of the

categories will certainly afford us the natural and safe guidance. For

it is precisely the categories whose application to possible

experience must constitute all pure a priori cognition of the

understanding; and the relation of which to sensibility will, on

that very account, present us with a complete and systematic catalogue

of all the transcendental principles of the use of the understanding.

  Principles a priori are so called, not merely because they contain

in themselves the grounds of other judgements, but also because they

themselves are not grounded in higher and more general cognitions.

This peculiarity, however, does not raise them altogether above the

need of a proof. For although there could be found no higher

cognition, and therefore no objective proof, and although such a

principle rather serves as the foundation for all cognition of the

object, this by no means hinders us from drawing a proof from the

subjective sources of the possibility of the cognition of an object.

Such a proof is necessary, moreover, because without it the

principle might be liable to the imputation of being a mere gratuitous

assertion.

  In the second place, we shall limit our investigations to those

principles which relate to the categories. For as to the principles of

transcendental aesthetic, according to which space and time are the

conditions of the possibility of things as phenomena, as also the

restriction of these principles, namely, that they cannot be applied

to objects as things in themselves- these, of course, do not fall

within the scope of our present inquiry. In like manner, the

principles of mathematical science form no part of this system,

because they are all drawn from intuition, and not from the pure

conception of the understanding. The possibility of these

principles, however, will necessarily be considered here, inasmuch

as they are synthetical judgements a priori, not indeed for the

purpose of proving their accuracy and apodeictic certainty, which is

unnecessary, but merely to render conceivable and deduce the

possibility of such evident a priori cognitions.

  But we shall have also to speak of the principle of analytical

judgements, in opposition to synthetical judgements, which is the

proper subject of our inquiries, because this very opposition will

free the theory of the latter from all ambiguity, and place it clearly

before our eyes in its true nature.



        SYSTEM OF THE PRINCIPLES OF THE PURE UNDERSTANDING.



  SECTION I. Of the Supreme Principle of all Analytical Judgements.



  Whatever may be the content of our cognition, and in whatever manner

our cognition may be related to its object, the universal, although

only negative conditions of all our judgements is that they do not

contradict themselves; otherwise these judgements are in themselves

(even without respect to the object) nothing. But although there may

exist no contradiction in our judgement, it may nevertheless connect

conceptions in such a manner that they do not correspond to the

object, or without any grounds either a priori or a posteriori for

arriving at such a judgement, and thus, without being

self-contradictory, a judgement may nevertheless be either false or

groundless.

  Now, the proposition: "No subject can have a predicate that

contradicts it," is called the principle of contradiction, and is a

universal but purely negative criterion of all truth. But it belongs

to logic alone, because it is valid of cognitions, merely as

cognitions and without respect to their content, and declares that the

contradiction entirely nullifies them. We can also, however, make a

positive use of this principle, that is, not merely to banish

falsehood and error (in so far as it rests upon contradiction), but

also for the cognition of truth. For if the judgement is analytical,

be it affirmative or negative, its truth must always be recognizable

by means of the principle of contradiction. For the contrary of that

which lies and is cogitated as conception in the cognition of the

object will be always properly negatived, but the conception itself

must always be affirmed of the object, inasmuch as the contrary

thereof would be in contradiction to the object.

  We must therefore hold the principle of contradiction to be the

universal and fully sufficient Principle of all analytical

cognition. But as a sufficient criterion of truth, it has no further

utility or authority. For the fact that no cognition can be at

variance with this principle without nullifying itself, constitutes

this principle the sine qua non, but not the determining ground of the

truth of our cognition. As our business at present is properly with

the synthetical part of our knowledge only, we shall always be on

our guard not to transgress this inviolable principle; but at the same

time not to expect from it any direct assistance in the

establishment of the truth of any synthetical proposition.

  There exists, however, a formula of this celebrated principle- a

principle merely formal and entirely without content- which contains a

synthesis that has been inadvertently and quite unnecessarily mixed up

with it. It is this: "It is impossible for a thing to be and not to be

at the same time." Not to mention the superfluousness of the

addition of the word impossible to indicate the apodeictic

certainty, which ought to be self-evident from the proposition itself,

the proposition is affected by the condition of time, and as it were

says: "A thing = A, which is something = B, cannot at the same time be

non-B." But both, B as well as non-B, may quite well exist in

succession. For example, a man who is young cannot at the same time be

old; but the same man can very well be at one time young, and at

another not young, that is, old. Now the principle of contradiction as

a merely logical proposition must not by any means limit its

application merely to relations of time, and consequently a formula

like the preceding is quite foreign to its true purpose. The

misunderstanding arises in this way. We first of all separate a

predicate of a thing from the conception of the thing, and

afterwards connect with this predicate its opposite, and hence do

not establish any contradiction with the subject, but only with its

predicate, which has been conjoined with the subject synthetically-

a contradiction, moreover, which obtains only when the first and

second predicate are affirmed in the same time. If I say: "A man who

is ignorant is not learned," the condition "at the same time" must

be added, for he who is at one time ignorant, may at another be

learned. But if I say: "No ignorant man is a learned man," the

proposition is analytical, because the characteristic ignorance is now

a constituent part of the conception of the subject; and in this

case the negative proposition is evident immediately from the

proposition of contradiction, without the necessity of adding the

condition "the same time." This is the reason why I have altered the

formula of this principle- an alteration which shows very clearly

the nature of an analytical proposition.



  SECTION II. Of the Supreme Principle of all Synthetical Judgements.



  The explanation of the possibility of synthetical judgements is a

task with which general logic has nothing to do; indeed she needs

not even be acquainted with its name. But in transcendental logic it

is the most important matter to be dealt with- indeed the only one, if

the question is of the possibility of synthetical judgements a priori,

the conditions and extent of their validity. For when this question is

fully decided, it can reach its aim with perfect ease, the

determination, to wit, of the extent and limits of the pure

understanding.

  In an analytical judgement I do not go beyond the given

conception, in order to arrive at some decision respecting it. If

the judgement is affirmative, I predicate of the conception only

that which was already cogitated in it; if negative, I merely

exclude from the conception its contrary. But in synthetical

judgements, I must go beyond the given conception, in order to

cogitate, in relation with it, something quite different from that

which was cogitated in it, a relation which is consequently never

one either of identity or contradiction, and by means of which the

truth or error of the judgement cannot be discerned merely from the

judgement itself.

  Granted, then, that we must go out beyond a given conception, in

order to compare it synthetically with another, a third thing is

necessary, in which alone the synthesis of two conceptions can

originate. Now what is this tertium quid that is to be the medium of

all synthetical judgements? It is only a complex in which all our

representations are contained, the internal sense to wit, and its form

a priori, time.

  The synthesis of our representations rests upon the imagination;

their synthetical unity (which is requisite to a judgement), upon

the unity of apperception. In this, therefore, is to be sought the

possibility of synthetical judgements, and as all three contain the

sources of a priori representations, the possibility of pure

synthetical judgements also; nay, they are necessary upon these

grounds, if we are to possess a knowledge of objects, which rests

solely upon the synthesis of representations.

  If a cognition is to have objective reality, that is, to relate to

an object, and possess sense and meaning in respect to it, it is

necessary that the object be given in some way or another. Without

this, our conceptions are empty, and we may indeed have thought by

means of them, but by such thinking we have not, in fact, cognized

anything, we have merely played with representation. To give an

object, if this expression be understood in the sense of "to

present" the object, not mediately but immediately in intuition, means

nothing else than to apply the representation of it to experience,

be that experience real or only possible. Space and time themselves,

pure as these conceptions are from all that is empirical, and

certain as it is that they are represented fully a priori in the mind,

would be completely without objective validity, and without sense

and significance, if their necessary use in the objects of

experience were not shown. Nay, the representation of them is a mere

schema, that always relates to the reproductive imagination, which

calls up the objects of experience, without which they have no

meaning. And so it is with all conceptions without distinction.

  The possibility of experience is, then, that which gives objective

reality to all our a priori cognitions. Now experience depends upon

the synthetical unity of phenomena, that is, upon a synthesis

according to conceptions of the object of phenomena in general, a

synthesis without which experience never could become knowledge, but

would be merely a rhapsody of perceptions, never fitting together into

any connected text, according to rules of a thoroughly united

(possible) consciousness, and therefore never subjected to the

transcendental and necessary unity of apperception. Experience has

therefore for a foundation, a priori principles of its form, that is

to say, general rules of unity in the synthesis of phenomena, the

objective reality of which rules, as necessary conditions even of

the possibility of experience can which rules, as necessary

conditions- even of the possibility of experience- can always be shown

in experience. But apart from this relation, a priori synthetical

propositions are absolutely impossible, because they have no third

term, that is, no pure object, in which the synthetical unity can

exhibit the objective reality of its conceptions.

  Although, then, respecting space, or the forms which productive

imagination describes therein, we do cognize much a priori in

synthetical judgements, and are really in no need of experience for

this purpose, such knowledge would nevertheless amount to nothing

but a busy trifling with a mere chimera, were not space to be

considered as the condition of the phenomena which constitute the

material of external experience. Hence those pure synthetical

judgements do relate, though but mediately, to possible experience, or

rather to the possibility of experience, and upon that alone is

founded the objective validity of their synthesis.

  While then, on the one hand, experience, as empirical synthesis,

is the only possible mode of cognition which gives reality to all

other synthesis; on the other hand, this latter synthesis, as

cognition a priori, possesses truth, that is, accordance with its

object, only in so far as it contains nothing more than what is

necessary to the synthetical unity of experience.

  Accordingly, the supreme principle of all synthetical judgements is:

"Every object is subject to the necessary conditions of the

synthetical unity of the manifold of intuition in a possible

experience."

  A priori synthetical judgements are possible when we apply the

formal conditions of the a priori intuition, the synthesis of the

imagination, and the necessary unity of that synthesis in a

transcendental apperception, to a possible cognition of experience,

and say: "The conditions of the possibility of experience in general

are at the same time conditions of the possibility of the objects of

experience, and have, for that reason, objective validity in an a

priori synthetical judgement."



     SECTION III. Systematic Representation of all Synthetical

             Principles of the Pure Understanding.



  That principles exist at all is to be ascribed solely to the pure

understanding, which is not only the faculty of rules in regard to

that which happens, but is even the source of principles according

to which everything that can be presented to us as an object is

necessarily subject to rules, because without such rules we never

could attain to cognition of an object. Even the laws of nature, if

they are contemplated as principles of the empirical use of the

understanding, possess also a characteristic of necessity, and we

may therefore at least expect them to be determined upon grounds which

are valid a priori and antecedent to all experience. But all laws of

nature, without distinction, are subject to higher principles of the

understanding, inasmuch as the former are merely applications of the

latter to particular cases of experience. These higher principles

alone therefore give the conception, which contains the necessary

condition, and, as it were, the exponent of a rule; experience, on the

other hand, gives the case which comes under the rule.

  There is no danger of our mistaking merely empirical principles

for principles of the pure understanding, or conversely; for the

character of necessity, according to conceptions which distinguish the

latter, and the absence of this in every empirical proposition, how

extensively valid soever it may be, is a perfect safeguard against

confounding them. There are, however, pure principles a priori,

which nevertheless I should not ascribe to the pure understanding- for

this reason, that they are not derived from pure conceptions, but

(although by the mediation of the understanding) from pure intuitions.

But understanding is the faculty of conceptions. Such principles

mathematical science possesses, but their application to experience,

consequently their objective validity, nay the possibility of such a

priori synthetical cognitions (the deduction thereof) rests entirely

upon the pure understanding.

  On this account, I shall not reckon among my principles those of

mathematics; though I shall include those upon the possibility and

objective validity a priori, of principles of the mathematical

science, which, consequently, are to be looked upon as the principle

of these, and which proceed from conceptions to intuition, and not

from intuition to conceptions.

  In the application of the pure conceptions of the understanding to

possible experience, the employment of their synthesis is either

mathematical or dynamical, for it is directed partly on the

intuition alone, partly on the existence of a phenomenon. But the a

priori conditions of intuition are in relation to a possible

experience absolutely necessary, those of the existence of objects

of a possible empirical intuition are in themselves contingent.

Hence the principles of the mathematical use of the categories will

possess a character of absolute necessity, that is, will be

apodeictic; those, on the other hand, of the dynamical use, the

character of an a priori necessity indeed, but only under the

condition of empirical thought in an experience, therefore only

mediately and indirectly. Consequently they will not possess that

immediate evidence which is peculiar to the former, although their

application to experience does not, for that reason, lose its truth

and certitude. But of this point we shall be better able to judge at

the conclusion of this system of principles.

  The table of the categories is naturally our guide to the table of

principles, because these are nothing else than rules for the

objective employment of the former. Accordingly, all principles of the

pure understanding are:



                                1

                              Axioms

                           of Intuition



               2                                    3

          Anticipations                          Analogies

          of Perception                        of Experience

                                4

                          Postulates of

                        Empirical Thought

                           in general



  These appellations I have chosen advisedly, in order that we might

not lose sight of the distinctions in respect of the evidence and

the employment of these principles. It will, however, soon appear

that- a fact which concerns both the evidence of these principles, and

the a priori determination of phenomena- according to the categories

of quantity and quality (if we attend merely to the form of these),

the principles of these categories are distinguishable from those of

the two others, in as much as the former are possessed of an

intuitive, but the latter of a merely discursive, though in both

instances a complete, certitude. I shall therefore call the former

mathematical, and the latter dynamical principles.* It must be

observed, however, that by these terms I mean just as little in the

one case the principles of mathematics as those of general

(physical) dynamics in the other. I have here in view merely the

principles of the pure understanding, in their application to the

internal sense (without distinction of the representations given

therein), by means of which the sciences of mathematics and dynamics

become possible. Accordingly, I have named these principles rather

with reference to their application than their content; and I shall

now proceed to consider them in the order in which they stand in the

table.



  *All combination (conjunctio) is either composition (compositio)

or connection (nexus). The former is the synthesis of a manifold,

the parts of which do not necessarily belong to each other. For

example, the two triangles into which a square is divided by a

diagonal, do not necessarily belong to each other, and of this kind is

the synthesis of the homogeneous in everything that can be

mathematically considered. This synthesis can be divided into those of

aggregation and coalition, the former of which is applied to

extensive, the latter to intensive quantities. The second sort of

combination (nexus) is the synthesis of a manifold, in so far as its

parts do belong necessarily to each other; for example, the accident

to a substance, or the effect to the cause. Consequently it is a

synthesis of that which though heterogeneous, is represented as

connected a priori. This combination- not an arbitrary one- I

entitle dynamical because it concerns the connection of the

existence of the manifold. This, again, may be divided into the

physical synthesis, of the phenomena divided among each other, and the

metaphysical synthesis, or the connection of phenomena a priori in the

faculty of cognition.



                 1. AXIOMS OF INTUITION.

     The principle of these is: All Intuitions are Extensive

                      Quantities.



                         PROOF.



  All phenomena contain, as regards their form, an intuition in

space and time, which lies a priori at the foundation of all without

exception. Phenomena, therefore, cannot be apprehended, that is,

received into empirical consciousness otherwise than through the

synthesis of a manifold, through which the representations of a

determinate space or time are generated; that is to say, through the

composition of the homogeneous and the consciousness of the

synthetical unity of this manifold (homogeneous). Now the

consciousness of a homogeneous manifold in intuition, in so far as

thereby the representation of an object is rendered possible, is the

conception of a quantity (quanti). Consequently, even the perception

of an object as phenomenon is possible only through the same

synthetical unity of the manifold of the given sensuous intuition,

through which the unity of the composition of the homogeneous manifold

in the conception of a quantity is cogitated; that is to say, all

phenomena are quantities, and extensive quantities, because as

intuitions in space or time they must be represented by means of the

same synthesis through which space and time themselves are determined.

  An extensive quantity I call that wherein the representation of

the parts renders possible (and therefore necessarily antecedes) the

representation of the whole. I cannot represent to myself any line,

however small, without drawing it in thought, that is, without

generating from a point all its parts one after another, and in this

way alone producing this intuition. Precisely the same is the case

with every, even the smallest, portion of time. I cogitate therein

only the successive progress from one moment to another, and hence, by

means of the different portions of time and the addition of them, a

determinate quantity of time is produced. As the pure intuition in all

phenomena is either time or space, so is every phenomenon in its

character of intuition an extensive quantity, inasmuch as it can

only be cognized in our apprehension by successive synthesis (from

part to part). All phenomena are, accordingly, to be considered as

aggregates, that is, as a collection of previously given parts;

which is not the case with every sort of quantities, but only with

those which are represented and apprehended by us as extensive.

  On this successive synthesis of the productive imagination, in the

generation of figures, is founded the mathematics of extension, or

geometry, with its axioms, which express the conditions of sensuous

intuition a priori, under which alone the schema of a pure

conception of external intuition can exist; for example, "be tween two

points only one straight line is possible," "two straight lines cannot

enclose a space," etc. These are the axioms which properly relate only

to quantities (quanta) as such.

  But, as regards the quantity of a thing (quantitas), that is to say,

the answer to the question: "How large is this or that object?"

although, in respect to this question, we have various propositions

synthetical and immediately certain (indemonstrabilia); we have, in

the proper sense of the term, no axioms. For example, the

propositions: "If equals be added to equals, the wholes are equal";

"If equals be taken from equals, the remainders are equal"; are

analytical, because I am immediately conscious of the identity of

the production of the one quantity with the production of the other;

whereas axioms must be a priori synthetical propositions. On the other

hand, the self-evident propositions as to the relation of numbers, are

certainly synthetical but not universal, like those of geometry, and

for this reason cannot be called axioms, but numerical formulae.

That 7 + 5 = 12 is not an analytical proposition. For neither in the

representation of seven, nor of five, nor of the composition of the

two numbers, do I cogitate the number twelve. (Whether I cogitate

the number in the addition of both, is not at present the question;

for in the case of an analytical proposition, the only point is

whether I really cogitate the predicate in the representation of the

subject.) But although the proposition is synthetical, it is

nevertheless only a singular proposition. In so far as regard is

here had merely to the synthesis of the homogeneous (the units), it

cannot take place except in one manner, although our use of these

numbers is afterwards general. If I say: "A triangle can be

constructed with three lines, any two of which taken together are

greater than the third," I exercise merely the pure function of the

productive imagination, which may draw the lines longer or shorter and

construct the angles at its pleasure. On the contrary, the number

seven is possible only in one manner, and so is likewise the number

twelve, which results from the synthesis of seven and five. Such

propositions, then, cannot be termed axioms (for in that case we

should have an infinity of these), but numerical formulae.

  This transcendental principle of the mathematics of phenomena

greatly enlarges our a priori cognition. For it is by this principle

alone that pure mathematics is rendered applicable in all its

precision to objects of experience, and without it the validity of

this application would not be so self-evident; on the contrary,

contradictions and confusions have often arisen on this very point.

Phenomena are not things in themselves. Empirical intuition is

possible only through pure intuition (of space and time);

consequently, what geometry affirms of the latter, is indisputably

valid of the former. All evasions, such as the statement that

objects of sense do not conform to the rules of construction in

space (for example, to the rule of the infinite divisibility of

lines or angles), must fall to the ground. For, if these objections

hold good, we deny to space, and with it to all mathematics, objective

validity, and no longer know wherefore, and how far, mathematics can

be applied to phenomena. The synthesis of spaces and times as the

essential form of all intuition, is that which renders possible the

apprehension of a phenomenon, and therefore every external experience,

consequently all cognition of the objects of experience; and

whatever mathematics in its pure use proves of the former, must

necessarily hold good of the latter. All objections are but the

chicaneries of an ill-instructed reason, which erroneously thinks to

liberate the objects of sense from the formal conditions of our

sensibility, and represents these, although mere phenomena, as

things in themselves, presented as such to our understanding. But in

this case, no a priori synthetical cognition of them could be

possible, consequently not through pure conceptions of space and the

science which determines these conceptions, that is to say,

geometry, would itself be impossible.



                2. ANTICIPATIONS OF PERCEPTION.



    The principle of these is: In all phenomena the Real, that

      which is an object of sensation, has Intensive Quantity,

                  that is, has a Degree.



                         PROOF.



  Perception is empirical consciousness, that is to say, a

consciousness which contains an element of sensation. Phenomena as

objects of perception are not pure, that is, merely formal intuitions,

like space and time, for they cannot be perceived in themselves.

They contain, then, over and above the intuition, the materials for an

object (through which is represented something existing in space or

time), that is to say, they contain the real of sensation, as a

representation merely subjective, which gives us merely the

consciousness that the subject is affected, and which we refer to some

external object. Now, a gradual transition from empirical

consciousness to pure consciousness is possible, inasmuch as the

real in this consciousness entirely vanishes, and there remains a

merely formal consciousness (a priori) of the manifold in time and

space; consequently there is possible a synthesis also of the

production of the quantity of a sensation from its commencement,

that is, from the pure intuition = 0 onwards up to a certain

quantity of the sensation. Now as sensation in itself is not an

objective representation, and in it is to be found neither the

intuition of space nor of time, it cannot possess any extensive

quantity, and yet there does belong to it a quantity (and that by

means of its apprehension, in which empirical consciousness can within

a certain time rise from nothing = 0 up to its given amount),

consequently an intensive quantity. And thus we must ascribe intensive

quantity, that is, a degree of influence on sense to all objects of

perception, in so far as this perception contains sensation.

  All cognition, by means of which I am enabled to cognize and

determine a priori what belongs to empirical cognition, may be

called an anticipation; and without doubt this is the sense in which

Epicurus employed his expression prholepsis. But as there is in

phenomena something which is never cognized a priori, which on this

account constitutes the proper difference between pure and empirical

cognition, that is to say, sensation (as the matter of perception), it

follows, that sensation is just that element in cognition which cannot

be at all anticipated. On the other hand, we might very well term

the pure determinations in space and time, as well in regard to figure

as to quantity, anticipations of phenomena, because they represent a

priori that which may always be given a posteriori in experience.

But suppose that in every sensation, as sensation in general,

without any particular sensation being thought of, there existed

something which could be cognized a priori, this would deserve to be

called anticipation in a special sense- special, because it may seem

surprising to forestall experience, in that which concerns the

matter of experience, and which we can only derive from itself. Yet

such really is the case here.

  Apprehension, by means of sensation alone, fills only one moment,

that is, if I do not take into consideration a succession of many

sensations. As that in the phenomenon, the apprehension of which is

not a successive synthesis advancing from parts to an entire

representation, sensation has therefore no extensive quantity; the

want of sensation in a moment of time would represent it as empty,

consequently = O. That which in the empirical intuition corresponds to

sensation is reality (realitas phaenomenon); that which corresponds to

the absence of it, negation = O. Now every sensation is capable of a

diminution, so that it can decrease, and thus gradually disappear.

Therefore, between reality in a phenomenon and negation, there

exists a continuous concatenation of many possible intermediate

sensations, the difference of which from each other is always

smaller than that between the given sensation and zero, or complete

negation. That is to say, the real in a phenomenon has always a

quantity, which however is not discoverable in apprehension,

inasmuch as apprehension take place by means of mere sensation in

one instant, and not by the successive synthesis of many sensations,

and therefore does not progress from parts to the whole. Consequently,

it has a quantity, but not an extensive quantity.

  Now that quantity which is apprehended only as unity, and in which

plurality can be represented only by approximation to negation = O,

I term intensive quantity. Consequently, reality in a phenomenon has

intensive quantity, that is, a degree. if we consider this reality

as cause (be it of sensation or of another reality in the

phenomenon, for example, a change), we call the degree of reality in

its character of cause a momentum, for example, the momentum of

weight; and for this reason, that the degree only indicates that

quantity the apprehension of which is not successive, but

instantaneous. This, however, I touch upon only in passing, for with

causality I have at present nothing to do.

  Accordingly, every sensation, consequently every reality in

phenomena, however small it may be, has a degree, that is, an

intensive quantity, which may always be lessened, and between

reality and negation there exists a continuous connection of

possible realities, and possible smaller perceptions. Every colour-

for example, red- has a degree, which, be it ever so small, is never

the smallest, and so is it always with heat, the momentum of weight,

etc.

  This property of quantities, according to which no part of them is

the smallest possible (no part simple), is called their continuity.

Space and time are quanta continua, because no part of them can be

given, without enclosing it within boundaries (points and moments),

consequently, this given part is itself a space or a time. Space,

therefore, consists only of spaces, and time of times. Points and

moments are only boundaries, that is, the mere places or positions

of their limitation. But places always presuppose intuitions which are

to limit or determine them; and we cannot conceive either space or

time composed of constituent parts which are given before space or

time. Such quantities may also be called flowing, because synthesis

(of the productive imagination) in the production of these

quantities is a progression in time, the continuity of which we are

accustomed to indicate by the expression flowing.

  All phenomena, then, are continuous quantities, in respect both to

intuition and mere perception (sensation, and with it reality). In the

former case they are extensive quantities; in the latter, intensive.

When the synthesis of the manifold of a phenomenon is interrupted,

there results merely an aggregate of several phenomena, and not

properly a phenomenon as a quantity, which is not produced by the mere

continuation of the productive synthesis of a certain kind, but by the

repetition of a synthesis always ceasing. For example, if I call

thirteen dollars a sum or quantity of money, I employ the term quite

correctly, inasmuch as I understand by thirteen dollars the value of a

mark in standard silver, which is, to be sure, a continuous

quantity, in which no part is the smallest, but every part might

constitute a piece of money, which would contain material for still

smaller pieces. If, however, by the words thirteen dollars I

understand so many coins (be their value in silver what it may), it

would be quite erroneous to use the expression a quantity of

dollars; on the contrary, I must call them aggregate, that is, a

number of coins. And as in every number we must have unity as the

foundation, so a phenomenon taken as unity is a quantity, and as

such always a continuous quantity (quantum continuum).

  Now, seeing all phenomena, whether considered as extensive or

intensive, are continuous quantities, the proposition: "All change

(transition of a thing from one state into another) is continuous,"

might be proved here easily, and with mathematical evidence, were it

not that the causality of a change lies, entirely beyond the bounds of

a transcendental philosophy, and presupposes empirical principles. For

of the possibility of a cause which changes the condition of things,

that is, which determines them to the contrary to a certain given

state, the understanding gives us a priori no knowledge; not merely

because it has no insight into the possibility of it (for such insight

is absent in several a priori cognitions), but because the notion of

change concerns only certain determinations of phenomena, which

experience alone can acquaint us with, while their cause lies in the

unchangeable. But seeing that we have nothing which we could here

employ but the pure fundamental conceptions of all possible

experience, among which of course nothing empirical can be admitted,

we dare not, without injuring the unity of our system, anticipate

general physical science, which is built upon certain fundamental

experiences.

  Nevertheless, we are in no want of proofs of the great influence

which the principle above developed exercises in the anticipation of

perceptions, and even in supplying the want of them, so far as to

shield us against the false conclusions which otherwise we might

rashly draw.

  If all reality in perception has a degree, between which and

negation there is an endless sequence of ever smaller degrees, and if,

nevertheless, every sense must have a determinate degree of

receptivity for sensations; no perception, and consequently no

experience is possible, which can prove, either immediately or

mediately, an entire absence of all reality in a phenomenon; in

other words, it is impossible ever to draw from experience a proof

of the existence of empty space or of empty time. For in the first

place, an entire absence of reality in a sensuous intuition cannot

of course be an object of perception; secondly, such absence cannot be

deduced from the contemplation of any single phenomenon, and the

difference of the degrees in its reality; nor ought it ever to be

admitted in explanation of any phenomenon. For if even the complete

intuition of a determinate space or time is thoroughly real, that

is, if no part thereof is empty, yet because every reality has its

degree, which, with the extensive quantity of the phenomenon

unchanged, can diminish through endless gradations down to nothing

(the void), there must be infinitely graduated degrees, with which

space or time is filled, and the intensive quantity in different

phenomena may be smaller or greater, although the extensive quantity

of the intuition remains equal and unaltered.

  We shall give an example of this. Almost all natural philosophers,

remarking a great difference in the quantity of the matter of

different kinds in bodies with the same volume (partly on account of

the momentum of gravity or weight, partly on account of the momentum

of resistance to other bodies in motion), conclude unanimously that

this volume (extensive quantity of the phenomenon) must be void in all

bodies, although in different proportion. But who would suspect that

these for the most part mathematical and mechanical inquirers into

nature should ground this conclusion solely on a metaphysical

hypothesis- a sort of hypothesis which they profess to disparage and

avoid? Yet this they do, in assuming that the real in space (I must

not here call it impenetrability or weight, because these are

empirical conceptions) is always identical, and can only be

distinguished according to its extensive quantity, that is,

multiplicity. Now to this presupposition, for which they can have no

ground in experience, and which consequently is merely metaphysical, I

oppose a transcendental demonstration, which it is true will not

explain the difference in the filling up of spaces, but which

nevertheless completely does away with the supposed necessity of the

above-mentioned presupposition that we cannot explain the said

difference otherwise than by the hypothesis of empty spaces. This

demonstration, moreover, has the merit of setting the understanding at

liberty to conceive this distinction in a different manner, if the

explanation of the fact requires any such hypothesis. For we

perceive that although two equal spaces may be completely filled by

matters altogether different, so that in neither of them is there left

a single point wherein matter is not present, nevertheless, every

reality has its degree (of resistance or of weight), which, without

diminution of the extensive quantity, can become less and less ad

infinitum, before it passes into nothingness and disappears. Thus an

expansion which fills a space- for example, caloric, or any other

reality in the phenomenal world- can decrease in its degrees to

infinity, yet without leaving the smallest part of the space empty; on

the contrary, filling it with those lesser degrees as completely as

another phenomenon could with greater. My intention here is by no

means to maintain that this is really the case with the difference

of matters, in regard to their specific gravity; I wish only to prove,

from a principle of the pure understanding, that the nature of our

perceptions makes such a mode of explanation possible, and that it

is erroneous to regard the real in a phenomenon as equal quoad its

degree, and different only quoad its aggregation and extensive

quantity, and this, too, on the pretended authority of an a priori

principle of the understanding.

  Nevertheless, this principle of the anticipation of perception

must somewhat startle an inquirer whom initiation into

transcendental philosophy has rendered cautious. We must naturally

entertain some doubt whether or not the understanding can enounce

any such synthetical proposition as that respecting the degree of

all reality in phenomena, and consequently the possibility of the

internal difference of sensation itself- abstraction being made of its

empirical quality. Thus it is a question not unworthy of solution:

"How the understanding can pronounce synthetically and a priori

respecting phenomena, and thus anticipate these, even in that which is

peculiarly and merely empirical, that, namely, which concerns

sensation itself?"

  The quality of sensation is in all cases merely empirical, and

cannot be represented a priori (for example, colours, taste, etc.).

But the real- that which corresponds to sensation- in opposition to

negation = O, only represents something the conception of which in

itself contains a being (ein seyn), and signifies nothing but the

synthesis in an empirical consciousness. That is to say, the empirical

consciousness in the internal sense can be raised from 0 to every

higher degree, so that the very same extensive quantity of

intuition, an illuminated surface, for example, excites as great a

sensation as an aggregate of many other surfaces less illuminated.

We can therefore make complete abstraction of the extensive quantity

of a phenomenon, and represent to ourselves in the mere sensation in a

certain momentum, a synthesis of homogeneous ascension from 0 up to

the given empirical consciousness, All sensations therefore as such

are given only a posteriori, but this property thereof, namely, that

they have a degree, can be known a priori. It is worthy of remark,

that in respect to quantities in general, we can cognize a priori only

a single quality, namely, continuity; but in respect to all quality

(the real in phenomena), we cannot cognize a priori anything more than

the intensive quantity thereof, namely, that they have a degree. All

else is left to experience.



                  3. ANALOGIES OF EXPERIENCE.



    The principle of these is: Experience is possible only

     through the representation of a necessary connection

                      of Perceptions.



                           PROOF.



  Experience is an empirical cognition; that is to say, a cognition

which determines an object by means of perceptions. It is therefore

a synthesis of perceptions, a synthesis which is not itself

contained in perception, but which contains the synthetical unity of

the manifold of perception in a consciousness; and this unity

constitutes the essential of our cognition of objects of the senses,

that is, of experience (not merely of intuition or sensation). Now

in experience our perceptions come together contingently, so that no

character of necessity in their connection appears, or can appear from

the perceptions themselves, because apprehension is only a placing

together of the manifold of empirical intuition, and no representation

of a necessity in the connected existence of the phenomena which

apprehension brings together, is to be discovered therein. But as

experience is a cognition of objects by means of perceptions, it

follows that the relation of the existence of the existence of the

manifold must be represented in experience not as it is put together

in time, but as it is objectively in time. And as time itself cannot

be perceived, the determination of the existence of objects in time

can only take place by means of their connection in time in general,

consequently only by means of a priori connecting conceptions. Now

as these conceptions always possess the character of necessity,

experience is possible only by means of a representation of the

necessary connection of perception.

  The three modi of time are permanence, succession, and

coexistence. Accordingly, there are three rules of all relations of

time in phenomena, according to which the existence of every

phenomenon is determined in respect of the unity of all time, and

these antecede all experience and render it possible.

  The general principle of all three analogies rests on the

necessary unity of apperception in relation to all possible

empirical consciousness (perception) at every time, consequently, as

this unity lies a priori at the foundation of all mental operations,

the principle rests on the synthetical unity of all phenomena

according to their relation in time. For the original apperception

relates to our internal sense (the complex of all representations),

and indeed relates a priori to its form, that is to say, the

relation of the manifold empirical consciousness in time. Now this

manifold must be combined in original apperception according to

relations of time- a necessity imposed by the a priori

transcendental unity of apperception, to which is subjected all that

can belong to my (i.e., my own) cognition, and therefore all that

can become an object for me. This synthetical and a priori

determined unity in relation of perceptions in time is therefore the

rule: "All empirical determinations of time must be subject to rules

of the general determination of time"; and the analogies of

experience, of which we are now about to treat, must be rules of

this nature.

  These principles have this peculiarity, that they do not concern

phenomena, and the synthesis of the empirical intuition thereof, but

merely the existence of phenomena and their relation to each other

in regard to this existence. Now the mode in which we apprehend a

thing in a phenomenon can be determined a priori in such a manner that

the rule of its synthesis can give, that is to say, can produce this a

priori intuition in every empirical example. But the existence of

phenomena cannot be known a priori, and although we could arrive by

this path at a conclusion of the fact of some existence, we could

not cognize that existence determinately, that is to say, we should be

incapable of anticipating in what respect the empirical intuition of

it would be distinguishable from that of others.

  The two principles above mentioned, which I called mathematical,

in consideration of the fact of their authorizing the application of

mathematic phenomena, relate to these phenomena only in regard to

their possibility, and instruct us how phenomena, as far as regards

their intuition or the real in their perception, can be generated

according to the rules of a mathematical synthesis. Consequently,

numerical quantities, and with them the determination of a

phenomenon as a quantity, can be employed in the one case as well as

in the other. Thus, for example, out of 200,000 illuminations by the

moon, I might compose and give a priori, that is construct, the degree

of our sensations of the sunlight. We may therefore entitle these

two principles constitutive.

  The case is very different with those principles whose province it

is to subject the existence of phenomena to rules a priori. For as

existence does not admit of being constructed, it is clear that they

must only concern the relations of existence and be merely

regulative principles. In this case, therefore, neither axioms nor

anticipations are to be thought of. Thus, if a perception is given us,

in a certain relation of time to other (although undetermined)

perceptions, we cannot then say a priori, what and how great (in

quantity) the other perception necessarily connected with the former

is, but only how it is connected, quoad its existence, in this given

modus of time. Analogies in philosophy mean something very different

from that which they represent in mathematics. In the latter they

are formulae, which enounce the equality of two relations of quantity,

and are always constitutive, so that if two terms of the proportion

are given, the third is also given, that is, can be constructed by the

aid of these formulae. But in philosophy, analogy is not the

equality of two quantitative but of two qualitative relations. In this

case, from three given terms, I can give a priori and cognize the

relation to a fourth member, but not this fourth term itself, although

I certainly possess a rule to guide me in the search for this fourth

term in experience, and a mark to assist me in discovering it. An

analogy of experience is therefore only a rule according to which

unity of experience must arise out of perceptions in respect to

objects (phenomena) not as a constitutive, but merely as a

regulative principle. The same holds good also of the postulates of

empirical thought in general, which relate to the synthesis of mere

intuition (which concerns the form of phenomena), the synthesis of

perception (which concerns the matter of phenomena), and the synthesis

of experience (which concerns the relation of these perceptions).

For they are only regulative principles, and clearly distinguishable

from the mathematical, which are constitutive, not indeed in regard to

the certainty which both possess a priori, but in the mode of evidence

thereof, consequently also in the manner of demonstration.

  But what has been observed of all synthetical propositions, and must

be particularly remarked in this place, is this, that these

analogies possess significance and validity, not as principles of

the transcendental, but only as principles of the empirical use of the

understanding, and their truth can therefore be proved only as such,

and that consequently the phenomena must not be subjoined directly

under the categories, but only under their schemata. For if the

objects to which those principles must be applied were things in

themselves, it would be quite impossible to cognize aught concerning

them synthetically a priori. But they are nothing but phenomena; a

complete knowledge of which- a knowledge to which all principles a

priori must at last relate- is the only possible experience. It

follows that these principles can have nothing else for their aim than

the conditions of the empirical cognition in the unity of synthesis of

phenomena. But this synthesis is cogitated only in the schema of the

pure conception of the understanding, of whose unity, as that of a

synthesis in general, the category contains the function

unrestricted by any sensuous condition. These principles will

therefore authorize us to connect phenomena according to an analogy,

with the logical and universal unity of conceptions, and

consequently to employ the categories in the principles themselves;

but in the application of them to experience, we shall use only

their schemata, as the key to their proper application, instead of the

categories, or rather the latter as restricting conditions, under

the title of "formulae" of the former.



                     A. FIRST ANALOGY.



           Principle of the Permanence of Substance.



   In all changes of phenomena, substance is permanent, and the

   quantum thereof in nature is neither increased nor diminished.



                          PROOF.



  All phenomena exist in time, wherein alone as substratum, that is,

as the permanent form of the internal intuition, coexistence and

succession can be represented. Consequently time, in which all changes

of phenomena must be cogitated, remains and changes not, because it is

that in which succession and coexistence can be represented only as

determinations thereof. Now, time in itself cannot be an object of

perception. It follows that in objects of perception, that is, in

phenomena, there must be found a substratum which represents time in

general, and in which all change or coexistence can be perceived by

means of the relation of phenomena to it. But the substratum of all

reality, that is, of all that pertains to the existence of things,

is substance; all that pertains to existence can be cogitated only

as a determination of substance. Consequently, the permanent, in

relation to which alone can all relations of time in phenomena be

determined, is substance in the world of phenomena, that is, the

real in phenomena, that which, as the substratum of all change,

remains ever the same. Accordingly, as this cannot change in

existence, its quantity in nature can neither be increased nor

diminished.

  Our apprehension of the manifold in a phenomenon is always

successive, is Consequently always changing. By it alone we could,

therefore, never determine whether this manifold, as an object of

experience, is coexistent or successive, unless it had for a

foundation something fixed and permanent, of the existence of which

all succession and coexistence are nothing but so many modes (modi

of time). Only in the permanent, then, are relations of time

possible (for simultaneity and succession are the only relations in

time); that is to say, the permanent is the substratum of our

empirical representation of time itself, in which alone all

determination of time is possible. Permanence is, in fact, just

another expression for time, as the abiding correlate of all existence

of phenomena, and of all change, and of all coexistence. For change

does not affect time itself, but only the phenomena in time (just as

coexistence cannot be regarded as a modus of time itself, seeing

that in time no parts are coexistent, but all successive). If we

were to attribute succession to time itself, we should be obliged to

cogitate another time, in which this succession would be possible.

It is only by means of the permanent that existence in different parts

of the successive series of time receives a quantity, which we entitle

duration. For in mere succession, existence is perpetually vanishing

and recommencing, and therefore never has even the least quantity.

Without the permanent, then, no relation in time is possible. Now,

time in itself is not an object of perception; consequently the

permanent in phenomena must be regarded as the substratum of all

determination of time, and consequently also as the condition of the

possibility of all synthetical unity of perceptions, that is, of

experience; and all existence and all change in time can only be

regarded as a mode in the existence of that which abides unchangeably.

Therefore, in all phenomena, the permanent is the object in itself,

that is, the substance (phenomenon); but all that changes or can

change belongs only to the mode of the existence of this substance

or substances, consequently to its determinations.

  I find that in all ages not only the philosopher, but even the

common understanding, has preposited this permanence as a substratum

of all change in phenomena; indeed, I am compelled to believe that

they will always accept this as an indubitable fact. Only the

philosopher expresses himself in a more precise and definite manner,

when he says: "In all changes in the world, the substance remains, and

the accidents alone are changeable." But of this decidedly synthetical

proposition, I nowhere meet with even an attempt at proof; nay, it

very rarely has the good fortune to stand, as it deserves to do, at

the head of the pure and entirely a priori laws of nature. In truth,

the statement that substance is permanent, is tautological. For this

very permanence is the ground on which we apply the category of

substance to the phenomenon; and we should have been obliged to

prove that in all phenomena there is something permanent, of the

existence of which the changeable is nothing but a determination.

But because a proof of this nature cannot be dogmatical, that is,

cannot be drawn from conceptions, inasmuch as it concerns a

synthetical proposition a priori, and as philosophers never

reflected that such propositions are valid only in relation to

possible experience, and therefore cannot be proved except by means of

a deduction of the possibility of experience, it is no wonder that

while it has served as the foundation of all experience (for we feel

the need of it in empirical cognition), it has never been supported by

proof.

  A philosopher was asked: "What is the weight of smoke?" He answered:

"Subtract from the weight of the burnt wood the weight of the

remaining ashes, and you will have the weight of the smoke." Thus he

presumed it to be incontrovertible that even in fire the matter

(substance) does not perish, but that only the form of it undergoes

a change. In like manner was the saying: "From nothing comes nothing,"

only another inference from the principle or permanence, or rather

of the ever-abiding existence of the true subject in phenomena. For if

that in the phenomenon which we call substance is to be the proper

substratum of all determination of time, it follows that all existence

in past as well as in future time, must be determinable by means of it

alone. Hence we are entitled to apply the term substance to a

phenomenon, only because we suppose its existence in all time, a

notion which the word permanence does not fully express, as it seems

rather to be referable to future time. However, the internal necessity

perpetually to be, is inseparably connected with the necessity

always to have been, and so the expression may stand as it is.

"Gigni de nihilo nihil; in nihilum nil posse reverti,"* are two

propositions which the ancients never parted, and which people

nowadays sometimes mistakenly disjoin, because they imagine that the

propositions apply to objects as things in themselves, and that the

former might be inimical to the dependence (even in respect of its

substance also) of the world upon a supreme cause. But this

apprehension is entirely needless, for the question in this case is

only of phenomena in the sphere of experience, the unity of which

never could be possible, if we admitted the possibility that new

things (in respect of their substance) should arise. For in that case,

we should lose altogether that which alone can represent the unity

of time, to wit, the identity of the substratum, as that through which

alone all change possesses complete and thorough unity. This

permanence is, however, nothing but the manner in which we represent

to ourselves the existence of things in the phenomenal world.



  *[Persius, Satirae, iii.83-84. "Nothing can be produced from

nothing; nothing can be returned into nothing."]



  The determinations of a substance, which are only particular modes

of its existence, are called accidents. They are always real,

because they concern the existence of substance (negations are only

determinations, which express the non-existence of something in the

substance). Now, if to this real in the substance we ascribe a

particular existence (for example, to motion as an accident of

matter), this existence is called inherence, in contradistinction to

the existence of substance, which we call subsistence. But hence arise

many misconceptions, and it would be a more accurate and just mode

of expression to designate the accident only as the mode in which

the existence of a substance is positively determined. Meanwhile, by

reason of the conditions of the logical exercise of our understanding,

it is impossible to avoid separating, as it were, that which in the

existence of a substance is subject to change, whilst the substance

remains, and regarding it in relation to that which is properly

permanent and radical. On this account, this category of substance

stands under the title of relation, rather because it is the condition

thereof than because it contains in itself any relation.

  Now, upon this notion of permanence rests the proper notion of the

conception change. Origin and extinction are not changes of that which

originates or becomes extinct. Change is but a mode of existence,

which follows on another mode of existence of the same object; hence

all that changes is permanent, and only the condition thereof changes.

Now since this mutation affects only determinations, which can have

a beginning or an end, we may say, employing an expression which seems

somewhat paradoxical: "Only the permanent (substance) is subject to

change; the mutable suffers no change, but rather alternation, that

is, when certain determinations cease, others begin."

  Change, when, cannot be perceived by us except in substances, and

origin or extinction in an absolute sense, that does not concern

merely a determination of the permanent, cannot be a possible

perception, for it is this very notion of the permanent which

renders possible the representation of a transition from one state

into another, and from non-being to being, which, consequently, can be

empirically cognized only as alternating determinations of that

which is permanent. Grant that a thing absolutely begins to be; we

must then have a point of time in which it was not. But how and by

what can we fix and determine this point of time, unless by that which

already exists? For a void time- preceding- is not an object of

perception; but if we connect this beginning with objects which

existed previously, and which continue to exist till the object in

question in question begins to be, then the latter can only be a

determination of the former as the permanent. The same holds good of

the notion of extinction, for this presupposes the empirical

representation of a time, in which a phenomenon no longer exists.

  Substances (in the world of phenomena) are the substratum of all

determinations of time. The beginning of some, and the ceasing to be

of other substances, would utterly do away with the only condition

of the empirical unity of time; and in that case phenomena would

relate to two different times, in which, side by side, existence would

pass; which is absurd. For there is only one time in which all

different times must be placed, not as coexistent, but as successive.

  Accordingly, permanence is a necessary condition under which alone

phenomena, as things or objects, are determinable in a possible

experience. But as regards the empirical criterion of this necessary

permanence, and with it of the substantiality of phenomena, we shall

find sufficient opportunity to speak in the sequel.



                   B. SECOND ANALOGY.



      Principle of the Succession of Time According

                to the Law of Causality.



     All changes take place according to the law of the

              connection of Cause and Effect.



                         PROOF.



  (That all phenomena in the succession of time are only changes, that

is, a successive being and non-being of the determinations of

substance, which is permanent; consequently that a being of

substance itself which follows on the non-being thereof, or a

non-being of substance which follows on the being thereof, in other

words, that the origin or extinction of substance itself, is

impossible- all this has been fully established in treating of the

foregoing principle. This principle might have been expressed as

follows: "All alteration (succession) of phenomena is merely

change"; for the changes of substance are not origin or extinction,

because the conception of change presupposes the same subject as

existing with two opposite determinations, and consequently as

permanent. After this premonition, we shall proceed to the proof.)

  I perceive that phenomena succeed one another, that is to say, a

state of things exists at one time, the opposite of which existed in a

former state. In this case, then, I really connect together two

perceptions in time. Now connection is not an operation of mere

sense and intuition, but is the product of a synthetical faculty of

imagination, which determines the internal sense in respect of a

relation of time. But imagination can connect these two states in

two ways, so that either the one or the other may antecede in time;

for time in itself cannot be an object of perception, and what in an

object precedes and what follows cannot be empirically determined in

relation to it. I am only conscious, then, that my imagination

places one state before and the other after; not that the one state

antecedes the other in the object. In other words, the objective

relation of the successive phenomena remains quite undetermined by

means of mere perception. Now in order that this relation may be

cognized as determined, the relation between the two states must be so

cogitated that it is thereby determined as necessary, which of them

must be placed before and which after, and not conversely. But the

conception which carries with it a necessity of synthetical unity, can

be none other than a pure conception of the understanding which does

not lie in mere perception; and in this case it is the conception of

"the relation of cause and effect," the former of which determines the

latter in time, as its necessary consequence, and not as something

which might possibly antecede (or which might in some cases not be

perceived to follow). It follows that it is only because we subject

the sequence of phenomena, and consequently all change, to the law

of causality, that experience itself, that is, empirical cognition

of phenomena, becomes possible; and consequently, that phenomena

themselves, as objects of experience, are possible only by virtue of

this law.

  Our apprehension of the manifold of phenomena is always

successive. The representations of parts succeed one another.

Whether they succeed one another in the object also, is a second point

for reflection, which was not contained in the former. Now we may

certainly give the name of object to everything, even to every

representation, so far as we are conscious thereof; but what this word

may mean in the case of phenomena, not merely in so far as they (as

representations) are objects, but only in so far as they indicate an

object, is a question requiring deeper consideration. In so far as

they, regarded merely as representations, are at the same time objects

of consciousness, they are not to be distinguished from

apprehension, that is, reception into the synthesis of imagination,

and we must therefore say: "The manifold of phenomena is always

produced successively in the mind." If phenomena were things in

themselves, no man would be able to conjecture from the succession

of our representations how this manifold is connected in the object;

for we have to do only with our representations. How things may be

in themselves, without regard to the representations through which

they affect us, is utterly beyond the sphere of our cognition. Now

although phenomena are not things in themselves, and are

nevertheless the only thing given to us to be cognized, it is my

duty to show what sort of connection in time belongs to the manifold

in phenomena themselves, while the representation of this manifold

in apprehension is always successive. For example, the apprehension of

the manifold in the phenomenon of a house which stands before me, is

successive. Now comes the question whether the manifold of this

house is in itself successive- which no one will be at all willing

to grant. But, so soon as I raise my conception of an object to the

transcendental signification thereof, I find that the house is not a

thing in itself, but only a phenomenon, that is, a representation, the

transcendental object of which remains utterly unknown. What then am I

to understand by the question: "How can the manifold be connected in

the phenomenon itself- not considered as a thing in itself, but merely

as a phenomenon?" Here that which lies in my successive apprehension

is regarded as representation, whilst the phenomenon which is given

me, notwithstanding that it is nothing more than a complex of these

representations, is regarded as the object thereof, with which my

conception, drawn from the representations of apprehension, must

harmonize. It is very soon seen that, as accordance of the cognition

with its object constitutes truth, the question now before us can only

relate to the formal conditions of empirical truth; and that the

phenomenon, in opposition to the representations of apprehension,

can only be distinguished therefrom as the object of them, if it is

subject to a rule which distinguishes it from every other

apprehension, and which renders necessary a mode of connection of

the manifold. That in the phenomenon which contains the condition of

this necessary rule of apprehension, is the object.

  Let us now proceed to our task. That something happens, that is to

say, that something or some state exists which before was not,

cannot be empirically perceived, unless a phenomenon precedes, which

does not contain in itself this state. For a reality which should

follow upon a void time, in other words, a beginning, which no state

of things precedes, can just as little be apprehended as the void time

itself. Every apprehension of an event is therefore a perception which

follows upon another perception. But as this is the case with all

synthesis of apprehension, as I have shown above in the example of a

house, my apprehension of an event is not yet sufficiently

distinguished from other apprehensions. But I remark also that if in a

phenomenon which contains an occurrence, I call the antecedent state

of my perception, A, and the following state, B, the perception B

can only follow A in apprehension, and the perception A cannot

follow B, but only precede it. For example, I see a ship float down

the stream of a river. My perception of its place lower down follows

upon my perception of its place higher up the course of the river, and

it is impossible that, in the apprehension of this phenomenon, the

vessel should be perceived first below and afterwards higher up the

stream. Here, therefore, the order in the sequence of perceptions in

apprehension is determined; and by this order apprehension is

regulated. In the former example, my perceptions in the apprehension

of a house might begin at the roof and end at the foundation, or

vice versa; or I might apprehend the manifold in this empirical

intuition, by going from left to right, and from right to left.

Accordingly, in the series of these perceptions, there was no

determined order, which necessitated my beginning at a certain

point, in order empirically to connect the manifold. But this rule

is always to be met with in the perception of that which happens,

and it makes the order of the successive perceptions in the

apprehension of such a phenomenon necessary.

  I must, therefore, in the present case, deduce the subjective

sequence of apprehension from the objective sequence of phenomena, for

otherwise the former is quite undetermined, and one phenomenon is

not distinguishable from another. The former alone proves nothing as

to the connection of the manifold in an object, for it is quite

arbitrary. The latter must consist in the order of the manifold in a

phenomenon, according to which order the apprehension of one thing

(that which happens) follows that of another thing (which precedes),

in conformity with a rule. In this way alone can I be authorized to

say of the phenomenon itself, and not merely of my own apprehension,

that a certain order or sequence is to be found therein. That is, in

other words, I cannot arrange my apprehension otherwise than in this

order.

  In conformity with this rule, then, it is necessary that in that

which antecedes an event there be found the condition of a rule,

according to which in this event follows always and necessarily; but I

cannot reverse this and go back from the event, and determine (by

apprehension) that which antecedes it. For no phenomenon goes back

from the succeeding point of time to the preceding point, although

it does certainly relate to a preceding point of time; from a given

time, on the other hand, there is always a necessary progression to

the determined succeeding time. Therefore, because there certainly

is something that follows, I must of necessity connect it with

something else, which antecedes, and upon which it follows, in

conformity with a rule, that is necessarily, so that the event, as

conditioned, affords certain indication of a condition, and this

condition determines the event.

  Let us suppose that nothing precedes an event, upon which this event

must follow in conformity with a rule. All sequence of perception

would then exist only in apprehension, that is to say, would be merely

subjective, and it could not thereby be objectively determined what

thing ought to precede, and what ought to follow in perception. In

such a case, we should have nothing but a play of representations,

which would possess no application to any object. That is to say, it

would not be possible through perception to distinguish one phenomenon

from another, as regards relations of time; because the succession

in the act of apprehension would always be of the same sort, and

therefore there would be nothing in the phenomenon to determine the

succession, and to render a certain sequence objectively necessary.

And, in this case, I cannot say that two states in a phenomenon follow

one upon the other, but only that one apprehension follows upon

another. But this is merely subjective, and does not determine an

object, and consequently cannot be held to be cognition of an

object- not even in the phenomenal world.

  Accordingly, when we know in experience that something happens, we

always presuppose that something precedes, whereupon it follows in

conformity with a rule. For otherwise I could not say of the object

that it follows; because the mere succession in my apprehension, if it

be not determined by a rule in relation to something preceding, does

not authorize succession in the object. Only, therefore, in

reference to a rule, according to which phenomena are determined in

their sequence, that is, as they happen, by the preceding state, can I

make my subjective synthesis (of apprehension) objective, and it is

only under this presupposition that even the experience of an event is

possible.

  No doubt it appears as if this were in thorough contradiction to all

the notions which people have hitherto entertained in regard to the

procedure of the human understanding. According to these opinions,

it is by means of the perception and comparison of similar

consequences following upon certain antecedent phenomena that the

understanding is led to the discovery of a rule, according to which

certain events always follow certain phenomena, and it is only by this

process that we attain to the conception of cause. Upon such a

basis, it is clear that this conception must be merely empirical,

and the rule which it furnishes us with- "Everything that happens must

have a cause"- would be just as contingent as experience itself. The

universality and necessity of the rule or law would be perfectly

spurious attributes of it. Indeed, it could not possess universal

validity, inasmuch as it would not in this case be a priori, but

founded on deduction. But the same is the case with this law as with

other pure a priori representations (e.g., space and time), which we

can draw in perfect clearness and completeness from experience, only

because we had already placed them therein, and by that means, and

by that alone, had rendered experience possible. Indeed, the logical

clearness of this representation of a rule, determining the series

of events, is possible only when we have made use thereof in

experience. Nevertheless, the recognition of this rule, as a condition

of the synthetical unity of phenomena in time, was the ground of

experience itself and consequently preceded it a priori.

  It is now our duty to show by an example that we never, even in

experience, attribute to an object the notion of succession or

effect (of an event- that is, the happening of something that did

not exist before), and distinguish it from the subjective succession

of apprehension, unless when a rule lies at the foundation, which

compels us to observe this order of perception in preference to any

other, and that, indeed, it is this necessity which first renders

possible the representation of a succession in the object.

  We have representations within us, of which also we can be

conscious. But, however widely extended, however accurate and

thoroughgoing this consciousness may be, these representations are

still nothing more than representations, that is, internal

determinations of the mind in this or that relation of time. Now how

happens it that to these representations we should set an object, or

that, in addition to their subjective reality, as modifications, we

should still further attribute to them a certain unknown objective

reality? It is clear that objective significancy cannot consist in a

relation to another representation (of that which we desire to term

object), for in that case the question again arises: "How does this

other representation go out of itself, and obtain objective

significancy over and above the subjective, which is proper to it,

as a determination of a state of mind?" If we try to discover what

sort of new property the relation to an object gives to our subjective

representations, and what new importance they thereby receive, we

shall find that this relation has no other effect than that of

rendering necessary the connection of our representations in a certain

manner, and of subjecting them to a rule; and that conversely, it is

only because a certain order is necessary in the relations of time

of our representations, that objective significancy is ascribed to

them.

  In the synthesis of phenomena, the manifold of our representations

is always successive. Now hereby is not represented an object, for

by means of this succession, which is common to all apprehension, no

one thing is distinguished from another. But so soon as I perceive

or assume that in this succession there is a relation to a state

antecedent, from which the representation follows in accordance with a

rule, so soon do I represent something as an event, or as a thing that

happens; in other words, I cognize an object to which I must assign

a certain determinate position in time, which cannot be altered,

because of the preceding state in the object. When, therefore, I

perceive that something happens, there is contained in this

representation, in the first place, the fact, that something

antecedes; because, it. is only in relation to this that the

phenomenon obtains its proper relation of time, in other words, exists

after an antecedent time, in which it did not exist. But it can

receive its determined place in time only by the presupposition that

something existed in the foregoing state, upon which it follows

inevitably and always, that is, in conformity with a rule. From all

this it is evident that, in the first place, I cannot reverse the

order of succession, and make that which happens precede that upon

which it follows; and that, in the second place, if the antecedent

state be posited, a certain determinate event inevitably and

necessarily follows. Hence it follows that there exists a certain

order in our representations, whereby the present gives a sure

indication of some previously existing state, as a correlate, though

still undetermined, of the existing event which is given- a

correlate which itself relates to the event as its consequence,

conditions it, and connects it necessarily with itself in the series

of time.

  If then it be admitted as a necessary law of sensibility, and

consequently a formal condition of all perception, that the

preceding necessarily determines the succeeding time (inasmuch as I

cannot arrive at the succeeding except through the preceding), it must

likewise be an indispensable law of empirical representation of the

series of time that the phenomena of the past determine all

phenomena in the succeeding time, and that the latter, as events,

cannot take place, except in so far as the former determine their

existence in time, that is to say, establish it according to a rule.

For it is of course only in phenomena that we can empirically

cognize this continuity in the connection of times.

  For all experience and for the possibility of experience,

understanding is indispensable, and the first step which it takes in

this sphere is not to render the representation of objects clear,

but to render the representation of an object in general, possible. It

does this by applying the order of time to phenomena, and their

existence. In other words, it assigns to each phenomenon, as a

consequence, a place in relation to preceding phenomena, determined

a priori in time, without which it could not harmonize with time

itself, which determines a place a priori to all its parts. This

determination of place cannot be derived from the relation of

phenomena to absolute time (for it is not an object of perception);

but, on the contrary, phenomena must reciprocally determine the places

in time of one another, and render these necessary in the order of

time. In other words, whatever follows or happens, must follow in

conformity with a universal rule upon that which was contained in

the foregoing state. Hence arises a series of phenomena, which, by

means of the understanding, produces and renders necessary exactly the

same order and continuous connection in the series of our possible

perceptions, as is found a priori in the form of internal intuition

(time), in which all our perceptions must have place.

  That something happens, then, is a perception which belongs to a

possible experience, which becomes real only because I look upon the

phenomenon as determined in regard to its place in time,

consequently as an object, which can always be found by means of a

rule in the connected series of my perceptions. But this rule of the

determination of a thing according to succession in time is as

follows: "In what precedes may be found the condition, under which

an event always (that is, necessarily) follows." From all this it is

obvious that the principle of cause and effect is the principle of

possible experience, that is, of objective cognition of phenomena,

in regard to their relations in the succession of time.

  The proof of this fundamental proposition rests entirely on the

following momenta of argument. To all empirical cognition belongs

the synthesis of the manifold by the imagination, a synthesis which is

always successive, that is, in which the representations therein

always follow one another. But the order of succession in

imagination is not determined, and the series of successive

representations may be taken retrogressively as well as progressively.

But if this synthesis is a synthesis of apprehension (of the

manifold of a given phenomenon),then the order is determined in the

object, or to speak more accurately, there is therein an order of

successive synthesis which determines an object, and according to

which something necessarily precedes, and when this is posited,

something else necessarily follows. If, then, my perception is to

contain the cognition of an event, that is, of something which

really happens, it must be an empirical judgement, wherein we think

that the succession is determined; that is, it presupposes another

phenomenon, upon which this event follows necessarily, or in

conformity with a rule. If, on the contrary, when I posited the

antecedent, the event did not necessarily follow, I should be

obliged to consider it merely as a subjective play of my

imagination, and if in this I represented to myself anything as

objective, I must look upon it as a mere dream. Thus, the relation

of phenomena (as possible perceptions), according to which that

which happens is, as to its existence, necessarily determined in

time by something which antecedes, in conformity with a rule- in other

words, the relation of cause and effect- is the condition of the

objective validity of our empirical judgements in regard to the

sequence of perceptions, consequently of their empirical truth, and

therefore of experience. The principle of the relation of causality in

the succession of phenomena is therefore valid for all objects of

experience, because it is itself the ground of the possibility of

experience.

  Here, however, a difficulty arises, which must be resolved. The

principle of the connection of causality among phenomena is limited in

our formula to the succession thereof, although in practice we find

that the principle applies also when the phenomena exist together in

the same time, and that cause and effect may be simultaneous. For

example, there is heat in a room, which does not exist in the open

air. I look about for the cause, and find it to be the fire, Now the

fire as the cause is simultaneous with its effect, the heat of the

room. In this case, then, there is no succession as regards time,

between cause and effect, but they are simultaneous; and still the law

holds good. The greater part of operating causes in nature are

simultaneous with their effects, and the succession in time of the

latter is produced only because the cause cannot achieve the total

of its effect in one moment. But at the moment when the effect first

arises, it is always simultaneous with the causality of its cause,

because, if the cause had but a moment before ceased to be, the effect

could not have arisen. Here it must be specially remembered that we

must consider the order of time and not the lapse thereof. The

relation remains, even though no time has elapsed. The time between

the causality of the cause and its immediate effect may entirely

vanish, and the cause and effect be thus simultaneous, but the

relation of the one to the other remains always determinable according

to time. If, for example, I consider a leaden ball, which lies upon

a cushion and makes a hollow in it, as a cause, then it is

simultaneous with the effect. But I distinguish the two through the

relation of time of the dynamical connection of both. For if I lay the

ball upon the cushion, then the hollow follows upon the before

smooth surface; but supposing the cushion has, from some cause or

another, a hollow, there does not thereupon follow a leaden ball.

  Thus, the law of succession of time is in all instances the only

empirical criterion of effect in relation to the causality of the

antecedent cause. The glass is the cause of the rising of the water

above its horizontal surface, although the two phenomena are

contemporaneous. For, as soon as I draw some water with the glass from

a larger vessel, an effect follows thereupon, namely, the change of

the horizontal state which the water had in the large vessel into a

concave, which it assumes in the glass.

  This conception of causality leads us to the conception of action;

that of action, to the conception of force; and through it, to the

conception of substance. As I do not wish this critical essay, the

sole purpose of which is to treat of the sources of our synthetical

cognition a priori, to be crowded with analyses which merely

explain, but do not enlarge the sphere of our conceptions, I reserve

the detailed explanation of the above conceptions for a future

system of pure reason. Such an analysis, indeed, executed with great

particularity, may already be found in well-known works on this

subject. But I cannot at present refrain from making a few remarks

on the empirical criterion of a substance, in so far as it seems to be

more evident and more easily recognized through the conception of

action than through that of the permanence of a phenomenon.

  Where action (consequently activity and force) exists, substance

also must exist, and in it alone must be sought the seat of that

fruitful source of phenomena. Very well. But if we are called upon

to explain what we mean by substance, and wish to avoid the vice of

reasoning in a circle, the answer is by no means so easy. How shall we

conclude immediately from the action to the permanence of that which

acts, this being nevertheless an essential and peculiar criterion of

substance (phenomenon)? But after what has been said above, the

solution of this question becomes easy enough, although by the

common mode of procedure- merely analysing our conceptions- it would

be quite impossible. The conception of action indicates the relation

of the subject of causality to the effect. Now because all effect

consists in that which happens, therefore in the changeable, the

last subject thereof is the permanent, as the substratum of all that

changes, that is, substance. For according to the principle of

causality, actions are always the first ground of all change in

phenomena and, consequently, cannot be a property of a subject which

itself changes, because if this were the case, other actions and

another subject would be necessary to determine this change. From

all this it results that action alone, as an empirical criterion, is a

sufficient proof of the presence of substantiality, without any

necessity on my part of endeavouring to discover the permanence of

substance by a comparison. Besides, by this mode of induction we could

not attain to the completeness which the magnitude and strict

universality of the conception requires. For that the primary

subject of the causality of all arising and passing away, all origin

and extinction, cannot itself (in the sphere of phenomena) arise and

pass away, is a sound and safe conclusion, a conclusion which leads us

to the conception of empirical necessity and permanence in

existence, and consequently to the conception of a substance as

phenomenon.

  When something happens, the mere fact of the occurrence, without

regard to that which occurs, is an object requiring investigation. The

transition from the non-being of a state into the existence of it,

supposing that this state contains no quality which previously existed

in the phenomenon, is a fact of itself demanding inquiry. Such an

event, as has been shown in No. A, does not concern substance (for

substance does not thus originate), but its condition or state. It

is therefore only change, and not origin from nothing. If this

origin be regarded as the effect of a foreign cause, it is termed

creation, which cannot be admitted as an event among phenomena,

because the very possibility of it would annihilate the unity of

experience. If, however, I regard all things not as phenomena, but

as things in themselves and objects of understanding alone, they,

although substances, may be considered as dependent, in respect of

their existence, on a foreign cause. But this would require a very

different meaning in the words, a meaning which could not apply to

phenomena as objects of possible experience.

  How a thing can be changed, how it is possible that upon one state

existing in one point of time, an opposite state should follow in

another point of time- of this we have not the smallest conception a

priori. There is requisite for this the knowledge of real powers,

which can only be given empirically; for example, knowledge of

moving forces, or, in other words, of certain successive phenomena (as

movements) which indicate the presence of such forces. But the form of

every change, the condition under which alone it can take place as the

coming into existence of another state (be the content of the

change, that is, the state which is changed, what it may), and

consequently the succession of the states themselves can very well

be considered a priori, in relation to the law of causality and the

conditions of time.*



  *It must be remarked that I do not speak of the change of certain

relations, but of the change of the state. Thus, when a body moves

in a uniform manner, it does not change its state (of motion); but

only when all motion increases or decreases.



  When a substance passes from one state, a, into another state, b,

the point of time in which the latter exists is different from, and

subsequent to that in which the former existed. In like manner, the

second state, as reality (in the phenomenon), differs from the

first, in which the reality of the second did not exist, as b from

zero. That is to say, if the state, b, differs from the state, a, only

in respect to quantity, the change is a coming into existence of b -

a, which in the former state did not exist, and in relation to which

that state is = O.

  Now the question arises how a thing passes from one state = a,

into another state = b. Between two moments there is always a

certain time, and between two states existing in these moments there

is always a difference having a certain quantity (for all parts of

phenomena are in their turn quantities). Consequently, every

transition from one state into another is always effected in a time

contained between two moments, of which the first determines the state

which leaves, and the second determines the state into the thing

passes. the thing leaves, and the second determines the state into

which the thing Both moments, then, are limitations of the time of a

change, consequently of the intermediate state between both, and as

such they belong to the total of the change. Now every change has a

cause, which evidences its causality in the whole time during which

the charge takes place. The cause, therefore, does not produce the

change all at once or in one moment, but in a time, so that, as the

time gradually increases from the commencing instant, a, to its

completion at b, in like manner also, the quantity of the reality

(b - a) is generated through the lesser degrees which are contained

between the first and last. All change is therefore possible only

through a continuous action of the causality, which, in so far as it

is uniform, we call a momentum. The change does not consist of these

momenta, but is generated or produced by them as their effect.

  Such is the law of the continuity of all change, the ground of which

is that neither time itself nor any phenomenon in time consists of

parts which are the smallest possible, but that, notwithstanding,

the state of a thing passes in the process of a change through all

these parts, as elements, to its second state. There is no smallest

degree of reality in a phenomenon, just as there is no smallest degree

in the quantity of time; and so the new state of reality grows up

out of the former state, through all the infinite degrees thereof, the

differences of which one from another, taken all together, are less

than the difference between o and a.

  It is not our business to inquire here into the utility of this

principle in the investigation of nature. But how such a

proposition, which appears so greatly to extend our knowledge of

nature, is possible completely a priori, is indeed a question which

deserves investigation, although the first view seems to demonstrate

the truth and reality of the principle, and the question, how it is

possible, may be considered superfluous. For there are so many

groundless pretensions to the enlargement of our knowledge by pure

reason that we must take it as a general rule to be mistrustful of all

such, and without a thoroughgoing and radical deduction, to believe

nothing of the sort even on the clearest dogmatical evidence.

  Every addition to our empirical knowledge, and every advance made in

the exercise of our perception, is nothing more than an extension of

the determination of the internal sense, that is to say, a progression

in time, be objects themselves what they may, phenomena, or pure

intuitions. This progression in time determines everything, and is

itself determined by nothing else. That is to say, the parts of the

progression exist only in time, and by means of the synthesis thereof,

and are not given antecedently to it. For this reason, every

transition in perception to anything which follows upon another in

time, is a determination of time by means of the production of this

perception. And as this determination of time is, always and in all

its parts, a quantity, the perception produced is to be considered

as a quantity which proceeds through all its degrees- no one of

which is the smallest possible- from zero up to its determined degree.

From this we perceive the possibility of cognizing a priori a law of

changes- a law, however, which concerns their form merely. We merely

anticipate our own apprehension, the formal condition of which,

inasmuch as it is itself to be found in the mind antecedently to all

given phenomena, must certainly be capable of being cognized a priori.

  Thus, as time contains the sensuous condition a priori of the

possibility of a continuous progression of that which exists to that

which follows it, the understanding, by virtue of the unity of

apperception, contains the condition a priori of the possibility of

a continuous determination of the position in time of all phenomena,

and this by means of the series of causes and effects, the former of

which necessitate the sequence of the latter, and thereby render

universally and for all time, and by consequence, objectively, valid

the empirical cognition of the relations of time.



                   C. THIRD ANALOGY.



      Principle of Coexistence, According to the Law

               of Reciprocity or Community.



   All substances, in so far as they can be perceived in space

    at the same time, exist in a state of complete reciprocity

                     of action.



                        PROOF.



  Things are coexistent, when in empirical intuition the perception of

the one can follow upon the perception of the other, and vice versa-

which cannot occur in the succession of phenomena, as we have shown in

the explanation of the second principle. Thus I can perceive the

moon and then the earth, or conversely, first the earth and then the

moon; and for the reason that my perceptions of these objects can

reciprocally follow each other, I say, they exist contemporaneously.

Now coexistence is the existence of the manifold in the same time. But

time itself is not an object of perception; and therefore we cannot

conclude from the fact that things are placed in the same time, the

other fact, that the perception of these things can follow each

other reciprocally. The synthesis of the imagination in apprehension

would only present to us each of these perceptions as present in the

subject when the other is not present, and contrariwise; but would not

show that the objects are coexistent, that is to say, that, if the one

exists, the other also exists in the same time, and that this is

necessarily so, in order that the perceptions may be capable of

following each other reciprocally. It follows that a conception of the

understanding or category of the reciprocal sequence of the

determinations of phenomena (existing, as they do, apart from each

other, and yet contemporaneously), is requisite to justify us in

saying that the reciprocal succession of perceptions has its

foundation in the object, and to enable us to represent coexistence as

objective. But that relation of substances in which the one contains

determinations the ground of which is in the other substance, is the

relation of influence. And, when this influence is reciprocal, it is

the relation of community or reciprocity. Consequently the coexistence

of substances in space cannot be cognized in experience otherwise than

under the precondition of their reciprocal action. This is therefore

the condition of the possibility of things themselves as objects of

experience.

  Things are coexistent, in so far as they exist in one and the same

time. But how can we know that they exist in one and the same time?

Only by observing that the order in the synthesis of apprehension of

the manifold is arbitrary and a matter of indifference, that is to

say, that it can proceed from A, through B, C, D, to E, or

contrariwise from E to A. For if they were successive in time (and

in the order, let us suppose, which begins with A), it is quite

impossible for the apprehension in perception to begin with E and go

backwards to A, inasmuch as A belongs to past time and, therefore,

cannot be an object of apprehension.

  Let us assume that in a number of substances considered as phenomena

each is completely isolated, that is, that no one acts upon another.

Then I say that the coexistence of these cannot be an object of

possible perception and that the existence of one cannot, by any

mode of empirical synthesis, lead us to the existence of another.

For we imagine them in this case to be separated by a completely

void space, and thus perception, which proceeds from the one to the

other in time, would indeed determine their existence by means of a

following perception, but would be quite unable to distinguish whether

the one phenomenon follows objectively upon the first, or is

coexistent with it.

  Besides the mere fact of existence, then, there must be something by

means of which A determines the position of B in time and, conversely,

B the position of A; because only under this condition can

substances be empirically represented as existing contemporaneously.

Now that alone determines the position of another thing in time

which is the cause of it or of its determinations. Consequently

every substance (inasmuch as it can have succession predicated of it

only in respect of its determinations) must contain the causality of

certain determinations in another substance, and at the same time

the effects of the causality of the other in itself. That is to say,

substances must stand (mediately or immediately) in dynamical

community with each other, if coexistence is to be cognized in any

possible experience. But, in regard to objects of experience, that

is absolutely necessary without which the experience of these

objects would itself be impossible. Consequently it is absolutely

necessary that all substances in the world of phenomena, in so far

as they are coexistent, stand in a relation of complete community of

reciprocal action to each other.

  The word community has in our language* two meanings, and contains

the two notions conveyed in the Latin communio and commercium. We

employ it in this place in the latter sense- that of a dynamical

community, without which even the community of place (communio spatii)

could not be empirically cognized. In our experiences it is easy to

observe that it is only the continuous influences in all parts of

space that can conduct our senses from one object to another; that the

light which plays between our eyes and the heavenly bodies produces

a mediating community between them and us, and thereby evidences their

coexistence with us; that we cannot empirically change our position

(perceive this change), unless the existence of matter throughout

the whole of space rendered possible the perception of the positions

we occupy; and that this perception can prove the contemporaneous

existence of these places only through their reciprocal influence, and

thereby also the coexistence of even the most remote objects- although

in this case the proof is only mediate. Without community, every

perception (of a phenomenon in space) is separated from every other

and isolated, and the chain of empirical representations, that is,

of experience, must, with the appearance of a new object, begin

entirely de novo, without the least connection with preceding

representations, and without standing towards these even in the

relation of time. My intention here is by no means to combat the

notion of empty space; for it may exist where our perceptions cannot

exist, inasmuch as they cannot reach thereto, and where, therefore, no

empirical perception of coexistence takes place. But in this case it

is not an object of possible experience.



  *German.



  The following remarks may be useful in the way of explanation. In

the mind, all phenomena, as contents of a possible experience, must

exist in community (communio) of apperception or consciousness, and in

so far as it is requisite that objects be represented as coexistent

and connected, in so far must they reciprocally determine the position

in time of each other and thereby constitute a whole. If this

subjective community is to rest upon an objective basis, or to be

applied to substances as phenomena, the perception of one substance

must render possible the perception of another, and conversely. For

otherwise succession, which is always found in perceptions as

apprehensions, would be predicated of external objects, and their

representation of their coexistence be thus impossible. But this is

a reciprocal influence, that is to say, a real community

(commercium) of substances, without which therefore the empirical

relation of coexistence would be a notion beyond the reach of our

minds. By virtue of this commercium, phenomena, in so far as they

are apart from, and nevertheless in connection with each other,

constitute a compositum reale. Such composita are possible in many

different ways. The three dynamical relations then, from which all

others spring, are those of inherence, consequence, and composition.



  These, then, are the three analogies of experience. They are nothing

more than principles of the determination of the existence of

phenomena in time, according to the three modi of this

determination; to wit, the relation to time itself as a quantity

(the quantity of existence, that is, duration), the relation in time

as a series or succession, finally, the relation in time as the

complex of all existence (simultaneity). This unity of determination

in regard to time is thoroughly dynamical; that is to say, time is not

considered as that in which experience determines immediately to every

existence its position; for this is impossible, inasmuch as absolute

time is not an object of perception, by means of which phenomena can

be connected with each other. On the contrary, the rule of the

understanding, through which alone the existence of phenomena can

receive synthetical unity as regards relations of time, determines for

every phenomenon its position in time, and consequently a priori,

and with validity for all and every time.

  By nature, in the empirical sense of the word, we understand the

totality of phenomena connected, in respect of their existence,

according to necessary rules, that is, laws. There are therefore

certain laws (which are moreover a priori) which make nature possible;

and all empirical laws can exist only by means of experience, and by

virtue of those primitive laws through which experience itself becomes

possible. The purpose of the analogies is therefore to represent to us

the unity of nature in the connection of all phenomena under certain

exponents, the only business of which is to express the relation of

time (in so far as it contains all existence in itself) to the unity

of apperception, which can exist in synthesis only according to rules.

The combined expression of all is this: "All phenomena exist in one

nature, and must so exist, inasmuch as without this a priori unity, no

unity of experience, and consequently no determination of objects in

experience, is possible."

  As regards the mode of proof which we have employed in treating of

these transcendental laws of nature, and the peculiar character of

we must make one remark, which will at the same time be important as a

guide in every other attempt to demonstrate the truth of

intellectual and likewise synthetical propositions a priori. Had we

endeavoured to prove these analogies dogmatically, that is, from

conceptions; that is to say, had we employed this method in attempting

to show that everything which exists, exists only in that which is

permanent- that every thing or event presupposes the existence of

something in a preceding state, upon which it follows in conformity

with a rule- lastly, that in the manifold, which is coexistent, the

states coexist in connection with each other according to a rule-

all our labour would have been utterly in vain. For more conceptions

of things, analyse them as we may, cannot enable us to conclude from

the existence of one object to the existence of another. What other

course was left for us to pursue? This only, to demonstrate the

possibility of experience as a cognition in which at last all

objects must be capable of being presented to us, if the

representation of them is to possess any objective reality. Now in

this third, this mediating term, the essential form of which

consists in the synthetical unity of the apperception of all

phenomena, we found a priori conditions of the universal and necessary

determination as to time of all existences in the world of

phenomena, without which the empirical determination thereof as to

time would itself be impossible, and we also discovered rules of

synthetical unity a priori, by means of which we could anticipate

experience. For want of this method, and from the fancy that it was

possible to discover a dogmatical proof of the synthetical

propositions which are requisite in the empirical employment of the

understanding, has it happened that a proof of the principle of

sufficient reason has been so often attempted, and always in vain. The

other two analogies nobody has ever thought of, although they have

always been silently employed by the mind,* because the guiding thread

furnished by the categories was wanting, the guide which alone can

enable us to discover every hiatus, both in the system of

conceptions and of principles.



  *The unity of the universe, in which all phenomena to be

connected, is evidently a mere consequence of the admitted principle

of the community of all substances which are coexistent. For were

substances isolated, they could not as parts constitute a whole, and

were their connection (reciprocal action of the manifold) not

necessary from the very fact of coexistence, we could not conclude

from the fact of the latter as a merely ideal relation to the former

as a real one. We have, however, shown in its place that community

is the proper ground of the possibility of an empirical cognition of

coexistence, and that we may therefore properly reason from the latter

to the former as its condition.



           4. THE POSTULATES OF EMPIRICAL THOUGHT.



  1. That which agrees with the formal conditions (intuition and

conception) of experience, is possible.

  2. That which coheres with the material conditions of experience

(sensation), is real.

  3. That whose coherence with the real is determined according to

universal conditions of experience is (exists) necessary.



                       Explanation.



  The categories of modality possess this peculiarity, that they do

not in the least determine the object, or enlarge the conception to

which they are annexed as predicates, but only express its relation to

the faculty of cognition. Though my conception of a thing is in itself

complete, I am still entitled to ask whether the object of it is

merely possible, or whether it is also real, or, if the latter,

whether it is also necessary. But hereby the object itself is not more

definitely determined in thought, but the question is only in what

relation it, including all its determinations, stands to the

understanding and its employment in experience, to the empirical

faculty of judgement, and to the reason of its application to

experience.

  For this very reason, too, the categories of modality are nothing

more than explanations of the conceptions of possibility, reality, and

necessity, as employed in experience, and at the same time,

restrictions of all the categories to empirical use alone, not

authorizing the transcendental employment of them. For if they are

to have something more than a merely logical significance, and to be

something more than a mere analytical expression of the form of

thought, and to have a relation to things and their possibility,

reality, or necessity, they must concern possible experience and its

synthetical unity, in which alone objects of cognition can be given.

  The postulate of the possibility of things requires also, that the

conception of the things agree with the formal conditions of our

experience in general. But this, that is to say, the objective form of

experience, contains all the kinds of synthesis which are requisite

for the cognition of objects. A conception which contains a

synthesis must be regarded as empty and, without reference to an

object, if its synthesis does not belong to experience- either as

borrowed from it, and in this case it is called an empirical

conception, or such as is the ground and a priori condition of

experience (its form), and in this case it is a pure conception, a

conception which nevertheless belongs to experience, inasmuch as its

object can be found in this alone. For where shall we find the

criterion or character of the possibility of an object which is

cogitated by means of an a priori synthetical conception, if not in

the synthesis which constitutes the form of empirical cognition of

objects? That in such a conception no contradiction exists is indeed a

necessary logical condition, but very far from being sufficient to

establish the objective reality of the conception, that is, the

possibility of such an object as is thought in the conception. Thus,

in the conception of a figure which is contained within two straight

lines, there is no contradiction, for the conceptions of two

straight lines and of their junction contain no negation of a

figure. The impossibility in such a case does not rest upon the

conception in itself, but upon the construction of it in space, that

is to say, upon the conditions of space and its determinations. But

these have themselves objective reality, that is, they apply to

possible things, because they contain a priori the form of

experience in general.

  And now we shall proceed to point out the extensive utility and

influence of this postulate of possibility. When I represent to myself

a thing that is permanent, so that everything in it which changes

belongs merely to its state or condition, from such a conception alone

I never can cognize that such a thing is possible. Or, if I

represent to myself something which is so constituted that, when it is

posited, something else follows always and infallibly, my thought

contains no self-contradiction; but whether such a property as

causality is to be found in any possible thing, my thought alone

affords no means of judging. Finally, I can represent to myself

different things (substances) which are so constituted that the

state or condition of one causes a change in the state of the other,

and reciprocally; but whether such a relation is a property of

things cannot be perceived from these conceptions, which contain a

merely arbitrary synthesis. Only from the fact, therefore, that

these conceptions express a priori the relations of perceptions in

every experience, do we know that they possess objective reality, that

is, transcendental truth; and that independent of experience, though

not independent of all relation to form of an experience in general

and its synthetical unity, in which alone objects can be empirically

cognized.

  But when we fashion to ourselves new conceptions of substances,

forces, action, and reaction, from the material presented to us by

perception, without following the example of experience in their

connection, we create mere chimeras, of the possibility of which we

cannot discover any criterion, because we have not taken experience

for our instructress, though we have borrowed the conceptions from

her. Such fictitious conceptions derive their character of possibility

not, like the categories, a priori, as conceptions on which all

experience depends, but only, a posteriori, as conceptions given by

means of experience itself, and their possibility must either be

cognized a posteriori and empirically, or it cannot be cognized at

all. A substance which is permanently present in space, yet without

filling it (like that tertium quid between matter and the thinking

subject which some have tried to introduce into metaphysics), or a

peculiar fundamental power of the mind of intuiting the future by

anticipation (instead of merely inferring from past and present

events), or, finally, a power of the mind to place itself in community

of thought with other men, however distant they may be- these are

conceptions the possibility of which has no ground to rest upon. For

they are not based upon experience and its known laws; and, without

experience, they are a merely arbitrary conjunction of thoughts,

which, though containing no internal contradiction, has no claim to

objective reality, neither, consequently, to the possibility of such

an object as is thought in these conceptions. As far as concerns

reality, it is self-evident that we cannot cogitate such a possibility

in concreto without the aid of experience; because reality is

concerned only with sensation, as the matter of experience, and not

with the form of thought, with which we can no doubt indulge in

shaping fancies.

  But I pass by everything which derives its possibility from

reality in experience, and I purpose treating here merely of the

possibility of things by means of a priori conceptions. I maintain,

then, that the possibility of things is not derived from such

conceptions per se, but only when considered as formal and objective

conditions of an experience in general.

  It seems, indeed, as if the possibility of a triangle could be

cognized from the conception of it alone (which is certainly

independent of experience); for we can certainly give to the

conception a corresponding object completely a priori, that is to say,

we can construct it. But as a triangle is only the form of an

object, it must remain a mere product of the imagination, and the

possibility of the existence of an object corresponding to it must

remain doubtful, unless we can discover some other ground, unless we

know that the figure can be cogitated under the conditions upon

which all objects of experience rest. Now, the facts that space is a

formal condition a priori of external experience, that the formative

synthesis, by which we construct a triangle in imagination, is the

very same as that we employ in the apprehension of a phenomenon for

the purpose of making an empirical conception of it, are what alone

connect the notion of the possibility of such a thing, with the

conception of it. In the same manner, the possibility of continuous

quantities, indeed of quantities in general, for the conceptions of

them are without exception synthetical, is never evident from the

conceptions in themselves, but only when they are considered as the

formal conditions of the determination of objects in experience. And

where, indeed, should we look for objects to correspond to our

conceptions, if not in experience, by which alone objects are

presented to us? It is, however, true that without antecedent

experience we can cognize and characterize the possibility of

things, relatively to the formal conditions, under which something

is determined in experience as an object, consequently, completely a

priori. But still this is possible only in relation to experience

and within its limits.

  The postulate concerning the cognition of the reality of things

requires perception, consequently conscious sensation, not indeed

immediately, that is, of the object itself, whose existence is to be

cognized, but still that the object have some connection with a real

perception, in accordance with the analogies of experience, which

exhibit all kinds of real connection in experience.

  From the mere conception of a thing it is impossible to conclude its

existence. For, let the conception be ever so complete, and containing

a statement of all the determinations of the thing, the existence of

it has nothing to do with all this, but only with thew question

whether such a thing is given, so that the perception of it can in

every case precede the conception. For the fact that the conception of

it precedes the perception, merely indicates the possibility of its

existence; it is perception which presents matter to the conception,

that is the sole criterion of reality. Prior to the perception of

the thing, however, and therefore comparatively a priori, we are

able to cognize its existence, provided it stands in connection with

some perceptions according to the principles of the empirical

conjunction of these, that is, in conformity with the analogies of

perception. For, in this case, the existence of the supposed thing

is connected with our perception in a possible experience, and we

are able, with the guidance of these analogies, to reason in the

series of possible perceptions from a thing which we do really

perceive to the thing we do not perceive. Thus, we cognize the

existence of a magnetic matter penetrating all bodies from the

perception of the attraction of the steel-filings by the magnet,

although the constitution of our organs renders an immediate

perception of this matter impossible for us. For, according to the

laws of sensibility and the connected context of our perceptions, we

should in an experience come also on an immediate empirical

intuition of this matter, if our senses were more acute- but this

obtuseness has no influence upon and cannot alter the form of possible

experience in general. Our knowledge of the existence of things

reaches as far as our perceptions, and what may be inferred from

them according to empirical laws, extend. If we do not set out from

experience, or do not proceed according to the laws of the empirical

connection of phenomena, our pretensions to discover the existence

of a thing which we do not immediately perceive are vain. Idealism,

however, brings forward powerful objections to these rules for proving

existence mediately. This is, therefore, the proper place for its

refutation.



                 REFUTATION OF IDEALISM.



  Idealism- I mean material idealism- is the theory which declares the

existence of objects in space without us to be either () doubtful

and indemonstrable, or (2) false and impossible. The first is the

problematical idealism of Descartes, who admits the undoubted

certainty of only one empirical assertion (assertio), to wit, "I

am." The second is the dogmatical idealism of Berkeley, who

maintains that space, together with all the objects of which it is the

inseparable condition, is a thing which is in itself impossible, and

that consequently the objects in space are mere products of the

imagination. The dogmatical theory of idealism is unavoidable, if we

regard space as a property of things in themselves; for in that case

it is, with all to which it serves as condition, a nonentity. But

the foundation for this kind of idealism we have already destroyed

in the transcendental aesthetic. Problematical idealism, which makes

no such assertion, but only alleges our incapacity to prove the

existence of anything besides ourselves by means of immediate

experience, is a theory rational and evidencing a thorough and

philosophical mode of thinking, for it observes the rule not to form a

decisive judgement before sufficient proof be shown. The desired proof

must therefore demonstrate that we have experience of external things,

and not mere fancies. For this purpose, we must prove, that our

internal and, to Descartes, indubitable experience is itself

possible only under the previous assumption of external experience.



                        THEOREM.



    The simple but empirically determined consciousness of

       my own existence proves the existence of external

       objects in space.



                         PROOF



  I am conscious of my own existence as determined in time. All

determination in regard to time presupposes the existence of something

permanent in perception. But this permanent something cannot be

something in me, for the very reason that my existence in time is

itself determined by this permanent something. It follows that the

perception of this permanent existence is possible only through a

thing without me and not through the mere representation of a thing

without me. Consequently, the determination of my existence in time is

possible only through the existence of real things external to me.

Now, consciousness in time is necessarily connected with the

consciousness of the possibility of this determination in time.

Hence it follows that consciousness in time is necessarily connected

also with the existence of things without me, inasmuch as the

existence of these things is the condition of determination in time.

That is to say, the consciousness of my own existence is at the same

time an immediate consciousness of the existence of other things

without me.

  Remark I. The reader will observe, that in the foregoing proof the

game which idealism plays is retorted upon itself, and with more

justice. It assumed that the only immediate experience is internal and

that from this we can only infer the existence of external things.

But, as always happens, when we reason from given effects to

determined causes, idealism bas reasoned with too much haste and

uncertainty, for it is quite possible that the cause of our

representations may lie in ourselves, and that we ascribe it falsely

to external things. But our proof shows that external experience is

properly immediate,* that only by virtue of it- not, indeed, the

consciousness of our own existence, but certainly the determination of

our existence in time, that is, internal experience- is possible. It

is true, that the representation "I am," which is the expression of

the consciousness which can accompany all my thoughts, is that which

immediately includes the existence of a subject. But in this

representation we cannot find any knowledge of the subject, and

therefore also no empirical knowledge, that is, experience. For

experience contains, in addition to the thought of something existing,

intuition, and in this case it must be internal intuition, that is,

time, in relation to which the subject must be determined. But the

existence of external things is absolutely requisite for this purpose,

so that it follows that internal experience is itself possible only

mediately and through external experience.



  *The immediate consciousness of the existence of external things is,

in the preceding theorem, not presupposed, but proved, by the

possibility of this consciousness understood by us or not. The

question as to the possibility of it would stand thus: "Have we an

internal sense, but no external sense, and is our belief in external

perception a mere delusion?" But it is evident that, in order merely

to fancy to ourselves anything as external, that is, to present it

to the sense in intuition we must already possess an external sense,

and must thereby distinguish immediately the mere receptivity of an

external intuition from the spontaneity which characterizes every

act of imagination. For merely to imagine also an external sense,

would annihilate the faculty of intuition itself which is to be

determined by the imagination.



  Remark II. Now with this view all empirical use of our faculty of

cognition in the determination of time is in perfect accordance. Its

truth is supported by the fact that it is possible to perceive a

determination of time only by means of a change in external

relations (motion) to the permanent in space (for example, we become

aware of the sun's motion by observing the changes of his relation

to the objects of this earth). But this is not all. We find that we

possess nothing permanent that can correspond and be submitted to

the conception of a substance as intuition, except matter. This idea

of permanence is not itself derived from external experience, but is

an a priori necessary condition of all determination of time,

consequently also of the internal sense in reference to our own

existence, and that through the existence of external things. In the

representation "I," the consciousness of myself is not an intuition,

but a merely intellectual representation produced by the spontaneous

activity of a thinking subject. It follows, that this "I" has not

any predicate of intuition, which, in its character of permanence,

could serve as correlate to the determination of time in the

internal sense- in the same way as impenetrability is the correlate of

matter as an empirical intuition.

  Remark III. From the fact that the existence of external things is a

necessary condition of the possibility of a determined consciousness

of ourselves, it does not follow that every intuitive representation

of external things involves the existence of these things, for their

representations may very well be the mere products of the

imagination (in dreams as well as in madness); though, indeed, these

are themselves created by the reproduction of previous external

perceptions, which, as has been shown, are possible only through the

reality of external objects. The sole aim of our remarks has, however,

been to prove that internal experience in general is possible only

through external experience in general. Whether this or that

supposed experience be purely imaginary must be discovered from its

particular determinations and by comparing these with the criteria

of all real experience.



  Finally, as regards the third postulate, it applies to material

necessity in existence, and not to merely formal and logical necessity

in the connection of conceptions. Now as we cannot cognize

completely a priori the existence of any object of sense, though we

can do so comparatively a priori, that is, relatively to some other

previously given existence- a cognition, however, which can only be of

such an existence as must be contained in the complex of experience,

of which the previously given perception is a part- the necessity of

existence can never be cognized from conceptions, but always, on the

contrary, from its connection with that which is an object of

perception. But the only existence cognized, under the condition of

other given phenomena, as necessary, is the existence of effects

from given causes in conformity with the laws of causality. It is

consequently not the necessity of the existence of things (as

substances), but the necessity of the state of things that we cognize,

and that not immediately, but by means of the existence of other

states given in perception, according to empirical laws of

causality. Hence it follows that the criterion of necessity is to be

found only in the law of possible experience- that everything which

happens is determined a priori in the phenomenon by its cause. Thus we

cognize only the necessity of effects in nature, the causes of which

are given us. Moreover, the criterion of necessity in existence

possesses no application beyond the field of possible experience,

and even in this it is not valid of the existence of things as

substances, because these can never be considered as empirical

effects, or as something that happens and has a beginning.

Necessity, therefore, regards only the relations of phenomena

according to the dynamical law of causality, and the possibility

grounded thereon, of reasoning from some given existence (of a

cause) a priori to another existence (of an effect). "Everything

that happens is hypothetically necessary," is a principle which

subjects the changes that take place in the world to a law, that is,

to a rule of necessary existence, without which nature herself could

not possibly exist. Hence the proposition, "Nothing happens by blind

chance (in mundo non datur casus)," is an a priori law of nature.

The case is the same with the proposition, "Necessity in nature is not

blind," that is, it is conditioned, consequently intelligible

necessity (non datur fatum). Both laws subject the play of change to

"a nature of things (as phenomena)," or, which is the same thing, to

the unity of the understanding, and through the understanding alone

can changes belong to an experience, as the synthetical unity of

phenomena. Both belong to the class of dynamical principles. The

former is properly a consequence of the principle of causality- one of

the analogies of experience. The latter belongs to the principles of

modality, which to the determination of causality adds the

conception of necessity, which is itself, however, subject to a rule

of the understanding. The principle of continuity forbids any leap

in the series of phenomena regarded as changes (in mundo non datur

saltus); and likewise, in the complex of all empirical intuitions in

space, any break or hiatus between two phenomena (non datur hiatus)-

for we can so express the principle, that experience can admit nothing

which proves the existence of a vacuum, or which even admits it as a

part of an empirical synthesis. For, as regards a vacuum or void,

which we may cogitate as out and beyond the field of possible

experience (the world), such a question cannot come before the

tribunal of mere understanding, which decides only upon questions that

concern the employment of given phenomena for the construction of

empirical cognition. It is rather a problem for ideal reason, which

passes beyond the sphere of a possible experience and aims at

forming a judgement of that which surrounds and circumscribes it,

and the proper place for the consideration of it is the transcendental

dialectic. These four propositions, "In mundo non datur hiatus, non

datur saltus, non datur casus, non datur fatum," as well as all

principles of transcendental origin, we could very easily exhibit in

their proper order, that is, in conformity with the order of the

categories, and assign to each its proper place. But the already

practised reader will do this for himself, or discover the clue to

such an arrangement. But the combined result of all is simply this, to

admit into the empirical synthesis nothing which might cause a break

in or be foreign to the understanding and the continuous connection of

all phenomena, that is, the unity of the conceptions of the

understanding. For in the understanding alone is the unity of

experience, in which all perceptions must have their assigned place,

possible.

  Whether the field of possibility be greater than that of reality,

and whether the field of the latter be itself greater than that of

necessity, are interesting enough questions, and quite capable of

synthetic solution, questions, however, which come under the

jurisdiction of reason alone. For they are tantamount to asking

whether all things as phenomena do without exception belong to the

complex and connected whole of a single experience, of which every

given perception is a part which therefore cannot be conjoined with

any other phenomena- or, whether my perceptions can belong to more

than one possible experience? The understanding gives to experience,

according to the subjective and formal conditions, of sensibility as

well as of apperception, the rules which alone make this experience

possible. Other forms of intuition besides those of space and time,

other forms of understanding besides the discursive forms of

thought, or of cognition by means of conceptions, we can neither

imagine nor make intelligible to ourselves; and even if we could, they

would still not belong to experience, which is the only mode of

cognition by which objects are presented to us. Whether other

perceptions besides those which belong to the total of our possible

experience, and consequently whether some other sphere of matter

exists, the understanding has no power to decide, its proper

occupation being with the synthesis of that which is given.

Moreover, the poverty of the usual arguments which go to prove the

existence of a vast sphere of possibility, of which all that is real

(every object of experience) is but a small part, is very

remarkable. "All real is possible"; from this follows naturally,

according to the logical laws of conversion, the particular

proposition: "Some possible is real." Now this seems to be

equivalent to: "Much is possible that is not real." No doubt it does

seem as if we ought to consider the sum of the possible to be

greater than that of the real, from the fact that something must be

added to the former to constitute the latter. But this notion of

adding to the possible is absurd. For that which is not in the sum

of the possible, and consequently requires to be added to it, is

manifestly impossible. In addition to accordance with the formal

conditions of experience, the understanding requires a connection with

some perception; but that which is connected with this perception is

real, even although it is not immediately perceived. But that

another series of phenomena, in complete coherence with that which

is given in perception, consequently more than one all-embracing

experience is possible, is an inference which cannot be concluded from

the data given us by experience, and still less without any data at

all. That which is possible only under conditions which are themselves

merely possible, is not possible in any respect. And yet we can find

no more certain ground on which to base the discussion of the question

whether the sphere of possibility is wider than that of experience.

  I have merely mentioned these questions, that in treating of the

conception of the understanding, there might be no omission of

anything that, in the common opinion, belongs to them. In reality,

however, the notion of absolute possibility (possibility which is

valid in every respect) is not a mere conception of the understanding,

which can be employed empirically, but belongs to reason alone,

which passes the bounds of all empirical use of the understanding.

We have, therefore, contented ourselves with a merely critical remark,

leaving the subject to be explained in the sequel.

  Before concluding this fourth section, and at the same time the

system of all principles of the pure understanding, it seems proper to

mention the reasons which induced me to term the principles of

modality postulates. This expression I do not here use in the sense

which some more recent philosophers, contrary to its meaning with

mathematicians, to whom the word properly belongs, attach to it-

that of a proposition, namely, immediately certain, requiring

neither deduction nor proof. For if, in the case of synthetical

propositions, however evident they may be, we accord to them without

deduction, and merely on the strength of their own pretensions,

unqualified belief, all critique of the understanding is entirely

lost; and, as there is no want of bold pretensions, which the common

belief (though for the philosopher this is no credential) does not

reject, the understanding lies exposed to every delusion and

conceit, without the power of refusing its assent to those assertions,

which, though illegitimate, demand acceptance as veritable axioms.

When, therefore, to the conception of a thing an a priori

determination is synthetically added, such a proposition must

obtain, if not a proof, at least a deduction of the legitimacy of

its assertion.

  The principles of modality are, however, not objectively

synthetical, for the predicates of possibility, reality, and necessity

do not in the least augment the conception of that of which they are

affirmed, inasmuch as they contribute nothing to the representation of

the object. But as they are, nevertheless, always synthetical, they

are so merely subjectively. That is to say, they have a reflective

power, and apply to the conception of a thing, of which, in other

respects, they affirm nothing, the faculty of cognition in which the

conception originates and has its seat. So that if the conception

merely agree with the formal conditions of experience, its object is

called possible; if it is in connection with perception, and

determined thereby, the object is real; if it is determined

according to conceptions by means of the connection of perceptions,

the object is called necessary. The principles of modality therefore

predicate of a conception nothing more than the procedure of the

faculty of cognition which generated it. Now a postulate in

mathematics is a practical proposition which contains nothing but

the synthesis by which we present an object to ourselves, and

produce the conception of it, for example- "With a given line, to

describe a circle upon a plane, from a given point"; and such a

proposition does not admit of proof, because the procedure, which it

requires, is exactly that by which alone it is possible to generate

the conception of such a figure. With the same right, accordingly, can

we postulate the principles of modality, because they do not

augment* the conception of a thing but merely indicate the manner in

which it is connected with the faculty of cognition.



  *When I think the reality of a thing, I do really think more than

the possibility, but not in the thing; for that can never contain more

in reality than was contained in its complete possibility. But while

the notion of possibility is merely the notion of a position of

thing in relation to the understanding (its empirical use), reality is

the conjunction of the thing with perception.



           GENERAL REMARK ON THE SYSTEM OF PRINCIPLES.



  It is very remarkable that we cannot perceive the possibility of a

thing from the category alone, but must always have an intuition, by

which to make evident the objective reality of the pure conception

of the understanding. Take, for example, the categories of relation.

How (1) a thing can exist only as a subject, and not as a mere

determination of other things, that is, can be substance; or how

(2), because something exists, some other thing must exist,

consequently how a thing can be a cause; or how (3), when several

things exist, from the fact that one of these things exists, some

consequence to the others follows, and reciprocally, and in this way a

community of substances can be possible- are questions whose

solution cannot be obtained from mere conceptions. The very same is

the case with the other categories; for example, how a thing can be of

the same sort with many others, that is, can be a quantity, and so on.

So long as we have not intuition we cannot know whether we do really

think an object by the categories, and where an object can anywhere be

found to cohere with them, and thus the truth is established, that the

categories are not in themselves cognitions, but mere forms of thought

for the construction of cognitions from given intuitions. For the same

reason is it true that from categories alone no synthetical

proposition can be made. For example: "In every existence there is

substance," that is, something that can exist only as a subject and

not as mere predicate; or, "Everything is a quantity"- to construct

propositions such as these, we require something to enable us to go

out beyond the given conception and connect another with it. For the

same reason the attempt to prove a synthetical proposition by means of

mere conceptions, for example: "Everything that exists contingently

has a cause," has never succeeded. We could never get further than

proving that, without this relation to conceptions, we could not

conceive the existence of the contingent, that is, could not a

priori through the understanding cognize the existence of such a

thing; but it does not hence follow that this is also the condition of

the possibility of the thing itself that is said to be contingent. If,

accordingly; we look back to our proof of the principle of

causality, we shall find that we were able to prove it as valid only

of objects of possible experience, and, indeed, only as itself the

principle of the possibility of experience, Consequently of the

cognition of an object given in empirical intuition, and not from mere

conceptions. That, however, the proposition: "Everything that is

contingent must have a cause," is evident to every one merely from

conceptions, is not to be denied. But in this case the conception of

the contingent is cogitated as involving not the category of

modality (as that the non-existence of which can be conceive but

that of relation (as that which can exist only as the consequence of

something else), and so it is really an identical proposition: "That

which can exist only as a consequence, has a cause." In fact, when

we have to give examples of contingent existence, we always refer to

changes, and not merely to the possibility of conceiving the

opposite.* But change is an event, which, as such, is possible only

through a cause, and considered per se its non-existence is

therefore possible, and we become cognizant of its contingency from

the fact that it can exist only as the effect of a cause. Hence, if

a thing is assumed to be contingent, it is an analytical proposition

to say, it has a cause.



  *We can easily conceive the non-existence of matter; but the

ancients did not thence infer its contingency. But even the

alternation of the existence and non-existence of a given state in a

thing, in which all change consists, by no means proves the

contingency of that state- the ground of proof being the reality of

its opposite. For example, a body is in a state of rest after

motion, but we cannot infer the contingency of the motion from the

fact that the former is the opposite of the latter. For this

opposite is merely a logical and not a real opposite to the other.

If we wish to demonstrate the contingency of the motion, what we ought

to prove is that, instead of the motion which took place in the

preceding point of time, it was possible for the body to have been

then in rest, not, that it is afterwards in rest; for in this case,

both opposites are perfectly consistent with each other.



  But it is still more remarkable that, to understand the

possibility of things according to the categories and thus to

demonstrate the objective reality of the latter, we require not merely

intuitions, but external intuitions. If, for example, we take the pure

conceptions of relation, we find that (1) for the purpose of

presenting to the conception of substance something permanent in

intuition corresponding thereto and thus of demonstrating the

objective reality of this conception, we require an intuition (of

matter) in space, because space alone is permanent and determines

things as such, while time, and with it all that is in the internal

sense, is in a state of continual flow; (2) in order to represent

change as the intuition corresponding to the conception of

causality, we require the representation of motion as change in space;

in fact, it is through it alone that changes, the possibility of which

no pure understanding can perceive, are capable of being intuited.

Change is the connection of determinations contradictorily opposed

to each other in the existence of one and the same thing. Now, how

it is possible that out of a given state one quite opposite to it in

the same thing should follow, reason without an example can not only

not conceive, but cannot even make intelligible without intuition; and

this intuition is the motion of a point in space; the existence of

which in different spaces (as a consequence of opposite

determinations) alone makes the intuition of change possible. For,

in order to make even internal change cognitable, we require to

represent time, as the form of the internal sense, figuratively by a

line, and the internal change by the drawing of that line (motion),

and consequently are obliged to employ external intuition to be able

to represent the successive existence of ourselves in different

states. The proper ground of this fact is that all change to be

perceived as change presupposes something permanent in intuition,

while in the internal sense no permanent intuition is to be found.

Lastly, the objective possibility of the category of community

cannot be conceived by mere reason, and consequently its objective

reality cannot be demonstrated without an intuition, and that external

in space. For how can we conceive the possibility of community, that

is, when several substances exist, that some effect on the existence

of the one follows from the existence of the other, and

reciprocally, and therefore that, because something exists in the

latter, something else must exist in the former, which could not be

understood from its own existence alone? For this is the very

essence of community- which is inconceivable as a property of things

which are perfectly isolated. Hence, Leibnitz, in attributing to the

substances of the world- as cogitated by the understanding alone- a

community, required the mediating aid of a divinity; for, from their

existence, such a property seemed to him with justice inconceivable.

But we can very easily conceive the possibility of community (of

substances as phenomena) if we represent them to ourselves as in

space, consequently in external intuition. For external intuition

contains in itself a priori formal external relations, as the

conditions of the possibility of the real relations of action and

reaction, and therefore of the possibility of community. With the same

ease can it be demonstrated, that the possibility of things as

quantities, and consequently the objective reality of the category

of quantity, can be grounded only in external intuition, and that by

its means alone is the notion of quantity appropriated by the internal

sense. But I must avoid prolixity, and leave the task of

illustrating this by examples to the reader's own reflection.

  The above remarks are of the greatest importance, not only for the

confirmation of our previous confutation of idealism, but still more

when the subject of self-cognition by mere internal consciousness

and the determination of our own nature without the aid of external

empirical intuitions is under discussion, for the indication of the

grounds of the possibility of such a cognition.

  The result of the whole of this part of the analytic of principles

is, therefore: "All principles of the pure understanding are nothing

more than a priori principles of the possibility of experience, and to

experience alone do all a priori synthetical propositions apply and

relate"; indeed, their possibility itself rests entirely on this

relation.

    CHAPTER III Of the Ground of the Division of all Objects

                 into Phenomena and Noumena.



  We have now not only traversed the region of the pure

understanding and carefully surveyed every part of it, but we have

also measured it, and assigned to everything therein its proper place.

But this land is an island, and enclosed by nature herself within

unchangeable limits. It is the land of truth (an attractive word),

surrounded by a wide and stormy ocean, the region of illusion, where

many a fog-bank, many an iceberg, seems to the mariner, on his

voyage of discovery, a new country, and, while constantly deluding him

with vain hopes, engages him in dangerous adventures, from which he

never can desist, and which yet he never can bring to a termination.

But before venturing upon this sea, in order to explore it in its

whole extent, and to arrive at a certainty whether anything is to be

discovered there, it will not be without advantage if we cast our eyes

upon the chart of the land that we are about to leave, and to ask

ourselves, firstly, whether we cannot rest perfectly contented with

what it contains, or whether we must not of necessity be contented

with it, if we can find nowhere else a solid foundation to build upon;

and, secondly, by what title we possess this land itself, and how we

hold it secure against all hostile claims? Although, in the course

of our analytic, we have already given sufficient answers to these

questions, yet a summary recapitulation of these solutions may be

useful in strengthening our conviction, by uniting in one point the

momenta of the arguments.

  We have seen that everything which the understanding draws from

itself, without borrowing from experience, it nevertheless possesses

only for the behoof and use of experience. The principles of the

pure understanding, whether constitutive a priori (as the mathematical

principles), or merely regulative (as the dynamical), contain

nothing but the pure schema, as it were, of possible experience. For

experience possesses its unity from the synthetical unity which the

understanding, originally and from itself, imparts to the synthesis of

the imagination in relation to apperception, and in a priori

relation to and agreement with which phenomena, as data for a possible

cognition, must stand. But although these rules of the understanding

are not only a priori true, but the very source of all truth, that is,

of the accordance of our cognition with objects, and on this ground,

that they contain the basis of the possibility of experience, as the

ensemble of all cognition, it seems to us not enough to propound

what is true- we desire also to be told what we want to know. If,

then, we learn nothing more by this critical examination than what

we should have practised in the merely empirical use of the

understanding, without any such subtle inquiry, the presumption is

that the advantage we reap from it is not worth the labour bestowed

upon it. It may certainly be answered that no rash curiosity is more

prejudicial to the enlargement of our knowledge than that which must

know beforehand the utility of this or that piece of information which

we seek, before we have entered on the needful investigations, and

before one could form the least conception of its utility, even though

it were placed before our eyes. But there is one advantage in such

transcendental inquiries which can be made comprehensible to the

dullest and most reluctant learner- this, namely, that the

understanding which is occupied merely with empirical exercise, and

does not reflect on the sources of its own cognition, may exercise its

functions very well and very successfully, but is quite unable to do

one thing, and that of very great importance, to determine, namely,

the bounds that limit its employment, and to know what lies within

or without its own sphere. This purpose can be obtained only by such

profound investigations as we have instituted. But if it cannot

distinguish whether certain questions lie within its horizon or not,

it can never be sure either as to its claims or possessions, but

must lay its account with many humiliating corrections, when it

transgresses, as it unavoidably will, the limits of its own territory,

and loses itself in fanciful opinions and blinding illusions.

  That the understanding, therefore, cannot make of its a priori

principles, or even of its conceptions, other than an empirical use,

is a proposition which leads to the most important results. A

transcendental use is made of a conception in a fundamental

proposition or principle, when it is referred to things in general and

considered as things in themselves; an empirical use, when it is

referred merely to phenomena, that is, to objects of a possible

experience. That the latter use of a conception is the only admissible

one is evident from the reasons following. For every conception are

requisite, firstly, the logical form of a conception (of thought)

general; and, secondly, the possibility of presenting to this an

object to which it may apply. Failing this latter, it has no sense,

and utterly void of content, although it may contain the logical

function for constructing a conception from certain data. Now,

object cannot be given to a conception otherwise than by intuition,

and, even if a pure intuition antecedent to the object is a priori

possible, this pure intuition can itself obtain objective validity

only from empirical intuition, of which it is itself but the form. All

conceptions, therefore, and with them all principles, however high the

degree of their a priori possibility, relate to empirical

intuitions, that is, to data towards a possible experience. Without

this they possess no objective validity, but are mere play of

imagination or of understanding with images or notions. Let us take,

for example, the conceptions of mathematics, and first in its pure

intuitions. "Space has three dimensions"- "Between two points there

can be only one straight line," etc. Although all these principles,

and the representation of the object with which this science

occupies itself, are generated in the mind entirely a priori, they

would nevertheless have no significance if we were not always able

to exhibit their significance in and by means of phenomena

(empirical objects). Hence it is requisite that an abstract conception

be made sensuous, that is, that an object corresponding to it in

intuition be forthcoming, otherwise the conception remains, as we say,

without sense, that is, without meaning. Mathematics fulfils this

requirement by the construction of the figure, which is a phenomenon

evident to the senses. The same science finds support and significance

in number; this in its turn finds it in the fingers, or in counters,

or in lines and points. The conception itself is always produced a

priori, together with the synthetical principles or formulas from such

conceptions; but the proper employment of them, and their

application to objects, can exist nowhere but in experience, the

possibility of which, as regards its form, they contain a priori.

  That this is also the case with all of the categories and the

principles based upon them is evident from the fact that we cannot

render intelligible the possibility of an object corresponding to them

without having recourse to the conditions of sensibility,

consequently, to the form of phenomena, to which, as their only proper

objects, their use must therefore be confined, inasmuch as, if this

condition is removed, all significance, that is, all relation to an

object, disappears, and no example can be found to make it

comprehensible what sort of things we ought to think under such

conceptions.

  The conception of quantity cannot be explained except by saying that

it is the determination of a thing whereby it can be cogitated how

many times one is placed in it. But this "how many times" is based

upon successive repetition, consequently upon time and the synthesis

of the homogeneous therein. Reality, in contradistinction to negation,

can be explained only by cogitating a time which is either filled

therewith or is void. If I leave out the notion of permanence (which

is existence in all time), there remains in the conception of

substance nothing but the logical notion of subject, a notion of which

I endeavour to realize by representing to myself something that can

exist only as a subject. But not only am I perfectly ignorant of any

conditions under which this logical prerogative can belong to a thing,

I can make nothing out of the notion, and draw no inference from it,

because no object to which to apply the conception is determined,

and we consequently do not know whether it has any meaning at all.

In like manner, if I leave out the notion of time, in which

something follows upon some other thing in conformity with a rule, I

can find nothing in the pure category, except that there is a

something of such a sort that from it a conclusion may be drawn as

to the existence of some other thing. But in this case it would not

only be impossible to distinguish between a cause and an effect,

but, as this power to draw conclusions requires conditions of which

I am quite ignorant, the conception is not determined as to the mode

in which it ought to apply to an object. The so-called principle:

"Everything that is contingent has a cause," comes with a gravity

and self-assumed authority that seems to require no support from

without. But, I ask, what is meant by contingent? The answer is that

the non-existence of which is possible. But I should like very well to

know by what means this possibility of non-existence is to be

cognized, if we do not represent to ourselves a succession in the

series of phenomena, and in this succession an existence which follows

a non-existence, or conversely, consequently, change. For to say, that

the non-existence of a thing is not self-contradictory is a lame

appeal to a logical condition, which is no doubt a necessary condition

of the existence of the conception, but is far from being sufficient

for the real objective possibility of non-existence. I can

annihilate in thought every existing substance without

self-contradiction, but I cannot infer from this their objective

contingency in existence, that is to say, the possibility of their

non-existence in itself. As regards the category of community, it

may easily be inferred that, as the pure categories of substance and

causality are incapable of a definition and explanation sufficient

to determine their object without the aid of intuition, the category

of reciprocal causality in the relation of substances to each other

(commercium) is just as little susceptible thereof. Possibility,

existence, and necessity nobody has ever yet been able to explain

without being guilty of manifest tautology, when the definition has

been drawn entirely from the pure understanding. For the

substitution of the logical possibility of the conception- the

condition of which is that it be not self-contradictory, for the

transcendental possibility of things- the condition of which is that

there be an object corresponding to the conception, is a trick which

can only deceive the inexperienced.*



  *In one word, to none of these conceptions belongs a corresponding

object, and consequently their real possibility cannot be

demonstrated, if we take away sensuous intuition- the only intuition

which we possess- and there then remains nothing but the logical

possibility, that is, the fact that the conception or thought is

possible- which, however, is not the question; what we want to know

being, whether it relates to an object and thus possesses any meaning.



  It follows incontestably, that the pure conceptions of the

understanding are incapable of transcendental, and must always be of

empirical use alone, and that the principles of the pure understanding

relate only to the general conditions of a possible experience, to

objects of the senses, and never to things in general, apart from

the mode in which we intuite them.

  Transcendental analytic has accordingly this important result, to

wit, that the understanding is competent' effect nothing a priori,

except the anticipation of the form of a possible experience in

general, and that, as that which is not phenomenon cannot be an object

of experience, it can never overstep the limits of sensibility, within

which alone objects are presented to us. Its principles are merely

principles of the exposition of phenomena, and the proud name of an

ontology, which professes to present synthetical cognitions a priori

of things in general in a systematic doctrine, must give place to

the modest title of analytic of the pure understanding.

  Thought is the act of referring a given intuition to an object. If

the mode of this intuition is unknown to us, the object is merely

transcendental, and the conception of the understanding is employed

only transcendentally, that is, to produce unity in the thought of a

manifold in general. Now a pure category, in which all conditions of

sensuous intuition- as the only intuition we possess- are

abstracted, does not determine an object, but merely expresses the

thought of an object in general, according to different modes. Now, to

employ a conception, the function of judgement is required, by which

an object is subsumed under the conception, consequently the at

least formal condition, under which something can be given in

intuition. Failing this condition of judgement (schema), subsumption

is impossible; for there is in such a case nothing given, which may be

subsumed under the conception. The merely transcendental use of the

categories is therefore, in fact, no use at all and has no determined,

or even, as regards its form, determinable object. Hence it follows

that the pure category is incompetent to establish a synthetical a

priori principle, and that the principles of the pure understanding

are only of empirical and never of transcendental use, and that beyond

the sphere of possible experience no synthetical a priori principles

are possible.

  It may be advisable, therefore, to express ourselves thus. The

pure categories, apart from the formal conditions of sensibility, have

a merely transcendental meaning, but are nevertheless not of

transcendental use, because this is in itself impossible, inasmuch

as all the conditions of any employment or use of them (in judgements)

are absent, to wit, the formal conditions of the subsumption of an

object under these conceptions. As, therefore, in the character of

pure categories, they must be employed empirically, and cannot be

employed transcendentally, they are of no use at all, when separated

from sensibility, that is, they cannot be applied to an object. They

are merely the pure form of the employment of the understanding in

respect of objects in general and of thought, without its being at the

same time possible to think or to determine any object by their means.

  But there lurks at the foundation of this subject an illusion

which it is very difficult to avoid. The categories are not based,

as regards their origin, upon sensibility, like the forms of

intuition, space, and time; they seem, therefore, to be capable of

an application beyond the sphere of sensuous objects. But this is

not the case. They are nothing but mere forms of thought, which

contain only the logical faculty of uniting a priori in

consciousness the manifold given in intuition. Apart, then, from the

only intuition possible for us, they have still less meaning than

the pure sensuous forms, space and time, for through them an object is

at least given, while a mode of connection of the manifold, when the

intuition which alone gives the manifold is wanting, has no meaning at

all. At the same time, when we designate certain objects as

phenomena or sensuous existences, thus distinguishing our mode of

intuiting them from their own nature as things in themselves, it is

evident that by this very distinction we as it were place the

latter, considered in this their own nature, although we do not so

intuite them, in opposition to the former, or, on the other hand, we

do so place other possible things, which are not objects of our

senses, but are cogitated by the understanding alone, and call them

intelligible existences (noumena). Now the question arises whether the

pure conceptions of our understanding do possess significance in

respect of these latter, and may possibly be a mode of cognizing them.

  But we are met at the very commencement with an ambiguity, which may

easily occasion great misapprehension. The understanding, when it

terms an object in a certain relation phenomenon, at the same time

forms out of this relation a representation or notion of an object

in itself, and hence believes that it can form also conceptions of

such objects. Now as the understanding possesses no other

fundamental conceptions besides the categories, it takes for granted

that an object considered as a thing in itself must be capable of

being thought by means of these pure conceptions, and is thereby led

to hold the perfectly undetermined conception of an intelligible

existence, a something out of the sphere of our sensibility, for a

determinate conception of an existence which we can cognize in some

way or other by means of the understanding.

  If, by the term noumenon, we understand a thing so far as it is

not an object of our sensuous intuition, thus making abstraction of

our mode of intuiting it, this is a noumenon in the negative sense

of the word. But if we understand by it an object of a non-sensuous

intuition, we in this case assume a peculiar mode of intuition, an

intellectual intuition, to wit, which does not, however, belong to us,

of the very possibility of which we have no notion- and this is a

noumenon in the positive sense.

  The doctrine of sensibility is also the doctrine of noumena in the

negative sense, that is, of things which the understanding is

obliged to cogitate apart from any relation to our mode of

intuition, consequently not as mere phenomena, but as things in

themselves. But the understanding at the same time comprehends that it

cannot employ its categories for the consideration of things in

themselves, because these possess significance only in relation to the

unity of intuitions in space and time, and that they are competent

to determine this unity by means of general a priori connecting

conceptions only on account of the pure ideality of space and time.

Where this unity of time is not to be met with, as is the case with

noumena, the whole use, indeed the whole meaning of the categories

is entirely lost, for even the possibility of things to correspond

to the categories is in this case incomprehensible. On this point, I

need only refer the reader to what I have said at the commencement

of the General Remark appended to the foregoing chapter. Now, the

possibility of a thing can never be proved from the fact that the

conception of it is not self-contradictory, but only by means of an

intuition corresponding to the conception. If, therefore, we wish to

apply the categories to objects which cannot be regarded as phenomena,

we must have an intuition different from the sensuous, and in this

case the objects would be a noumena in the positive sense of the word.

Now, as such an intuition, that is, an intellectual intuition, is no

part of our faculty of cognition, it is absolutely impossible for

the categories to possess any application beyond the limits of

experience. It may be true that there are intelligible existences to

which our faculty of sensuous intuition has no relation, and cannot be

applied, but our conceptions of the understanding, as mere forms of

thought for our sensuous intuition, do not extend to these. What,

therefore, we call noumenon must be understood by us as such in a

negative sense.

  If I take away from an empirial intuition all thought (by means of

the categories), there remains no cognition of any object; for by

means of mere intuition nothing is cogitated, and, from the

existence of such or such an affection of sensibility in me, it does

not follow that this affection or representation has any relation to

an object without me. But if I take away all intuition, there still

remains the form of thought, that is, the mode of determining an

object for the manifold of a possible intuition. Thus the categories

do in some measure really extend further than sensuous intuition,

inasmuch as they think objects in general, without regard to the

mode (of sensibility) in which these objects are given. But they do

not for this reason apply to and determine a wider sphere of

objects, because we cannot assume that such can be given, without

presupposing the possibility of another than the sensuous mode of

intuition, a supposition we are not justified in making.

  I call a conception problematical which contains in itself no

contradiction, and which is connected with other cognitions as a

limitation of given conceptions, but whose objective reality cannot be

cognized in any manner. The conception of a noumenon, that is, of a

thing which must be cogitated not as an object of sense, but as a

thing in itself (solely through the pure understanding), is not

self-contradictory, for we are not entitled to maintain that

sensibility is the only possible mode of intuition. Nay, further, this

conception is necessary to restrain sensuous intuition within the

bounds of phenomena, and thus to limit the objective validity of

sensuous cognition; for things in themselves, which lie beyond its

province, are called noumena for the very purpose of indicating that

this cognition does not extend its application to all that the

understanding thinks. But, after all, the possibility of such

noumena is quite incomprehensible, and beyond the sphere of phenomena,

all is for us a mere void; that is to say, we possess an understanding

whose province does problematically extend beyond this sphere, but

we do not possess an intuition, indeed, not even the conception of a

possible intuition, by means of which objects beyond the region of

sensibility could be given us, and in reference to which the

understanding might be employed assertorically. The conception of a

noumenon is therefore merely a limitative conception and therefore

only of negative use. But it is not an arbitrary or fictitious notion,

but is connected with the limitation of sensibility, without, however,

being capable of presenting us with any positive datum beyond this

sphere.

  The division of objects into phenomena and noumena, and of the world

into a mundus sensibilis and intelligibilis is therefore quite

inadmissible in a positive sense, although conceptions do certainly

admit of such a division; for the class of noumena have no determinate

object corresponding to them, and cannot therefore possess objective

validity. If we abandon the senses, how can it be made conceivable

that the categories (which are the only conceptions that could serve

as conceptions for noumena) have any sense or meaning at all, inasmuch

as something more than the mere unity of thought, namely, a possible

intuition, is requisite for their application to an object? The

conception of a noumenon, considered as merely problematical, is,

however, not only admissible, but, as a limitative conception of

sensibility, absolutely necessary. But, in this case, a noumenon is

not a particular intelligible object for our understanding; on the

contrary, the kind of understanding to which it could belong is itself

a problem, for we cannot form the most distant conception of the

possibility of an understanding which should cognize an object, not

discursively by means of categories, but intuitively in a non-sensuous

intuition. Our understanding attains in this way a sort of negative

extension. That is to say, it is not limited by, but rather limits,

sensibility, by giving the name of noumena to things, not considered

as phenomena, but as things in themselves. But it at the same time

prescribes limits to itself, for it confesses itself unable to cognize

these by means of the categories, and hence is compelled to cogitate

them merely as an unknown something.

  I find, however, in the writings of modern authors, an entirely

different use of the expressions, mundus sensibilis and

intelligibilis, which quite departs from the meaning of the

ancients- an acceptation in which, indeed, there is to be found no

difficulty, but which at the same time depends on mere verbal

quibbling. According to this meaning, some have chosen to call the

complex of phenomena, in so far as it is intuited, mundus

sensibilis, but in so far as the connection thereof is cogitated

according to general laws of thought, mundus intelligibilis.

Astronomy, in so far as we mean by the word the mere observation of

the starry heaven, may represent the former; a system of astronomy,

such as the Copernican or Newtonian, the latter. But such twisting

of words is a mere sophistical subterfuge, to avoid a difficult

question, by modifying its meaning to suit our own convenience. To

be sure, understanding and reason are employed in the cognition of

phenomena; but the question is, whether these can be applied when

the object is not a phenomenon and in this sense we regard it if it is

cogitated as given to the understanding alone, and not to the

senses. The question therefore is whether, over and above the

empirical use of the understanding, a transcendental use is

possible, which applies to the noumenon as an object. This question we

have answered in the negative.

  When therefore we say, the senses represent objects as they

appear, the understanding as they are, the latter statement must not

be understood in a transcendental, but only in an empirical

signification, that is, as they must be represented in the complete

connection of phenomena, and not according to what they may be,

apart from their relation to possible experience, consequently not

as objects of the pure understanding. For this must ever remain

unknown to us. Nay, it is also quite unknown to us whether any such

transcendental or extraordinary cognition is possible under any

circumstances, at least, whether it is possible by means of our

categories. Understanding and sensibility, with us, can determine

objects only in conjunction. If we separate them, we have intuitions

without conceptions, or conceptions without intuitions; in both cases,

representations, which we cannot apply to any determinate object.

  If, after all our inquiries and explanations, any one still

hesitates to abandon the mere transcendental use of the categories,

let him attempt to construct with them a synthetical proposition. It

would, of course, be unnecessary for this purpose to construct an

analytical proposition, for that does not extend the sphere of the

understanding, but, being concerned only about what is cogitated in

the conception itself, it leaves it quite undecided whether the

conception has any relation to objects, or merely indicates the

unity of thought- complete abstraction being made of the modi in which

an object may be given: in such a proposition, it is sufficient for

the understanding to know what lies in the conception- to what it

applies is to it indifferent. The attempt must therefore be made

with a synthetical and so-called transcendental principle, for

example: "Everything that exists, exists as substance," or,

"Everything that is contingent exists as an effect of some other

thing, viz., of its cause." Now I ask, whence can the understanding

draw these synthetical propositions, when the conceptions contained

therein do not relate to possible experience but to things in

themselves (noumena)? Where is to be found the third term, which is

always requisite PURE site in a synthetical proposition, which may

connect in the same proposition conceptions which have no logical

(analytical) connection with each other? The proposition never will be

demonstrated, nay, more, the possibility of any such pure assertion

never can be shown, without making reference to the empirical use of

the understanding, and thus, ipso facto, completely renouncing pure

and non-sensuous judgement. Thus the conception of pure and merely

intelligible objects is completely void of all principles of its

application, because we cannot imagine any mode in which they might be

given, and the problematical thought which leaves a place open for

them serves only, like a void space, to limit the use of empirical

principles, without containing at the same time any other object of

cognition beyond their sphere.

APPENDIX

                         APPENDIX.



   Of the Equivocal Nature or Amphiboly of the Conceptions of

     Reflection from the Confusion of the Transcendental with

     the Empirical use of the Understanding.



  Reflection (reflexio) is not occupied about objects themselves,

for the purpose of directly obtaining conceptions of them, but is that

state of the mind in which we set ourselves to discover the subjective

conditions under which we obtain conceptions. It is the

consciousness of the relation of given representations to the

different sources or faculties of cognition, by which alone their

relation to each other can be rightly determined. The first question

which occurs in considering our representations is to what faculty

of cognition do they belong? To the understanding or to the senses?

Many judgements are admitted to be true from mere habit or

inclination; but, because reflection neither precedes nor follows,

it is held to be a judgement that has its origin in the understanding.

All judgements do not require examination, that is, investigation into

the grounds of their truth. For, when they are immediately certain

(for example: "Between two points there can be only one straight

line"), no better or less mediate test of their truth can be found

than that which they themselves contain and express. But all

judgement, nay, all comparisons require reflection, that is, a

distinction of the faculty of cognition to which the given conceptions

belong. The act whereby I compare my representations with the

faculty of cognition which originates them, and whereby I

distinguish whether they are compared with each other as belonging

to the pure understanding or to sensuous intuition, I term

transcendental reflection. Now, the relations in which conceptions can

stand to each other are those of identity and difference, agreement

and opposition, of the internal and external, finally, of the

determinable and the determining (matter and form). The proper

determination of these relations rests on the question, to what

faculty of cognition they subjectively belong, whether to

sensibility or understanding? For, on the manner in which we solve

this question depends the manner in which we must cogitate these

relations.

  Before constructing any objective judgement, we compare the

conceptions that are to be placed in the judgement, and observe

whether there exists identity (of many representations in one

conception), if a general judgement is to be constructed, or

difference, if a particular; whether there is agreement when

affirmative; and opposition when negative judgements are to be

constructed, and so on. For this reason we ought to call these

conceptions, conceptions of comparison (conceptus comparationis).

But as, when the question is not as to the logical form, but as to the

content of conceptions, that is to say, whether the things

themselves are identical or different, in agreement or opposition, and

so on, the things can have a twofold relation to our faculty of

cognition, to wit, a relation either to sensibility or to the

understanding, and as on this relation depends their relation to

each other, transcendental reflection, that is, the relation of

given representations to one or the other faculty of cognition, can

alone determine this latter relation. Thus we shall not be able to

discover whether the things are identical or different, in agreement

or opposition, etc., from the mere conception of the things by means

of comparison (comparatio), but only by distinguishing the mode of

cognition to which they belong, in other words, by means of

transcendental reflection. We may, therefore, with justice say, that

logical reflection is mere comparison, for in it no account is taken

of the faculty of cognition to which the given conceptions belong, and

they are consequently, as far as regards their origin, to be treated

as homogeneous; while transcendental reflection (which applies to

the objects themselves) contains the ground of the possibility of

objective comparison of representations with each other, and is

therefore very different from the former, because the faculties of

cognition to which they belong are not even the same. Transcendental

reflection is a duty which no one can neglect who wishes to

establish an a priori judgement upon things. We shall now proceed to

fulfil this duty, and thereby throw not a little light on the question

as to the determination of the proper business of the understanding.

  1. Identity and Difference. When an object is presented to us

several times, but always with the same internal determinations

(qualitas et quantitas), it, if an object of pure understanding, is

always the same, not several things, but only one thing (numerica

identitas); but if a phenomenon, we do not concern ourselves with

comparing the conception of the thing with the conception of some

other, but, although they may be in this respect perfectly the same,

the difference of place at the same time is a sufficient ground for

asserting the numerical difference of these objects (of sense).

Thus, in the case of two drops of water, we may make complete

abstraction of all internal difference (quality and quantity), and,

the fact that they are intuited at the same time in different

places, is sufficient to justify us in holding them to be

numerically different. Leibnitz regarded phenomena as things in

themselves, consequently as intelligibilia, that is, objects of pure

understanding (although, on account of the confused nature of their

representations, he gave them the name of phenomena), and in this case

his principle of the indiscernible (principium identatis

indiscernibilium) is not to be impugned. But, as phenomena are objects

of sensibility, and, as the understanding, in respect of them, must be

employed empirically and not purely or transcendentally, plurality and

numerical difference are given by space itself as the condition of

external phenomena. For one part of space, although it may be

perfectly similar and equal to another part, is still without it,

and for this reason alone is different from the latter, which is added

to it in order to make up a greater space. It follows that this must

hold good of all things that are in the different parts of space at

the same time, however similar and equal one may be to another.

  2. Agreement and Opposition. When reality is represented by the pure

understanding (realitas noumenon), opposition between realities is

incogitable- such a relation, that is, that when these realities are

connected in one subject, they annihilate the effects of each other

and may be represented in the formula 3 - 3 = 0. On the other hand,

the real in a phenomenon (realitas phaenomenon) may very well be in

mutual opposition, and, when united in the same subject, the one may

completely or in part annihilate the effect or consequence of the

other; as in the case of two moving forces in the same straight line

drawing or impelling a point in opposite directions, or in the case of

a pleasure counterbalancing a certain amount of pain.

  3. The Internal and External. In an object of the pure

understanding, only that is internal which has no relation (as regards

its existence) to anything different from itself. On the other hand,

the internal determinations of a substantia phaenomenon in space are

nothing but relations, and it is itself nothing more than a complex of

mere relations. Substance in space we are cognizant of only through

forces operative in it, either drawing others towards itself

(attraction), or preventing others from forcing into itself (repulsion

and impenetrability). We know no other properties that make up the

conception of substance phenomenal in space, and which we term matter.

On the other hand, as an object of the pure understanding, every

substance must have internal determination and forces. But what

other internal attributes of such an object can I think than those

which my internal sense presents to me? That, to wit, which in

either itself thought, or something analogous to it. Hence Leibnitz,

who looked upon things as noumena, after denying them everything

like external relation, and therefore also composition or combination,

declared that all substances, even the component parts of matter, were

simple substances with powers of representation, in one word, monads.

  4. Matter and Form. These two conceptions lie at the foundation of

all other reflection, so inseparably are they connected with every

mode of exercising the understanding. The former denotes the

determinable in general, the second its determination, both in a

transcendental sense, abstraction being made of every difference in

that which is given, and of the mode in which it is determined.

Logicians formerly termed the universal, matter, the specific

difference of this or that part of the universal, form. In a judgement

one may call the given conceptions logical matter (for the judgement),

the relation of these to each other (by means of the copula), the form

of the judgement. In an object, the composite parts thereof

(essentialia) are the matter; the mode in which they are connected

in the object, the form. In respect to things in general, unlimited

reality was regarded as the matter of all possibility, the

limitation thereof (negation) as the form, by which one thing is

distinguished from another according to transcendental conceptions.

The understanding demands that something be given (at least in the

conception), in order to be able to determine it in a certain

manner. Hence, in a conception of the pure understanding, the matter

precedes the form, and for this reason Leibnitz first assumed the

existence of things (monads) and of an internal power of

representation in them, in order to found upon this their external

relation and the community their state (that is, of their

representations). Hence, with him, space and time were possible- the

former through the relation of substances, the latter through the

connection of their determinations with each other, as causes and

effects. And so would it really be, if the pure understanding were

capable of an immediate application to objects, and if space and

time were determinations of things in themselves. But being merely

sensuous intuitions, in which we determine all objects solely as

phenomena, the form of intuition (as a subjective property of

sensibility) must antecede all matter (sensations), consequently space

and time must antecede all phenomena and all data of experience, and

rather make experience itself possible. But the intellectual

philosopher could not endure that the form should precede the things

themselves and determine their possibility; an objection perfectly

correct, if we assume that we intuite things as they are, although

with confused representation. But as sensuous intuition is a

peculiar subjective condition, which is a priori at the foundation

of all perception, and the form of which is primitive, the form must

be given per se, and so far from matter (or the things themselves

which appear) lying at the foundation of experience (as we must

conclude, if we judge by mere conceptions), the very possibility of

itself presupposes, on the contrary, a given formal intuition (space

and time).



    REMARK ON THE AMPHIBOLY OF THE CONCEPTIONS OF REFLECTION.



  Let me be allowed to term the position which we assign to a

conception either in the sensibility or in the pure understanding, the

transcendental place. In this manner, the appointment of the

position which must be taken by each conception according to the

difference in its use, and the directions for determining this place

to all conceptions according to rules, would be a transcendental

topic, a doctrine which would thoroughly shield us from the

surreptitious devices of the pure understanding and the delusions

which thence arise, as it would always distinguish to what faculty

of cognition each conception properly belonged. Every conception,

every title, under which many cognitions rank together, may be

called a logical place. Upon this is based the logical topic of

Aristotle, of which teachers and rhetoricians could avail

themselves, in order, under certain titles of thought, to observe what

would best suit the matter they had to treat, and thus enable

themselves to quibble and talk with fluency and an appearance of

profundity.

  Transcendental topic, on the contrary, contains nothing more than

the above-mentioned four titles of all comparison and distinction,

which differ from categories in this respect, that they do not

represent the object according to that which constitutes its

conception (quantity, reality), but set forth merely the comparison of

representations, which precedes our conceptions of things. But this

comparison requires a previous reflection, that is, a determination of

the place to which the representations of the things which are

compared belong, whether, to wit, they are cogitated by the pure

understanding, or given by sensibility.

  Conceptions may be logically compared without the trouble of

inquiring to what faculty their objects belong, whether as noumena, to

the understanding, or as phenomena, to sensibility. If, however, we

wish to employ these conceptions in respect of objects, previous

transcendental reflection is necessary. Without this reflection I

should make a very unsafe use of these conceptions, and construct

pretended synthetical propositions which critical reason cannot

acknowledge and which are based solely upon a transcendental

amphiboly, that is, upon a substitution of an object of pure

understanding for a phenomenon.

  For want of this doctrine of transcendental topic, and

consequently deceived by the amphiboly of the conceptions of

reflection, the celebrated Leibnitz constructed an intellectual system

of the world, or rather, believed himself competent to cognize the

internal nature of things, by comparing all objects merely with the

understanding and the abstract formal conceptions of thought. Our

table of the conceptions of reflection gives us the unexpected

advantage of being able to exhibit the distinctive peculiarities of

his system in all its parts, and at the same time of exposing the

fundamental principle of this peculiar mode of thought, which rested

upon naught but a misconception. He compared all things with each

other merely by means of conceptions, and naturally found no other

differences than those by which the understanding distinguishes its

pure conceptions one from another. The conditions of sensuous

intuition, which contain in themselves their own means of distinction,

he did not look upon as primitive, because sensibility was to him

but a confused mode of representation and not any particular source of

representations. A phenomenon was for him the representation of the

thing in itself, although distinguished from cognition by the

understanding only in respect of the logical form- the former with its

usual want of analysis containing, according to him, a certain mixture

of collateral representations in its conception of a thing, which it

is the duty of the understanding to separate and distinguish. In one

word, Leibnitz intellectualized phenomena, just as Locke, in his

system of noogony (if I may be allowed to make use of such

expressions), sensualized the conceptions of the understanding, that

is to say, declared them to be nothing more than empirical or abstract

conceptions of reflection. Instead of seeking in the understanding and

sensibility two different sources of representations, which,

however, can present us with objective judgements of things only in

conjunction, each of these great men recognized but one of these

faculties, which, in their opinion, applied immediately to things in

themselves, the other having no duty but that of confusing or

arranging the representations of the former.

  Accordingly, the objects of sense were compared by Leibnitz as

things in general merely in the understanding.

  1st. He compares them in regard to their identity or difference-

as judged by the understanding. As, therefore, he considered merely

the conceptions of objects, and not their position in intuition, in

which alone objects can be given, and left quite out of sight the

transcendental locale of these conceptions- whether, that is, their

object ought to be classed among phenomena, or among things in

themselves, it was to be expected that he should extend the

application of the principle of indiscernibles, which is valid

solely of conceptions of things in general, to objects of sense

(mundus phaenomenon), and that he should believe that he had thereby

contributed in no small degree to extend our knowledge of nature. In

truth, if I cognize in all its inner determinations a drop of water as

a thing in itself, I cannot look upon one drop as different from

another, if the conception of the one is completely identical with

that of the other. But if it is a phenomenon in space, it has a

place not merely in the understanding (among conceptions), but also in

sensuous external intuition (in space), and in this case, the physical

locale is a matter of indifference in regard to the internal

determinations of things, and one place, B, may contain a thing

which is perfectly similar and equal to another in a place, A, just as

well as if the two things were in every respect different from each

other. Difference of place without any other conditions, makes the

plurality and distinction of objects as phenomena, not only possible

in itself, but even necessary. Consequently, the above so-called law

is not a law of nature. It is merely an analytical rule for the

comparison of things by means of mere conceptions.

  2nd. The principle: "Realities (as simple affirmations) never

logically contradict each other," is a proposition perfectly true

respecting the relation of conceptions, but, whether as regards

nature, or things in themselves (of which we have not the slightest

conception), is without any the least meaning. For real opposition, in

which A - B is = 0, exists everywhere, an opposition, that is, in

which one reality united with another in the same subject

annihilates the effects of the other- a fact which is constantly

brought before our eyes by the different antagonistic actions and

operations in nature, which, nevertheless, as depending on real

forces, must be called realitates phaenomena. General mechanics can

even present us with the empirical condition of this opposition in

an a priori rule, as it directs its attention to the opposition in the

direction of forces- a condition of which the transcendental

conception of reality can tell us nothing. Although M. Leibnitz did

not announce this proposition with precisely the pomp of a new

principle, he yet employed it for the establishment of new

propositions, and his followers introduced it into their

Leibnitzio-Wolfian system of philosophy. According to this

principle, for example, all evils are but consequences of the

limited nature of created beings, that is, negations, because these

are the only opposite of reality. (In the mere conception of a thing

in general this is really the case, but not in things as phenomena.)

In like manner, the upholders of this system deem it not only

possible, but natural also, to connect and unite all reality in one

being, because they acknowledge no other sort of opposition than

that of contradiction (by which the conception itself of a thing is

annihilated), and find themselves unable to conceive an opposition

of reciprocal destruction, so to speak, in which one real cause

destroys the effect of another, and the conditions of whose

representation we meet with only in sensibility.

  3rd. The Leibnitzian monadology has really no better foundation than

on this philosopher's mode of falsely representing the difference of

the internal and external solely in relation to the understanding.

Substances, in general, must have something inward, which is therefore

free from external relations, consequently from that of composition

also. The simple- that which can be represented by a unit- is

therefore the foundation of that which is internal in things in

themselves. The internal state of substances cannot therefore

consist in place, shape, contact, or motion, determinations which

are all external relations, and we can ascribe to them no other than

that whereby we internally determine our faculty of sense itself, that

is to say, the state of representation. Thus, then, were constructed

the monads, which were to form the elements of the universe, the

active force of which consists in representation, the effects of

this force being thus entirely confined to themselves.

  For the same reason, his view of the possible community of

substances could not represent it but as a predetermined harmony,

and by no means as a physical influence. For inasmuch as everything is

occupied only internally, that is, with its own representations, the

state of the representations of one substance could not stand in

active and living connection with that of another, but some third

cause operating on all without exception was necessary to make the

different states correspond with one another. And this did not

happen by means of assistance applied in each particular case (systema

assistentiae), but through the unity of the idea of a cause occupied

and connected with all substances, in which they necessarily

receive, according to the Leibnitzian school, their existence and

permanence, consequently also reciprocal correspondence, according

to universal laws.

  4th. This philosopher's celebrated doctrine of space and time, in

which he intellectualized these forms of sensibility, originated in

the same delusion of transcendental reflection. If I attempt to

represent by the mere understanding, the external relations of things,

I can do so only by employing the conception of their reciprocal

action, and if I wish to connect one state of the same thing with

another state, I must avail myself of the notion of the order of cause

and effect. And thus Leibnitz regarded space as a certain order in the

community of substances, and time as the dynamical sequence of their

states. That which space and time possess proper to themselves and

independent of things, he ascribed to a necessary confusion in our

conceptions of them, whereby that which is a mere form of dynamical

relations is held to be a self-existent intuition, antecedent even

to things themselves. Thus space and time were the intelligible form

of the connection of things (substances and their states) in

themselves. But things were intelligible substances (substantiae

noumena). At the same time, he made these conceptions valid of

phenomena, because he did not allow to sensibility a peculiar mode

of intuition, but sought all, even the empirical representation of

objects, in the understanding, and left to sense naught but the

despicable task of confusing and disarranging the representations of

the former.

  But even if we could frame any synthetical proposition concerning

things in themselves by means of the pure understanding (which is

impossible), it could not apply to phenomena, which do not represent

things in themselves. In such a case I should be obliged in

transcendental reflection to compare my conceptions only under the

conditions of sensibility, and so space and time would not be

determinations of things in themselves, but of phenomena. What

things may be in themselves, I know not and need not know, because a

thing is never presented to me otherwise than as a phenomenon.

  I must adopt the same mode of procedure with the other conceptions

of reflection. Matter is substantia phaenomenon. That in it which is

internal I seek to discover in all parts of space which it occupies,

and in all the functions and operations it performs, and which are

indeed never anything but phenomena of the external sense. I cannot

therefore find anything that is absolutely, but only what is

comparatively internal, and which itself consists of external

relations. The absolutely internal in matter, and as it should be

according to the pure understanding, is a mere chimera, for matter

is not an object for the pure understanding. But the transcendental

object, which is the foundation of the phenomenon which we call

matter, is a mere nescio quid, the nature of which we could not

understand, even though someone were found able to tell us. For we can

understand nothing that does not bring with it something in

intuition corresponding to the expressions employed. If, by the

complaint of being unable to perceive the internal nature of things,

it is meant that we do not comprehend by the pure understanding what

the things which appear to us may be in themselves, it is a silly

and unreasonable complaint; for those who talk thus really desire that

we should be able to cognize, consequently to intuite, things

without senses, and therefore wish that we possessed a faculty of

cognition perfectly different from the human faculty, not merely in

degree, but even as regards intuition and the mode thereof, so that

thus we should not be men, but belong to a class of beings, the

possibility of whose existence, much less their nature and

constitution, we have no means of cognizing. By observation and

analysis of phenomena we penetrate into the interior of nature, and no

one can say what progress this knowledge may make in time. But those

transcendental questions which pass beyond the limits of nature, we

could never answer, even although all nature were laid open to us,

because we have not the power of observing our own mind with any other

intuition than that of our internal sense. For herein lies the mystery

of the origin and source of our faculty of sensibility. Its

application to an object, and the transcendental ground of this

unity of subjective and objective, lie too deeply concealed for us,

who cognize ourselves only through the internal sense, consequently as

phenomena, to be able to discover in our existence anything but

phenomena, the non-sensuous cause of which we at the same time

earnestly desire to penetrate to.

  The great utility of this critique of conclusions arrived at by

the processes of mere reflection consists in its clear demonstration

of the nullity of all conclusions respecting objects which are

compared with each other in the understanding alone, while it at the

same time confirms what we particularly insisted on, namely, that,

although phenomena are not included as things in themselves among

the objects of the pure understanding, they are nevertheless the

only things by which our cognition can possess objective reality, that

is to say, which give us intuitions to correspond with our

conceptions.

  When we reflect in a purely logical manner, we do nothing more

than compare conceptions in our understanding, to discover whether

both have the same content, whether they are self-contradictory or

not, whether anything is contained in either conception, which of

the two is given, and which is merely a mode of thinking that given.

But if I apply these conceptions to an object in general (in the

transcendental sense), without first determining whether it is an

object of sensuous or intellectual intuition, certain limitations

present themselves, which forbid us to pass beyond the conceptions and

render all empirical use of them impossible. And thus these

limitations prove that the representation of an object as a thing in

general is not only insufficient, but, without sensuous

determination and independently of empirical conditions,

self-contradictory; that we must therefore make abstraction of all

objects, as in logic, or, admitting them, must think them under

conditions of sensuous intuition; that, consequently, the intelligible

requires an altogether peculiar intuition, which we do not possess,

and in the absence of which it is for us nothing; while, on the

other hand phenomena cannot be objects in themselves. For, when I

merely think things in general, the difference in their external

relations cannot constitute a difference in the things themselves;

on the contrary, the former presupposes the latter, and if the

conception of one of two things is not internally different from

that of the other, I am merely thinking the same thing in different

relations. Further, by the addition of one affirmation (reality) to

the other, the positive therein is really augmented, and nothing is

abstracted or withdrawn from it; hence the real in things cannot be in

contradiction with or opposition to itself- and so on.



  The true use of the conceptions of reflection in the employment of

the understanding has, as we have shown, been so misconceived by

Leibnitz, one of the most acute philosophers of either ancient or

modern times, that he has been misled into the construction of a

baseless system of intellectual cognition, which professes to

determine its objects without the intervention of the senses. For this

reason, the exposition of the cause of the amphiboly of these

conceptions, as the origin of these false principles, is of great

utility in determining with certainty the proper limits of the

understanding.

  It is right to say whatever is affirmed or denied of the whole of

a conception can be affirmed or denied of any part of it (dictum de

omni et nullo); but it would be absurd so to alter this logical

proposition as to say whatever is not contained in a general

conception is likewise not contained in the particular conceptions

which rank under it; for the latter are particular conceptions, for

the very reason that their content is greater than that which is

cogitated in the general conception. And yet the whole intellectual

system of Leibnitz is based upon this false principle, and with it

must necessarily fall to the ground, together with all the ambiguous

principles in reference to the employment of the understanding which

have thence originated.

  Leibnitz's principle of the identity of indiscernibles or

indistinguishables is really based on the presupposition that, if in

the conception of a thing a certain distinction is not to be found, it

is also not to be met with in things themselves; that, consequently,

all things are completely identical (numero eadem) which are not

distinguishable from each other (as to quality or quantity) in our

conceptions of them. But, as in the mere conception of anything

abstraction has been made of many necessary conditions of intuition,

that of which abstraction has been made is rashly held to be

non-existent, and nothing is attributed to the thing but what is

contained in its conception.

  The conception of a cubic foot of space, however I may think it,

is in itself completely identical. But two cubic feet in space are

nevertheless distinct from each other from the sole fact of their

being in different places (they are numero diversa); and these

places are conditions of intuition, wherein the object of this

conception is given, and which do not belong to the conception, but to

the faculty of sensibility. In like manner, there is in the conception

of a thing no contradiction when a negative is not connected with an

affirmative; and merely affirmative conceptions cannot, in

conjunction, produce any negation. But in sensuous intuition,

wherein reality (take for example, motion) is given, we find

conditions (opposite directions)- of which abstraction has been made

in the conception of motion in general- which render possible a

contradiction or opposition (not indeed of a logical kind)- and

which from pure positives produce zero = 0. We are therefore not

justified in saying that all reality is in perfect agreement and

harmony, because no contradiction is discoverable among its

conceptions.* According to mere conceptions, that which is internal is

the substratum of all relations or external determinations. When,

therefore, I abstract all conditions of intuition, and confine

myself solely to the conception of a thing in general, I can make

abstraction of all external relations, and there must nevertheless

remain a conception of that which indicates no relation, but merely

internal determinations. Now it seems to follow that in everything

(substance) there is something which is absolutely internal and

which antecedes all external determinations, inasmuch as it renders

them possible; and that therefore this substratum is something which

does not contain any external relations and is consequently simple

(for corporeal things are never anything but relations, at least of

their parts external to each other); and, inasmuch as we know of no

other absolutely internal determinations than those of the internal

sense, this substratum is not only simple, but also, analogously

with our internal sense, determined through representations, that is

to say, all things are properly monads, or simple beings endowed

with the power of representation. Now all this would be perfectly

correct, if the conception of a thing were the only necessary

condition of the presentation of objects of external intuition. It is,

on the contrary, manifest that a permanent phenomenon in space

(impenetrable extension) can contain mere relations, and nothing

that is absolutely internal, and yet be the primary substratum of

all external perception. By mere conceptions I cannot think anything

external, without, at the same time, thinking something internal,

for the reason that conceptions of relations presuppose given

things, and without these are impossible. But, as an intuition there

is something (that is, space, which, with all it contains, consists of

purely formal, or, indeed, real relations) which is not found in the

mere conception of a thing in general, and this presents to us the

substratum which could not be cognized through conceptions alone, I

cannot say: because a thing cannot be represented by mere

conceptions without something absolutely internal, there is also, in

the things themselves which are contained under these conceptions, and

in their intuition nothing external to which something absolutely

internal does not serve as the foundation. For, when we have made

abstraction of all the conditions of intuition, there certainly

remains in the mere conception nothing but the internal in general,

through which alone the external is possible. But this necessity,

which is grounded upon abstraction alone, does not obtain in the

case of things themselves, in so far as they are given in intuition

with such determinations as express mere relations, without having

anything internal as their foundation; for they are not things of a

thing of which we can neither for they are not things in themselves,

but only phenomena. What we cognize in matter is nothing but relations

(what we call its internal determinations are but comparatively

internal). But there are some self-subsistent and permanent, through

which a determined object is given. That I, when abstraction is made

of these relations, have nothing more to think, does not destroy the

conception of a thing as phenomenon, nor the conception of an object

in abstracto, but it does away with the possibility of an object

that is determinable according to mere conceptions, that is, of a

noumenon. It is certainly startling to hear that a thing consists

solely of relations; but this thing is simply a phenomenon, and cannot

be cogitated by means of the mere categories: it does itself consist

in the mere relation of something in general to the senses. In the

same way, we cannot cogitate relations of things in abstracto, if we

commence with conceptions alone, in any other manner than that one

is the cause of determinations in the other; for that is itself the

conception of the understanding or category of relation. But, as in

this case we make abstraction of all intuition, we lose altogether the

mode in which the manifold determines to each of its parts its

place, that is, the form of sensibility (space); and yet this mode

antecedes all empirical causality.



  *If any one wishes here to have recourse to the usual subterfuge,

and to say, that at least realitates noumena cannot be in opposition

to each other, it will be requisite for him to adduce an example of

this pure and non-sensuous reality, that it may be understood

whether the notion represents something or nothing. But an example

cannot be found except in experience, which never presents to us

anything more than phenomena; and thus the proposition means nothing

more than that the conception which contains only affirmatives does

not contain anything negative- a proposition nobody ever doubted.



  If by intelligible objects we understand things which can be thought

by means of the pure categories, without the need of the schemata of

sensibility, such objects are impossible. For the condition of the

objective use of all our conceptions of understanding is the mode of

our sensuous intuition, whereby objects are given; and, if we make

abstraction of the latter, the former can have no relation to an

object. And even if we should suppose a different kind of intuition

from our own, still our functions of thought would have no use or

signification in respect thereof. But if we understand by the term,

objects of a non-sensuous intuition, in respect of which our

categories are not valid, and of which we can accordingly have no

knowledge (neither intuition nor conception), in this merely

negative sense noumena must be admitted. For this is no more than

saying that our mode of intuition is not applicable to all things, but

only to objects of our senses, that consequently its objective

validity is limited, and that room is therefore left for another

kind of intuition, and thus also for things that may be objects of it.

But in this sense the conception of a noumenon is problematical,

that is to say, it is the notion of that it that it is possible, nor

that it is impossible, inasmuch as we do not know of any mode of

intuition besides the sensuous, or of any other sort of conceptions

than the categories- a mode of intuition and a kind of conception

neither of which is applicable to a non-sensuous object. We are on

this account incompetent to extend the sphere of our objects of

thought beyond the conditions of our sensibility, and to assume the

existence of objects of pure thought, that is, of noumena, inasmuch as

these have no true positive signification. For it must be confessed of

the categories that they are not of themselves sufficient for the

cognition of things in themselves and, without the data of

sensibility, are mere subjective forms of the unity of the

understanding. Thought is certainly not a product of the senses, and

in so far is not limited by them, but it does not therefore follow

that it may be employed purely and without the intervention of

sensibility, for it would then be without reference to an object.

And we cannot call a noumenon an object of pure thought; for the

representation thereof is but the problematical conception of an

object for a perfectly different intuition and a perfectly different

understanding from ours, both of which are consequently themselves

problematical. The conception of a noumenon is therefore not the

conception of an object, but merely a problematical conception

inseparably connected with the limitation of our sensibility. That

is to say, this conception contains the answer to the question: "Are

there objects quite unconnected with, and independent of, our

intuition?"- a question to which only an indeterminate answer can be

given. That answer is: "Inasmuch as sensuous intuition does not

apply to all things without distinction, there remains room for

other and different objects." The existence of these problematical

objects is therefore not absolutely denied, in the absence of a

determinate conception of them, but, as no category is valid in

respect of them, neither must they be admitted as objects for our

understanding.

  Understanding accordingly limits sensibility, without at the same

time enlarging its own field. While, moreover, it forbids

sensibility to apply its forms and modes to things in themselves and

restricts it to the sphere of phenomena, it cogitates an object in

itself, only, however, as a transcendental object, which is the

cause of a phenomenon (consequently not itself a phenomenon), and

which cannot be thought either as a quantity or as reality, or as

substance (because these conceptions always require sensuous forms

in which to determine an object)- an object, therefore, of which we

are quite unable to say whether it can be met with in ourselves or out

of us, whether it would be annihilated together with sensibility,

or, if this were taken away, would continue to exist. If we wish to

call this object a noumenon, because the representation of it is

non-sensuous, we are at liberty to do so. But as we can apply to it

none of the conceptions of our understanding, the representation is

for us quite void, and is available only for the indication of the

limits of our sensuous intuition, thereby leaving at the same time

an empty space, which we are competent to fill by the aid neither of

possible experience, nor of the pure understanding.

  The critique of the pure understanding, accordingly, does not permit

us to create for ourselves a new field of objects beyond those which

are presented to us as phenomena, and to stray into intelligible

worlds; nay, it does not even allow us to endeavour to form so much as

a conception of them. The specious error which leads to this- and

which is a perfectly excusable one- lies in the fact that the

employment of the understanding, contrary to its proper purpose and

destination, is made transcendental, and objects, that is, possible

intuitions, are made to regulate themselves according to

conceptions, instead of the conceptions arranging themselves according

to the intuitions, on which alone their own objective validity

rests. Now the reason of this again is that apperception, and with

it thought, antecedes all possible determinate arrangement of

representations. Accordingly we think something in general and

determine it on the one hand sensuously, but, on the other,

distinguish the general and in abstracto represented object from

this particular mode of intuiting it. In this case there remains a

mode of determining the object by mere thought, which is really but

a logical form without content, which, however, seems to us to be a

mode of the existence of the object in itself (noumenon), without

regard to intuition which is limited to our senses.



  Before ending this transcendental analytic, we must make an

addition, which, although in itself of no particular importance, seems

to be necessary to the completeness of the system. The highest

conception, with which a transcendental philosophy commonly begins, is

the division into possible and impossible. But as all division

presupposes a divided conception, a still higher one must exist, and

this is the conception of an object in general- problematically

understood and without its being decided whether it is something or

nothing. As the categories are the only conceptions which apply to

objects in general, the distinguishing of an object, whether it is

something or nothing, must proceed according to the order and

direction of the categories.

  1. To the categories of quantity, that is, the conceptions of all,

many, and one, the conception which annihilates all, that is, the

conception of none, is opposed. And thus the object of a conception,

to which no intuition can be found to correspond, is = nothing. That

is, it is a conception without an object (ens rationis), like noumena,

which cannot be considered possible in the sphere of reality, though

they must not therefore be held to be impossible- or like certain

new fundamental forces in matter, the existence of which is

cogitable without contradiction, though, as examples from experience

are not forthcoming, they must not be regarded as possible.

  2. Reality is something; negation is nothing, that is, a

conception of the absence of an object, as cold, a shadow (nihil

privativum).

  3. The mere form of intuition, without substance, is in itself no

object, but the merely formal condition of an object (as

phenomenon), as pure space and pure time. These are certainly

something, as forms of intuition, but are not themselves objects which

are intuited (ens imaginarium).

  4. The object of a conception which is self-contradictory, is

nothing, because the conception is nothing- is impossible, as a figure

composed of two straight lines (nihil negativum).

  The table of this division of the conception of nothing (the

corresponding division of the conception of something does not require

special description) must therefore be arranged as follows:



                      NOTHING

                        AS



                        1

                As Empty Conception

                 without object,

                  ens rationis

           2                               3

     Empty object of               Empty intuition

      a conception,                without object,

     nihil privativum              ens imaginarium

                        4

                   Empty object

                 without conception,

                  nihil negativum



  We see that the ens rationis is distinguished from the nihil

negativum or pure nothing by the consideration that the former must

not be reckoned among possibilities, because it is a mere fiction-

though not self-contradictory, while the latter is completely

opposed to all possibility, inasmuch as the conception annihilates

itself. Both, however, are empty conceptions.  On the other hand,

the nihil privativum and ens imaginarium are empty data for

conceptions. If light be not given to the senses, we cannot

represent to ourselves darkness, and if extended objects are not

perceived, we cannot represent space. Neither the negation, nor the

mere form of intuition can, without something real, be an object.

INTRO

           TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC. SECOND DIVISION.



           TRANSCENDENTAL DIALECTIC. INTRODUCTION.



         I. Of Transcendental Illusory Appearance.



  We termed dialectic in general a logic of appearance. This does

not signify a doctrine of probability; for probability is truth,

only cognized upon insufficient grounds, and though the information it

gives us is imperfect, it is not therefore deceitful. Hence it must

not be separated from the analytical part of logic. Still less must

phenomenon and appearance be held to be identical. For truth or

illusory appearance does not reside in the object, in so far as it

is intuited, but in the judgement upon the object, in so far as it

is thought. It is, therefore, quite correct to say that the senses

do not err, not because they always judge correctly, but because

they do not judge at all. Hence truth and error, consequently also,

illusory appearance as the cause of error, are only to be found in a

judgement, that is, in the relation of an object to our understanding.

In a cognition which completely harmonizes with the laws of the

understanding, no error can exist. In a representation of the

senses- as not containing any judgement- there is also no error. But

no power of nature can of itself deviate from its own laws. Hence

neither the understanding per se (without the influence of another

cause), nor the senses per se, would fall into error; the former could

not, because, if it acts only according to its own laws, the effect

(the judgement) must necessarily accord with these laws. But in

accordance with the laws of the understanding consists the formal

element in all truth. In the senses there is no judgement- neither a

true nor a false one. But, as we have no source of cognition besides

these two, it follows that error is caused solely by the unobserved

influence of the sensibility upon the understanding. And thus it

happens that the subjective grounds of a judgement and are

confounded with the objective, and cause them to deviate from their

proper determination,* just as a body in motion would always of itself

proceed in a straight line, but if another impetus gives to it a

different direction, it will then start off into a curvilinear line of

motion. To distinguish the peculiar action of the understanding from

the power which mingles with it, it is necessary to consider an

erroneous judgement as the diagonal between two forces, that determine

the judgement in two different directions, which, as it were, form

an angle, and to resolve this composite operation into the simple ones

of the understanding and the sensibility. In pure a priori

judgements this must be done by means of transcendental reflection,

whereby, as has been already shown, each representation has its

place appointed in the corresponding faculty of cognition, and

consequently the influence of the one faculty upon the other is made

apparent.



  *Sensibility, subjected to the understanding, as the object upon

which the understanding employs its functions, is the source of real

cognitions. But, in so far as it exercises an influence upon the

action of the understanding and determines it to judgement,

sensibility is itself the cause of error.



  It is not at present our business to treat of empirical illusory

appearance (for example, optical illusion), which occurs in the

empirical application of otherwise correct rules of the understanding,

and in which the judgement is misled by the influence of

imagination. Our purpose is to speak of transcendental illusory

appearance, which influences principles- that are not even applied

to experience, for in this case we should possess a sure test of their

correctness- but which leads us, in disregard of all the warnings of

criticism, completely beyond the empirical employment of the

categories and deludes us with the chimera of an extension of the

sphere of the pure understanding. We shall term those principles the

application of which is confined entirely within the limits of

possible experience, immanent; those, on the other hand, which

transgress these limits, we shall call transcendent principles. But by

these latter I do not understand principles of the transcendental

use or misuse of the categories, which is in reality a mere fault of

the judgement when not under due restraint from criticism, and

therefore not paying sufficient attention to the limits of the

sphere in which the pure understanding is allowed to exercise its

functions; but real principles which exhort us to break down all those

barriers, and to lay claim to a perfectly new field of cognition,

which recognizes no line of demarcation. Thus transcendental and

transcendent are not identical terms. The principles of the pure

understanding, which we have already propounded, ought to be of

empirical and not of transcendental use, that is, they are not

applicable to any object beyond the sphere of experience. A

principle which removes these limits, nay, which authorizes us to

overstep them, is called transcendent. If our criticism can succeed in

exposing the illusion in these pretended principles, those which are

limited in their employment to the sphere of experience may be called,

in opposition to the others, immanent principles of the pure

understanding.

  Logical illusion, which consists merely in the imitation of the form

of reason (the illusion in sophistical syllogisms), arises entirely

from a want of due attention to logical rules. So soon as the

attention is awakened to the case before us, this illusion totally

disappears. Transcendental illusion, on the contrary, does not cease

to exist, even after it has been exposed, and its nothingness

clearly perceived by means of transcendental criticism. Take, for

example, the illusion in the proposition: "The world must have a

beginning in time." The cause of this is as follows. In our reason,

subjectively considered as a faculty of human cognition, there exist

fundamental rules and maxims of its exercise, which have completely

the appearance of objective principles. Now from this cause it happens

that the subjective necessity of a certain connection of our

conceptions, is regarded as an objective necessity of the

determination of things in themselves. This illusion it is

impossible to avoid, just as we cannot avoid perceiving that the sea

appears to be higher at a distance than it is near the shore,

because we see the former by means of higher rays than the latter, or,

which is a still stronger case, as even the astronomer cannot

prevent himself from seeing the moon larger at its rising than some

time afterwards, although he is not deceived by this illusion.

  Transcendental dialectic will therefore content itself with exposing

the illusory appearance in transcendental judgements, and guarding

us against it; but to make it, as in the case of logical illusion,

entirely disappear and cease to be illusion is utterly beyond its

power. For we have here to do with a natural and unavoidable illusion,

which rests upon subjective principles and imposes these upon us as

objective, while logical dialectic, in the detection of sophisms,

has to do merely with an error in the logical consequence of the

propositions, or with an artificially constructed illusion, in

imitation of the natural error. There is, therefore, a natural and

unavoidable dialectic of pure reason- not that in which the bungler,

from want of the requisite knowledge, involves himself, nor that which

the sophist devises for the purpose of misleading, but that which is

an inseparable adjunct of human reason, and which, even after its

illusions have been exposed, does not cease to deceive, and

continually to lead reason into momentary errors, which it becomes

necessary continually to remove.



    II. Of Pure Reason as the Seat of Transcendental Illusory

                        Appearance.



                  A. OF REASON IN GENERAL.



  All our knowledge begins with sense, proceeds thence to

understanding, and ends with reason, beyond which nothing higher can

be discovered in the human mind for elaborating the matter of

intuition and subjecting it to the highest unity of thought. At this

stage of our inquiry it is my duty to give an explanation of this, the

highest faculty of cognition, and I confess I find myself here in some

difficulty. Of reason, as of the understanding, there is a merely

formal, that is, logical use, in which it makes abstraction of all

content of cognition; but there is also a real use, inasmuch as it

contains in itself the source of certain conceptions and principles,

which it does not borrow either from the senses or the

understanding. The former faculty has been long defined by logicians

as the faculty of mediate conclusion in contradistinction to immediate

conclusions (consequentiae immediatae); but the nature of the

latter, which itself generates conceptions, is not to be understood

from this definition. Now as a division of reason into a logical and a

transcendental faculty presents itself here, it becomes necessary to

seek for a higher conception of this source of cognition which shall

comprehend both conceptions. In this we may expect, according to the

analogy of the conceptions of the understanding, that the logical

conception will give us the key to the transcendental, and that the

table of the functions of the former will present us with the clue

to the conceptions of reason.

  In the former part of our transcendental logic, we defined the

understanding to be the faculty of rules; reason may be

distinguished from understanding as the faculty of principles.

  The term principle is ambiguous, and commonly signifies merely a

cognition that may be employed as a principle, although it is not in

itself, and as regards its proper origin, entitled to the distinction.

Every general proposition, even if derived from experience by the

process of induction, may serve as the major in a syllogism; but it is

not for that reason a principle. Mathematical axioms (for example,

there can be only one straight line between two points) are general

a priori cognitions, and are therefore rightly denominated principles,

relatively to the cases which can be subsumed under them. But I cannot

for this reason say that I cognize this property of a straight line

from principles- I cognize it only in pure intuition.

  Cognition from principles, then, is that cognition in which I

cognize the particular in the general by means of conceptions. Thus

every syllogism is a form of the deduction of a cognition from a

principle. For the major always gives a conception, through which

everything that is subsumed under the condition thereof is cognized

according to a principle. Now as every general cognition may serve

as the major in a syllogism, and the understanding presents us with

such general a priori propositions, they may be termed principles,

in respect of their possible use.

  But if we consider these principles of the pure understanding in

relation to their origin, we shall find them to be anything rather

than cognitions from conceptions. For they would not even be

possible a priori, if we could not rely on the assistance of pure

intuition (in mathematics), or on that of the conditions of a possible

experience. That everything that happens has a cause, cannot be

concluded from the general conception of that which happens; on the

contrary the principle of causality instructs us as to the mode of

obtaining from that which happens a determinate empirical conception.

  Synthetical cognitions from conceptions the understanding cannot

supply, and they alone are entitled to be called principles. At the

same time, all general propositions may be termed comparative

principles.

  It has been a long-cherished wish- that (who knows how late), may

one day, be happily accomplished- that the principles of the endless

variety of civil laws should be investigated and exposed; for in

this way alone can we find the secret of simplifying legislation.

But in this case, laws are nothing more than limitations of our

freedom upon conditions under which it subsists in perfect harmony

with itself; they consequently have for their object that which is

completely our own work, and of which we ourselves may be the cause by

means of these conceptions. But how objects as things in themselves-

how the nature of things is subordinated to principles and is to be

determined. according to conceptions, is a question which it seems

well nigh impossible to answer. Be this, however, as it may- for on

this point our investigation is yet to be made- it is at least

manifest from what we have said that cognition from principles is

something very different from cognition by means of the understanding,

which may indeed precede other cognitions in the form of a

principle, but in itself- in so far as it is synthetical- is neither

based upon mere thought, nor contains a general proposition drawn from

conceptions alone shall comprehend

  The understanding may be a faculty for the production of unity of

phenomena by virtue of rules; the reason is a faculty for the

production of unity of rules (of the understanding) under

principles. Reason, therefore, never applies directly to experience,

or to any sensuous object; its object is, on the contrary, the

understanding, to the manifold cognition of which it gives a unity a

priori by means of conceptions- a unity which may be called rational

unity, and which is of a nature very different from that of the

unity produced by the understanding.

  The above is the general conception of the faculty of reason, in

so far as it has been possible to make it comprehensible in the

absence of examples. These will be given in the sequel.



             B. OF THE LOGICAL USE OF REASON.



  A distinction is commonly made between that which is immediately

cognized and that which is inferred or concluded. That in a figure

which is bounded by three straight lines there are three angles, is an

immediate cognition; but that these angles are together equal to two

right angles, is an inference or conclusion. Now, as we are constantly

employing this mode of thought and have thus become quite accustomed

to it, we no longer remark the above distinction, and, as in the

case of the so-called deceptions of sense, consider as immediately

perceived, what has really been inferred. In every reasoning or

syllogism, there is a fundamental proposition, afterwards a second

drawn from it, and finally the conclusion, which connects the truth in

the first with the truth in the second- and that infallibly. If the

judgement concluded is so contained in the first proposition that it

can be deduced from it without the meditation of a third notion, the

conclusion is called immediate (consequentia immediata); I prefer

the term conclusion of the understanding. But if, in addition to the

fundamental cognition, a second judgement is necessary for the

production of the conclusion, it is called a conclusion of the reason.

In the proposition: All men are mortal, are contained the

propositions: Some men are mortal, Nothing that is not mortal is a

man, and these are therefore immediate conclusions from the first.

On the other hand, the proposition: all the learned are mortal, is not

contained in the main proposition (for the conception of a learned man

does not occur in it), and it can be deduced from the main proposition

only by means of a mediating judgement.

  In every syllogism I first cogitate a rule (the major) by means of

the understanding. In the next place I subsume a cognition under the

condition of the rule (and this is the minor) by means of the

judgement. And finally I determine my cognition by means of the

predicate of the rule (this is the conclusio), consequently, I

determine it a priori by means of the reason. The relations,

therefore, which the major proposition, as the rule, represents

between a cognition and its condition, constitute the different

kinds of syllogisms. These are just threefold- analogously with all

judgements, in so far as they differ in the mode of expressing the

relation of a cognition in the understanding- namely, categorical,

hypothetical, and disjunctive.

  When as often happens, the conclusion is a judgement which may

follow from other given judgements, through which a perfectly

different object is cogitated, I endeavour to discover in the

understanding whether the assertion in this conclusion does not

stand under certain conditions according to a general rule. If I

find such a condition, and if the object mentioned in the conclusion

can be subsumed under the given condition, then this conclusion

follows from a rule which is also valid for other objects of

cognition. From this we see that reason endeavours to subject the

great variety of the cognitions of the understanding to the smallest

possible number of principles (general conditions), and thus to

produce in it the highest unity.



               C. OF THE PURE USE OF REASON.



  Can we isolate reason, and, if so, is it in this case a peculiar

source of conceptions and judgements which spring from it alone, and

through which it can be applied to objects; or is it merely a

subordinate faculty, whose duty it is to give a certain form to

given cognitions- a form which is called logical, and through which

the cognitions of the understanding are subordinated to each other,

and lower rules to higher (those, to wit, whose condition comprises in

its sphere the condition of the others), in so far as this can be done

by comparison? This is the question which we have at present to

answer. Manifold variety of rules and unity of principles is a

requirement of reason, for the purpose of bringing the understanding

into complete accordance with itself, just as understanding subjects

the manifold content of intuition to conceptions, and thereby

introduces connection into it. But this principle prescribes no law to

objects, and does not contain any ground of the possibility of

cognizing or of determining them as such, but is merely a subjective

law for the proper arrangement of the content of the understanding.

The purpose of this law is, by a comparison of the conceptions of

the understanding, to reduce them to the smallest possible number,

although, at the same time, it does not justify us in demanding from

objects themselves such a uniformity as might contribute to the

convenience and the enlargement of the sphere of the understanding, or

in expecting that it will itself thus receive from them objective

validity. In one word, the question is: "does reason in itself, that

is, does pure reason contain a priori synthetical principles and

rules, and what are those principles?"

  The formal and logical procedure of reason in syllogisms gives us

sufficient information in regard to the ground on which the

transcendental principle of reason in its pure synthetical cognition

will rest.

  1. Reason, as observed in the syllogistic process, is not applicable

to intuitions, for the purpose of subjecting them to rules- for this

is the province of the understanding with its categories- but to

conceptions and judgements. If pure reason does apply to objects and

the intuition of them, it does so not immediately, but mediately-

through the understanding and its judgements, which have a direct

relation to the senses and their intuition, for the purpose of

determining their objects. The unity of reason is therefore not the

unity of a possible experience, but is essentially different from this

unity, which is that of the understanding. That everything which

happens has a cause, is not a principle cognized and prescribed by

reason. This principle makes the unity of experience possible and

borrows nothing from reason, which, without a reference to possible

experience, could never have produced by means of mere conceptions any

such synthetical unity.

  2. Reason, in its logical use, endeavours to discover the general

condition of its judgement (the conclusion), and a syllogism is itself

nothing but a judgement by means of the subsumption of its condition

under a general rule (the major). Now as this rule may itself be

subjected to the same process of reason, and thus the condition of the

condition be sought (by means of a prosyllogism) as long as the

process can be continued, it is very manifest that the peculiar

principle of reason in its logical use is to find for the

conditioned cognition of the understanding the unconditioned whereby

the unity of the former is completed.

  But this logical maxim cannot be a principle of pure reason,

unless we admit that, if the conditioned is given, the whole series of

conditions subordinated to one another- a series which is consequently

itself unconditioned- is also given, that is, contained in the

object and its connection.

  But this principle of pure reason is evidently synthetical; for,

analytically, the conditioned certainly relates to some condition, but

not to the unconditioned. From this principle also there must

originate different synthetical propositions, of which the pure

understanding is perfectly ignorant, for it has to do only with

objects of a possible experience, the cognition and synthesis of which

is always conditioned. The unconditioned, if it does really exist,

must be especially considered in regard to the determinations which

distinguish it from whatever is conditioned, and will thus afford us

material for many a priori synthetical propositions.

  The principles resulting from this highest principle of pure

reason will, however, be transcendent in relation to phenomena, that

is to say, it will be impossible to make any adequate empirical use of

this principle. It is therefore completely different from all

principles of the understanding, the use made of which is entirely

immanent, their object and purpose being merely the possibility of

experience. Now our duty in the transcendental dialectic is as

follows. To discover whether the principle that the series of

conditions (in the synthesis of phenomena, or of thought in general)

extends to the unconditioned is objectively true, or not; what

consequences result therefrom affecting the empirical use of the

understanding, or rather whether there exists any such objectively

valid proposition of reason, and whether it is not, on the contrary, a

merely logical precept which directs us to ascend perpetually to still

higher conditions, to approach completeness in the series of them, and

thus to introduce into our cognition the highest possible unity of

reason. We must ascertain, I say, whether this requirement of reason

has not been regarded, by a misunderstanding, as a transcendental

principle of pure reason, which postulates a thorough completeness

in the series of conditions in objects themselves. We must show,

moreover, the misconceptions and illusions that intrude into

syllogisms, the major proposition of which pure reason has supplied- a

proposition which has perhaps more of the character of a petitio

than of a postulatum- and that proceed from experience upwards to

its conditions. The solution of these problems is our task in

transcendental dialectic, which we are about to expose even at its

source, that lies deep in human reason. We shall divide it into two

parts, the first of which will treat of the transcendent conceptions

of pure reason, the second of transcendent and dialectical syllogisms.

                           BOOK I.



             OF THE CONCEPTIONS OF PURE REASON.



  The conceptions of pure reason- we do not here speak of the

possibility of them- are not obtained by reflection, but by

inference or conclusion. The conceptions of understanding are also

cogitated a priori antecedently to experience, and render it possible;

but they contain nothing but the unity of reflection upon phenomena,

in so far as these must necessarily belong to a possible empirical

consciousness. Through them alone are cognition and the

determination of an object possible. It is from them, accordingly,

that we receive material for reasoning, and antecedently to them we

possess no a priori conceptions of objects from which they might be

deduced, On the other hand, the sole basis of their objective

reality consists in the necessity imposed on them, as containing the

intellectual form of all experience, of restricting their

application and influence to the sphere of experience.

  But the term, conception of reason, or rational conception, itself

indicates that it does not confine itself within the limits of

experience, because its object-matter is a cognition, of which every

empirical cognition is but a part- nay, the whole of possible

experience may be itself but a part of it- a cognition to which no

actual experience ever fully attains, although it does always

pertain to it. The aim of rational conceptions is the comprehension,

as that of the conceptions of understanding is the understanding of

perceptions. If they contain the unconditioned, they relate to that to

which all experience is subordinate, but which is never itself an

object of experience- that towards which reason tends in all its

conclusions from experience, and by the standard of which it estimates

the degree of their empirical use, but which is never itself an

element in an empirical synthesis. If, notwithstanding, such

conceptions possess objective validity, they may be called conceptus

ratiocinati (conceptions legitimately concluded); in cases where

they do not, they have been admitted on account of having the

appearance of being correctly concluded, and may be called conceptus

ratiocinantes (sophistical conceptions). But as this can only be

sufficiently demonstrated in that part of our treatise which relates

to the dialectical conclusions of reason, we shall omit any

consideration of it in this place. As we called the pure conceptions

of the understanding categories, we shall also distinguish those of

pure reason by a new name and call them transcendental ideas. These

terms, however, we must in the first place explain and justify.



               SECTION I - Of Ideas in General.



  Despite the great wealth of words which European languages

possess, the thinker finds himself often at a loss for an expression

exactly suited to his conception, for want of which he is unable to

make himself intelligible either to others or to himself. To coin

new words is a pretension to legislation in language which is seldom

successful; and, before recourse is taken to so desperate an

expedient, it is advisable to examine the dead and learned

languages, with the hope and the probability that we may there meet

with some adequate expression of the notion we have in our minds. In

this case, even if the original meaning of the word has become

somewhat uncertain, from carelessness or want of caution on the part

of the authors of it, it is always better to adhere to and confirm its

proper meaning- even although it may be doubtful whether it was

formerly used in exactly this sense- than to make our labour vain by

want of sufficient care to render ourselves intelligible.

  For this reason, when it happens that there exists only a single

word to express a certain conception, and this word, in its usual

acceptation, is thoroughly adequate to the conception, the accurate

distinction of which from related conceptions is of great

importance, we ought not to employ the expression improvidently, or,

for the sake of variety and elegance of style, use it as a synonym for

other cognate words. It is our duty, on the contrary, carefully to

preserve its peculiar signification, as otherwise it easily happens

that when the attention of the reader is no longer particularly

attracted to the expression, and it is lost amid the multitude of

other words of very different import, the thought which it conveyed,

and which it alone conveyed, is lost with it.

  Plato employed the expression idea in a way that plainly showed he

meant by it something which is never derived from the senses, but

which far transcends even the conceptions of the understanding (with

which Aristotle occupied himself), inasmuch as in experience nothing

perfectly corresponding to them could be found. Ideas are, according

to him, archetypes of things themselves, and not merely keys to

possible experiences, like the categories. In his view they flow

from the highest reason, by which they have been imparted to human

reason, which, however, exists no longer in its original state, but is

obliged with great labour to recall by reminiscence- which is called

philosophy- the old but now sadly obscured ideas. I will not here

enter upon any literary investigation of the sense which this

sublime philosopher attached to this expression. I shall content

myself with remarking that it is nothing unusual, in common

conversation as well as in written works, by comparing the thoughts

which an author has delivered upon a subject, to understand him better

than he understood himself inasmuch as he may not have sufficiently

determined his conception, and thus have sometimes spoken, nay even

thought, in opposition to his own opinions.

  Plato perceived very clearly that our faculty of cognition has the

feeling of a much higher vocation than that of merely spelling out

phenomena according to synthetical unity, for the purpose of being

able to read them as experience, and that our reason naturally

raises itself to cognitions far too elevated to admit of the

possibility of an object given by experience corresponding to them-

cognitions which are nevertheless real, and are not mere phantoms of

the brain.

  This philosopher found his ideas especially in all that is

practical,* that is, which rests upon freedom, which in its turn ranks

under cognitions that are the peculiar product of reason. He who would

derive from experience the conceptions of virtue, who would make (as

many have really done) that, which at best can but serve as an

imperfectly illustrative example, a model for or the formation of a

perfectly adequate idea on the subject, would in fact transform virtue

into a nonentity changeable according to time and circumstance and

utterly incapable of being employed as a rule. On the contrary,

every one is conscious that, when any one is held up to him as a model

of virtue, he compares this so-called model with the true original

which he possesses in his own mind and values him according to this

standard. But this standard is the idea of virtue, in relation to

which all possible objects of experience are indeed serviceable as

examples- proofs of the practicability in a certain degree of that

which the conception of virtue demands- but certainly not as

archetypes. That the actions of man will never be in perfect

accordance with all the requirements of the pure ideas of reason, does

not prove the thought to be chimerical. For only through this idea are

all judgements as to moral merit or demerit possible; it

consequently lies at the foundation of every approach to moral

perfection, however far removed from it the obstacles in human nature-

indeterminable as to degree- may keep us.



  *He certainly extended the application of his conception to

speculative cognitions also, provided they were given pure and

completely a priori, nay, even to mathematics, although this science

cannot possess an object otherwhere than in Possible experience. I

cannot follow him in this, and as little can I follow him in his

mystical deduction of these ideas, or in his hypostatization of

them; although, in truth, the elevated and exaggerated language

which he employed in describing them is quite capable of an

interpretation more subdued and more in accordance with fact and the

nature of things.



  The Platonic Republic has become proverbial as an example- and a

striking one- of imaginary perfection, such as can exist only in the

brain of the idle thinker; and Brucker ridicules the philosopher for

maintaining that a prince can never govern well, unless he is

participant in the ideas. But we should do better to follow up this

thought and, where this admirable thinker leaves us without

assistance, employ new efforts to place it in clearer light, rather

than carelessly fling it aside as useless, under the very miserable

and pernicious pretext of impracticability. A constitution of the

greatest possible human freedom according to laws, by which the

liberty of every individual can consist with the liberty of every

other (not of the greatest possible happiness, for this follows

necessarily from the former), is, to say the least, a necessary

idea, which must be placed at the foundation not only of the first

plan of the constitution of a state, but of all its laws. And, in

this, it not necessary at the outset to take account of the

obstacles which lie in our way- obstacles which perhaps do not

necessarily arise from the character of human nature, but rather

from the previous neglect of true ideas in legislation. For there is

nothing more pernicious and more unworthy of a philosopher, than the

vulgar appeal to a so-called adverse experience, which indeed would

not have existed, if those institutions had been established at the

proper time and in accordance with ideas; while, instead of this,

conceptions, crude for the very reason that they have been drawn

from experience, have marred and frustrated all our better views and

intentions. The more legislation and government are in harmony with

this idea, the more rare do punishments become and thus it is quite

reasonable to maintain, as Plato did, that in a perfect state no

punishments at all would be necessary. Now although a perfect state

may never exist, the idea is not on that account the less just,

which holds up this maximum as the archetype or standard of a

constitution, in order to bring legislative government always nearer

and nearer to the greatest possible perfection. For at what precise

degree human nature must stop in its progress, and how wide must be

the chasm which must necessarily exist between the idea and its

realization, are problems which no one can or ought to determine-

and for this reason, that it is the destination of freedom to overstep

all assigned limits between itself and the idea.

  But not only in that wherein human reason is a real causal agent and

where ideas are operative causes (of actions and their objects),

that is to say, in the region of ethics, but also in regard to

nature herself, Plato saw clear proofs of an origin from ideas. A

plant, and animal, the regular order of nature- probably also the

disposition of the whole universe- give manifest evidence that they

are possible only by means of and according to ideas; that, indeed, no

one creature, under the individual conditions of its existence,

perfectly harmonizes with the idea of the most perfect of its kind-

just as little as man with the idea of humanity, which nevertheless he

bears in his soul as the archetypal standard of his actions; that,

notwithstanding, these ideas are in the highest sense individually,

unchangeably, and completely determined, and are the original causes

of things; and that the totality of connected objects in the

universe is alone fully adequate to that idea. Setting aside the

exaggerations of expression in the writings of this philosopher, the

mental power exhibited in this ascent from the ectypal mode of

regarding the physical world to the architectonic connection thereof

according to ends, that is, ideas, is an effort which deserves

imitation and claims respect. But as regards the principles of ethics,

of legislation, and of religion, spheres in which ideas alone render

experience possible, although they never attain to full expression

therein, he has vindicated for himself a position of peculiar merit,

which is not appreciated only because it is judged by the very

empirical rules, the validity of which as principles is destroyed by

ideas. For as regards nature, experience presents us with rules and is

the source of truth, but in relation to ethical laws experience is the

parent of illusion, and it is in the highest degree reprehensible to

limit or to deduce the laws which dictate what I ought to do, from

what is done.

  We must, however, omit the consideration of these important

subjects, the development of which is in reality the peculiar duty and

dignity of philosophy, and confine ourselves for the present to the

more humble but not less useful task of preparing a firm foundation

for those majestic edifices of moral science. For this foundation

has been hitherto insecure from the many subterranean passages which

reason in its confident but vain search for treasures has made in

all directions. Our present duty is to make ourselves perfectly

acquainted with the transcendental use made of pure reason, its

principles and ideas, that we may be able properly to determine and

value its influence and real worth. But before bringing these

introductory remarks to a close, I beg those who really have

philosophy at heart- and their number is but small- if they shall find

themselves convinced by the considerations following as well as by

those above, to exert themselves to preserve to the expression idea

its original signification, and to take care that it be not lost among

those other expressions by which all sorts of representations are

loosely designated- that the interests of science may not thereby

suffer. We are in no want of words to denominate adequately every mode

of representation, without the necessity of encroaching upon terms

which are proper to others. The following is a graduated list of them.

The genus is representation in general (representation. Under it

stands representation with consciousness (perceptio). A perception

which relates solely to the subject as a modification of its state, is

a sensation (sensatio), an objective perception is a cognition

(cognitio). A cognition is either an intuition or a conception

(intuitus vel conceptus). The former has an immediate relation to

the object and is singular and individual; the latter has but a

mediate relation, by means of a characteristic mark which may be

common to several things. A conception is either empirical or pure.

A pure conception, in so far as it has its origin in the understanding

alone, and is not the conception of a pure sensuous image, is called

notio. A conception formed from notions, which transcends the

possibility of experience, is an idea, or a conception of reason. To

one who has accustomed himself to these distinctions, it must be quite

intolerable to hear the representation of the colour red called an

idea. It ought not even to be called a notion or conception of

understanding.



             SECTION II. Of Transcendental Ideas.



  Transcendental analytic showed us how the mere logical form of our

cognition can contain the origin of pure conceptions a priori,

conceptions which represent objects antecedently to all experience, or

rather, indicate the synthetical unity which alone renders possible an

empirical cognition of objects. The form of judgements- converted into

a conception of the synthesis of intuitions- produced the categories

which direct the employment of the understanding in experience. This

consideration warrants us to expect that the form of syllogisms,

when applied to synthetical unity of intuitions, following the rule of

the categories, will contain the origin of particular a priori

conceptions, which we may call pure conceptions of reason or

transcendental ideas, and which will determine the use of the

understanding in the totality of experience according to principles.

  The function of reason in arguments consists in the universality

of a cognition according to conceptions, and the syllogism itself is a

judgement which is determined a priori in the whole extent of its

condition. The proposition: "Caius is mortal," is one which may be

obtained from experience by the aid of the understanding alone; but my

wish is to find a conception which contains the condition under

which the predicate of this judgement is given- in this case, the

conception of man- and after subsuming under this condition, taken

in its whole extent (all men are mortal), I determine according to

it the cognition of the object thought, and say: "Caius is mortal."

  Hence, in the conclusion of a syllogism we restrict a predicate to a

certain object, after having thought it in the major in its whole

extent under a certain condition. This complete quantity of the extent

in relation to such a condition is called universality

(universalitas). To this corresponds totality (universitas) of

conditions in the synthesis of intuitions. The transcendental

conception of reason is therefore nothing else than the conception

of the totality of the conditions of a given conditioned. Now as the

unconditioned alone renders possible totality of conditions, and,

conversely, the totality of conditions is itself always unconditioned;

a pure rational conception in general can be defined and explained

by means of the conception of the unconditioned, in so far as it

contains a basis for the synthesis of the conditioned.

  To the number of modes of relation which the understanding cogitates

by means of the categories, the number of pure rational conceptions

will correspond. We must therefore seek for, first, an unconditioned

of the categorical synthesis in a subject; secondly, of the

hypothetical synthesis of the members of a series; thirdly, of the

disjunctive synthesis of parts in a system.

  There are exactly the same number of modes of syllogisms, each of

which proceeds through prosyllogisms to the unconditioned- one to

the subject which cannot be employed as predicate, another to the

presupposition which supposes nothing higher than itself, and the

third to an aggregate of the members of the complete division of a

conception. Hence the pure rational conceptions of totality in the

synthesis of conditions have a necessary foundation in the nature of

human reason- at least as modes of elevating the unity of the

understanding to the unconditioned. They may have no valid

application, corresponding to their transcendental employment, in

concreto, and be thus of no greater utility than to direct the

understanding how, while extending them as widely as possible, to

maintain its exercise and application in perfect consistence and

harmony.

  But, while speaking here of the totality of conditions and of the

unconditioned as the common title of all conceptions of reason, we

again light upon an expression which we find it impossible to dispense

with, and which nevertheless, owing to the ambiguity attaching to it

from long abuse, we cannot employ with safety. The word absolute is

one of the few words which, in its original signification, was

perfectly adequate to the conception it was intended to convey- a

conception which no other word in the same language exactly suits, and

the loss- or, which is the same thing, the incautious and loose

employment- of which must be followed by the loss of the conception

itself. And, as it is a conception which occupies much of the

attention of reason, its loss would be greatly to the detriment of all

transcendental philosophy. The word absolute is at present

frequently used to denote that something can be predicated of a

thing considered in itself and intrinsically. In this sense absolutely

possible would signify that which is possible in itself (interne)-

which is, in fact, the least that one can predicate of an object. On

the other hand, it is sometimes employed to indicate that a thing is

valid in all respects- for example, absolute sovereignty. Absolutely

possible would in this sense signify that which is possible in all

relations and in every respect; and this is the most that can be

predicated of the possibility of a thing. Now these significations

do in truth frequently coincide. Thus, for example, that which is

intrinsically impossible, is also impossible in all relations, that

is, absolutely impossible. But in most cases they differ from each

other toto caelo, and I can by no means conclude that, because a thing

is in itself possible, it is also possible in all relations, and

therefore absolutely. Nay, more, I shall in the sequel show that

absolute necessity does not by any means depend on internal necessity,

and that, therefore, it must not be considered as synonymous with

it. Of an opposite which is intrinsically impossible, we may affirm

that it is in all respects impossible, and that, consequently, the

thing itself, of which this is the opposite, is absolutely

necessary; but I cannot reason conversely and say, the opposite of

that which is absolutely necessary is intrinsically impossible, that

is, that the absolute necessity of things is an internal necessity.

For this internal necessity is in certain cases a mere empty word with

which the least conception cannot be connected, while the conception

of the necessity of a thing in all relations possesses very peculiar

determinations. Now as the loss of a conception of great utility in

speculative science cannot be a matter of indifference to the

philosopher, I trust that the proper determination and careful

preservation of the expression on which the conception depends will

likewise be not indifferent to him.

  In this enlarged signification, then, shall I employ the word

absolute, in opposition to that which is valid only in some particular

respect; for the latter is restricted by conditions, the former is

valid without any restriction whatever.

  Now the transcendental conception of reason has for its object

nothing else than absolute totality in the synthesis of conditions and

does not rest satisfied till it has attained to the absolutely, that

is, in all respects and relations, unconditioned. For pure reason

leaves to the understanding everything that immediately relates to the

object of intuition or rather to their synthesis in imagination. The

former restricts itself to the absolute totality in the employment

of the conceptions of the understanding and aims at carrying out the

synthetical unity which is cogitated in the category, even to the

unconditioned. This unity may hence be called the rational unity of

phenomena, as the other, which the category expresses, may be termed

the unity of the understanding. Reason, therefore, has an immediate

relation to the use of the understanding, not indeed in so far as

the latter contains the ground of possible experience (for the

conception of the absolute totality of conditions is not a

conception that can be employed in experience, because no experience

is unconditioned), but solely for the purpose of directing it to a

certain unity, of which the understanding has no conception, and the

aim of which is to collect into an absolute whole all acts of the

understanding. Hence the objective employment of the pure

conceptions of reason is always transcendent, while that of the pure

conceptions of the understanding must, according to their nature, be

always immanent, inasmuch as they are limited to possible experience.

  I understand by idea a necessary conception of reason, to which no

corresponding object can be discovered in the world of sense.

Accordingly, the pure conceptions of reason at present under

consideration are transcendental ideas. They are conceptions of pure

reason, for they regard all empirical cognition as determined by means

of an absolute totality of conditions. They are not mere fictions, but

natural and necessary products of reason, and have hence a necessary

relation to the whole sphere of the exercise of the understanding.

And, finally, they are transcendent, and overstep the limits of all

experiences, in which, consequently, no object can ever be presented

that would be perfectly adequate to a transcendental idea. When we use

the word idea, we say, as regards its object (an object of the pure

understanding), a great deal, but as regards its subject (that is,

in respect of its reality under conditions of experience), exceedingly

little, because the idea, as the conception of a maximum, can never be

completely and adequately presented in concreto. Now, as in the merely

speculative employment of reason the latter is properly the sole

aim, and as in this case the approximation to a conception, which is

never attained in practice, is the same thing as if the conception

were non-existent- it is commonly said of the conception of this kind,

"it is only an idea." So we might very well say, "the absolute

totality of all phenomena is only an idea," for, as we never can

present an adequate representation of it, it remains for us a

problem incapable of solution. On the other hand, as in the

practical use of the understanding we have only to do with action

and practice according to rules, an idea of pure reason can always

be given really in concreto, although only partially, nay, it is the

indispensable condition of all practical employment of reason. The

practice or execution of the idea is always limited and defective, but

nevertheless within indeterminable boundaries, consequently always

under the influence of the conception of an absolute perfection. And

thus the practical idea is always in the highest degree fruitful,

and in relation to real actions indispensably necessary. In the

idea, pure reason possesses even causality and the power of

producing that which its conception contains. Hence we cannot say of

wisdom, in a disparaging way, "it is only an idea." For, for the

very reason that it is the idea of the necessary unity of all possible

aims, it must be for all practical exertions and endeavours the

primitive condition and rule- a rule which, if not constitutive, is at

least limitative.

  Now, although we must say of the transcendental conceptions of

reason, "they are only ideas," we must not, on this account, look upon

them as superfluous and nugatory. For, although no object can be

determined by them, they can be of great utility, unobserved and at

the basis of the edifice of the understanding, as the canon for its

extended and self-consistent exercise- a canon which, indeed, does not

enable it to cognize more in an object than it would cognize by the

help of its own conceptions, but which guides it more securely in

its cognition. Not to mention that they perhaps render possible a

transition from our conceptions of nature and the non-ego to the

practical conceptions, and thus produce for even ethical ideas

keeping, so to speak, and connection with the speculative cognitions

of reason. The explication of all this must be looked for in the

sequel.

  But setting aside, in conformity with our original purpose, the

consideration of the practical ideas, we proceed to contemplate reason

in its speculative use alone, nay, in a still more restricted

sphere, to wit, in the transcendental use; and here must strike into

the same path which we followed in our deduction of the categories.

That is to say, we shall consider the logical form of the cognition of

reason, that we may see whether reason may not be thereby a source

of conceptions which enables us to regard objects in themselves as

determined synthetically a priori, in relation to one or other of

the functions of reason.

  Reason, considered as the faculty of a certain logical form of

cognition, is the faculty of conclusion, that is, of mediate

judgement- by means of the subsumption of the condition of a

possible judgement under the condition of a given judgement. The given

judgement is the general rule (major). The subsumption of the

condition of another possible judgement under the condition of the

rule is the minor. The actual judgement, which enounces the

assertion of the rule in the subsumed case, is the conclusion

(conclusio). The rule predicates something generally under a certain

condition. The condition of the rule is satisfied in some particular

case. It follows that what was valid in general under that condition

must also be considered as valid in the particular case which

satisfies this condition. It is very plain that reason attains to a

cognition, by means of acts of the understanding which constitute a

series of conditions. When I arrive at the proposition, "All bodies

are changeable," by beginning with the more remote cognition (in which

the conception of body does not appear, but which nevertheless

contains the condition of that conception), "All compound is

changeable," by proceeding from this to a less remote cognition, which

stands under the condition of the former, "Bodies are compound," and

hence to a third, which at length connects for me the remote cognition

(changeable) with the one before me, "Consequently, bodies are

changeable"- I have arrived at a cognition (conclusion) through a

series of conditions (premisses). Now every series, whose exponent (of

the categorical or hypothetical judgement) is given, can be continued;

consequently the same procedure of reason conducts us to the

ratiocinatio polysyllogistica, which is a series of syllogisms, that

can be continued either on the side of the conditions (per

prosyllogismos) or of the conditioned (per episyllogismos) to an

indefinite extent.

  But we very soon perceive that the chain or series of prosyllogisms,

that is, of deduced cognitions on the side of the grounds or

conditions of a given cognition, in other words, the ascending

series of syllogisms must have a very different relation to the

faculty of reason from that of the descending series, that is, the

progressive procedure of reason on the side of the conditioned by

means of episyllogisms. For, as in the former case the cognition

(conclusio) is given only as conditioned, reason can attain to this

cognition only under the presupposition that all the members of the

series on the side of the conditions are given (totality in the series

of premisses), because only under this supposition is the judgement we

may be considering possible a priori; while on the side of the

conditioned or the inferences, only an incomplete and becoming, and

not a presupposed or given series, consequently only a potential

progression, is cogitated. Hence, when a cognition is contemplated

as conditioned, reason is compelled to consider the series of

conditions in an ascending line as completed and given in their

totality. But if the very same condition is considered at the same

time as the condition of other cognitions, which together constitute a

series of inferences or consequences in a descending line, reason

may preserve a perfect indifference, as to how far this progression

may extend a parte posteriori, and whether the totality of this series

is possible, because it stands in no need of such a series for the

purpose of arriving at the conclusion before it, inasmuch as this

conclusion is sufficiently guaranteed and determined on grounds a

parte priori. It may be the case, that upon the side of the conditions

the series of premisses has a first or highest condition, or it may

not possess this, and so be a parte priori unlimited; but it must,

nevertheless, contain totality of conditions, even admitting that we

never could succeed in completely apprehending it; and the whole

series must be unconditionally true, if the conditioned, which is

considered as an inference resulting from it, is to be held as true.

This is a requirement of reason, which announces its cognition as

determined a priori and as necessary, either in itself- and in this

case it needs no grounds to rest upon- or, if it is deduced, as a

member of a series of grounds, which is itself unconditionally true.



        SECTION III. System of Transcendental Ideas.



  We are not at present engaged with a logical dialectic, which

makes complete abstraction of the content of cognition and aims only

at unveiling the illusory appearance in the form of syllogisms. Our

subject is transcendental dialectic, which must contain, completely

a priori, the origin of certain cognitions drawn from pure reason, and

the origin of certain deduced conceptions, the object of which

cannot be given empirically and which therefore lie beyond the

sphere of the faculty of understanding. We have observed, from the

natural relation which the transcendental use of our cognition, in

syllogisms as well as in judgements, must have to the logical, that

there are three kinds of dialectical arguments, corresponding to the

three modes of conclusion, by which reason attains to cognitions on

principles; and that in all it is the business of reason to ascend

from the conditioned synthesis, beyond which the understanding never

proceeds, to the unconditioned which the understanding never can

reach.

  Now the most general relations which can exist in our

representations are: 1st, the relation to the subject; 2nd, the

relation to objects, either as phenomena, or as objects of thought

in general. If we connect this subdivision with the main division, all

the relations of our representations, of which we can form either a

conception or an idea, are threefold: 1. The relation to the

subject; 2. The relation to the manifold of the object as a

phenomenon; 3. The relation to all things in general.

  Now all pure conceptions have to do in general with the

synthetical unity of representations; conceptions of pure reason

(transcendental ideas), on the other hand, with the unconditional

synthetical unity of all conditions. It follows that all

transcendental ideas arrange themselves in three classes, the first of

which contains the absolute (unconditioned) unity of the thinking

subject, the second the absolute unity of the series of the conditions

of a phenomenon, the third the absolute unity of the condition of

all objects of thought in general.

  The thinking subject is the object-matter of Psychology; the sum

total of all phenomena (the world) is the object-matter of

Cosmology; and the thing which contains the highest condition of the

possibility of all that is cogitable (the being of all beings) is

the object-matter of all Theology. Thus pure reason presents us with

the idea of a transcendental doctrine of the soul (psychologia

rationalis), of a transcendental science of the world (cosmologia

rationalis), and finally of a transcendental doctrine of God

(theologia transcendentalis). Understanding cannot originate even

the outline of any of these sciences, even when connected with the

highest logical use of reason, that is, all cogitable syllogisms-

for the purpose of proceeding from one object (phenomenon) to all

others, even to the utmost limits of the empirical synthesis. They

are, on the contrary, pure and genuine products, or problems, of

pure reason.

  What modi of the pure conceptions of reason these transcendental

ideas are will be fully exposed in the following chapter. They

follow the guiding thread of the categories. For pure reason never

relates immediately to objects, but to the conceptions of these

contained in the understanding. In like manner, it will be made

manifest in the detailed explanation of these ideas- how reason,

merely through the synthetical use of the same function which it

employs in a categorical syllogism, necessarily attains to the

conception of the absolute unity of the thinking subject- how the

logical procedure in hypothetical ideas necessarily produces the

idea of the absolutely unconditioned in a series of given

conditions, and finally- how the mere form of the disjunctive

syllogism involves the highest conception of a being of all beings:

a thought which at first sight seems in the highest degree

paradoxical.

  An objective deduction, such as we were able to present in the

case of the categories, is impossible as regards these

transcendental ideas. For they have, in truth, no relation to any

object, in experience, for the very reason that they are only ideas.

But a subjective deduction of them from the nature of our reason is

possible, and has been given in the present chapter.

  It is easy to perceive that the sole aim of pure reason is the

absolute totality of the synthesis on the side of the conditions,

and that it does not concern itself with the absolute completeness

on the Part of the conditioned. For of the former alone does she stand

in need, in order to preposit the whole series of conditions, and thus

present them to the understanding a priori. But if we once have a

completely (and unconditionally) given condition, there is no

further necessity, in proceeding with the series, for a conception

of reason; for the understanding takes of itself every step

downward, from the condition to the conditioned. Thus the

transcendental ideas are available only for ascending in the series of

conditions, till we reach the unconditioned, that is, principles. As

regards descending to the conditioned, on the other hand, we find that

there is a widely extensive logical use which reason makes of the laws

of the understanding, but that a transcendental use thereof is

impossible; and that when we form an idea of the absolute totality

of such a synthesis, for example, of the whole series of all future

changes in the world, this idea is a mere ens rationis, an arbitrary

fiction of thought, and not a necessary presupposition of reason.

For the possibility of the conditioned presupposes the totality of its

conditions, but not of its consequences. Consequently, this conception

is not a transcendental idea- and it is with these alone that we are

at present occupied.

  Finally, it is obvious that there exists among the transcendental

ideas a certain connection and unity, and that pure reason, by means

of them, collects all its cognitions into one system. From the

cognition of self to the cognition of the world, and through these

to the supreme being, the progression is so natural, that it seems

to resemble the logical march of reason from the premisses to the

conclusion.* Now whether there lies unobserved at the foundation of

these ideas an analogy of the same kind as exists between the

logical and transcendental procedure of reason, is another of those

questions, the answer to which we must not expect till we arrive at

a more advanced stage in our inquiries. In this cursory and

preliminary view, we have, meanwhile, reached our aim. For we have

dispelled the ambiguity which attached to the transcendental

conceptions of reason, from their being commonly mixed up with other

conceptions in the systems of philosophers, and not properly

distinguished from the conceptions of the understanding; we have

exposed their origin and, thereby, at the same time their

determinate number, and presented them in a systematic connection, and

have thus marked out and enclosed a definite sphere for pure reason.



  *The science of Metaphysics has for the proper object of its

inquiries only three grand ideas: GOD, FREEDOM, and IMMORTALITY, and

it aims at showing, that the second conception, conjoined with the

first, must lead to the third, as a necessary conclusion. All the

other subjects with which it occupies itself, are merely means for the

attainment and realization of these ideas. It does not require these

ideas for the construction of a science of nature, but, on the

contrary, for the purpose of passing beyond the sphere of nature. A

complete insight into and comprehension of them would render Theology,

Ethics, and, through the conjunction of both, Religion, solely

dependent on the speculative faculty of reason. In a systematic

representation of these ideas the above-mentioned arrangement- the

synthetical one- would be the most suitable; but in the

investigation which must necessarily precede it, the analytical, which

reverses this arrangement, would be better adapted to our purpose,

as in it we should proceed from that which experience immediately

presents to us- psychology, to cosmology, and thence to theology.

                        BOOK II.



        OF THE DIALECTICAL PROCEDURE OF PURE REASON.



  It may be said that the object of a merely transcendental idea is

something of which we have no conception, although the idea may be a

necessary product of reason according to its original laws. For, in

fact, a conception of an object that is adequate to the idea given

by reason, is impossible. For such an object must be capable of

being presented and intuited in a Possible experience. But we should

express our meaning better, and with less risk of being misunderstood,

if we said that we can have no knowledge of an object, which perfectly

corresponds to an idea, although we may possess a problematical

conception thereof.

  Now the transcendental (subjective) reality at least of the pure

conceptions of reason rests upon the fact that we are led to such

ideas by a necessary procedure of reason. There must therefore be

syllogisms which contain no empirical premisses, and by means of which

we conclude from something that we do know, to something of which we

do not even possess a conception, to which we, nevertheless, by an

unavoidable illusion, ascribe objective reality. Such arguments are,

as regards their result, rather to be termed sophisms than syllogisms,

although indeed, as regards their origin, they are very well

entitled to the latter name, inasmuch as they are not fictions or

accidental products of reason, but are necessitated by its very

nature. They are sophisms, not of men, but of pure reason herself,

from which the Wisest cannot free himself. After long labour he may be

able to guard against the error, but he can never be thoroughly rid of

the illusion which continually mocks and misleads him.

  Of these dialectical arguments there are three kinds,

corresponding to the number of the ideas which their conclusions

present. In the argument or syllogism of the first class, I

conclude, from the transcendental conception of the subject contains

no manifold, the absolute unity of the subject itself, of which I

cannot in this manner attain to a conception. This dialectical

argument I shall call the transcendental paralogism. The second

class of sophistical arguments is occupied with the transcendental

conception of the absolute totality of the series of conditions for

a given phenomenon, and I conclude, from the fact that I have always a

self-contradictory conception of the unconditioned synthetical unity

of the series upon one side, the truth of the opposite unity, of which

I have nevertheless no conception. The condition of reason in these

dialectical arguments, I shall term the antinomy of pure reason.

Finally, according to the third kind of sophistical argument, I

conclude, from the totality of the conditions of thinking objects in

general, in so far as they can be given, the absolute synthetical

unity of all conditions of the possibility of things in general;

that is, from things which I do not know in their mere

transcendental conception, I conclude a being of all beings which I

know still less by means of a transcendental conception, and of

whose unconditioned necessity I can form no conception whatever.

This dialectical argument I shall call the ideal of pure reason.

          CHAPTER I. Of the Paralogisms of Pure Reason.



  The logical paralogism consists in the falsity of an argument in

respect of its form, be the content what it may. But a

transcendental paralogism has a transcendental foundation, and

concludes falsely, while the form is correct and unexceptionable. In

this manner the paralogism has its foundation in the nature of human

reason, and is the parent of an unavoidable, though not insoluble,

mental illusion.

  We now come to a conception which was not inserted in the general

list of transcendental conceptions. and yet must be reckoned with

them, but at the same time without in the least altering, or

indicating a deficiency in that table. This is the conception, or,

if the term is preferred, the judgement, "I think." But it is

readily perceived that this thought is as it were the vehicle of all

conceptions in general, and consequently of transcendental conceptions

also, and that it is therefore regarded as a transcendental

conception, although it can have no peculiar claim to be so ranked,

inasmuch as its only use is to indicate that all thought is

accompanied by consciousness. At the same time, pure as this

conception is from empirical content (impressions of the senses), it

enables us to distinguish two different kinds of objects. "I," as

thinking, am an object of the internal sense, and am called soul. That

which is an object of the external senses is called body. Thus the

expression, "I," as a thinking being, designates the object-matter

of psychology, which may be called "the rational doctrine of the

soul," inasmuch as in this science I desire to know nothing of the

soul but what, independently of all experience (which determines me in

concreto), may be concluded from this conception "I," in so far as

it appears in all thought.

  Now, the rational doctrine of the soul is really an undertaking of

this kind. For if the smallest empirical element of thought, if any

particular perception of my internal state, were to be introduced

among the grounds of cognition of this science, it would not be a

rational, but an empirical doctrine of the soul. We have thus before

us a pretended science, raised upon the single proposition, "I think,"

whose foundation or want of foundation we may very properly, and

agreeably with the nature of a transcendental philosophy, here

examine. It ought not to be objected that in this proposition, which

expresses the perception of one's self, an internal experience is

asserted, and that consequently the rational doctrine of the soul

which is founded upon it, is not pure, but partly founded upon an

empirical principle. For this internal perception is nothing more than

the mere apperception, "I think," which in fact renders all

transcendental conceptions possible, in which we say, "I think

substance, cause, etc." For internal experience in general and its

possibility, or perception in general, and its relation to other

perceptions, unless some particular distinction or determination

thereof is empirically given, cannot be regarded as empirical

cognition, but as cognition of the empirical, and belongs to the

investigation of the possibility of every experience, which is

certainly transcendental. The smallest object of experience (for

example, only pleasure or pain), that should be included in the

general representation of self-consciousness, would immediately change

the rational into an empirical psychology.

  "I think" is therefore the only text of rational psychology, from

which it must develop its whole system. It is manifest that this

thought, when applied to an object (myself), can contain nothing but

transcendental predicates thereof; because the least empirical

predicate would destroy the purity of the science and its independence

of all experience.

  But we shall have to follow here the guidance of the categories-

only, as in the present case a thing, "I," as thinking being, is at

first given, we shall- not indeed change the order of the categories

as it stands in the table- but begin at the category of substance,

by which at the a thing a thing is represented and proceeds

backwards through the series. The topic of the rational doctrine of

the soul, from which everything else it may contain must be deduced,

is accordingly as follows:



            1                          2

  The Soul is SUBSTANCE       As regards its quality

                                it is SIMPLE



                      3

          As regards the different

          times in which it exists,

          it is numerically identical,

          that is UNITY, not Plurality.



                       4

  It is in relation to possible objects in space*



  *The reader, who may not so easily perceive the psychological

sense of these expressions, taken here in their transcendental

abstraction, and cannot guess why the latter attribute of the soul

belongs to the category of existence, will find the expressions

sufficiently explained and justified in the sequel. I have,

moreover, to apologize for the Latin terms which have been

employed,instead of their German synonyms, contrary to the rules of

correct writing. But I judged it better to sacrifice elegance to

perspicuity.



  From these elements originate all the conceptions of pure

psychology, by combination alone, without the aid of any other

principle. This substance, merely as an object of the internal

sense, gives the conception of Immateriality; as simple substance,

that of Incorruptibility; its identity, as intellectual substance,

gives the conception of Personality; all these three together,

Spirituality. Its relation to objects in space gives us the conception

of connection (commercium) with bodies. Thus it represents thinking

substance as the principle of life in matter, that is, as a soul

(anima), and as the ground of Animality; and this, limited and

determined by the conception of spirituality, gives us that of

Immortality.

  Now to these conceptions relate four paralogisms of a transcendental

psychology, which is falsely held to be a science of pure reason.

touching the nature of our thinking being. We can, however, lay at the

foundation of this science nothing but the simple and in itself

perfectly contentless representation "I which cannot even be called

a conception, but merely a consciousness which accompanies all

conceptions. By this "I," or "He," or "It," who or which thinks,

nothing more is represented than a transcendental subject of thought =

x, which is cognized only by means of the thoughts that are its

predicates, and of which, apart from these, we cannot form the least

conception. Hence in a perpetual circle, inasmuch as we must always

employ it, in order to frame any judgement respecting it. And this

inconvenience we find it impossible to rid ourselves of, because

consciousness in itself is not so much a representation distinguishing

a particular object, as a form of representation in general, in so far

as it may be termed cognition; for in and by cognition alone do I

think anything.

  It must, however, appear extraordinary at first sight that the

condition under which I think, and which is consequently a property of

my subject, should be held to be likewise valid for every existence

which thinks, and that we can presume to base upon a seemingly

empirical proposition a judgement which is apodeictic and universal,

to wit, that everything which thinks is constituted as the voice of my

consciousness declares it to be, that is, as a self-conscious being.

The cause of this belief is to be found in the fact that we

necessarily attribute to things a priori all the properties which

constitute conditions under which alone we can cogitate them. Now I

cannot obtain the least representation of a thinking being by means of

external experience, but solely through self-consciousness. Such

objects are consequently nothing more than the transference of this

consciousness of mine to other things which can only thus be

represented as thinking beings. The proposition, "I think," is, in the

present case, understood in a problematical sense, not in so far as it

contains a perception of an existence (like the Cartesian "Cogito,

ergo sum"),* but in regard to its mere possibility- for the purpose of

discovering what properties may be inferred from so simple a

proposition and predicated of the subject of it.



  *["I think, therefore I am."]



  If at the foundation of our pure rational cognition of thinking

beings there lay more than the mere Cogito- if we could likewise

call in aid observations on the play of our thoughts, and the thence

derived natural laws of the thinking self, there would arise an

empirical psychology which would be a kind of physiology of the

internal sense and might possibly be capable of explaining the

phenomena of that sense. But it could never be available for

discovering those properties which do not belong to possible

experience (such as the quality of simplicity), nor could it make

any apodeictic enunciation on the nature of thinking beings: it

would therefore not be a rational psychology.

  Now, as the proposition "I think" (in the problematical sense)

contains the form of every judgement in general and is the constant

accompaniment of all the categories, it is manifest that conclusions

are drawn from it only by a transcendental employment of the

understanding. This use of the understanding excludes all empirical

elements; and we cannot, as has been shown above, have any

favourable conception beforehand of its procedure. We shall

therefore follow with a critical eye this proposition through all

the predicaments of pure psychology; but we shall, for brevity's sake,

allow this examination to proceed in an uninterrupted connection.

  Before entering on this task, however, the following general

remark may help to quicken our attention to this mode of argument.

It is not merely through my thinking that I cognize an object, but

only through my determining a given intuition in relation to the unity

of consciousness in which all thinking consists. It follows that I

cognize myself, not through my being conscious of myself as

thinking, but only when I am conscious of the intuition of myself as

determined in relation to the function of thought. All the modi of

self-consciousness in thought are hence not conceptions of objects

(conceptions of the understanding- categories); they are mere

logical functions, which do not present to thought an object to be

cognized, and cannot therefore present my Self as an object. Not the

consciousness of the determining, but only that of the determinable

self, that is, of my internal intuition (in so far as the manifold

contained in it can be connected conformably with the general

condition of the unity of apperception in thought), is the object.

  1. In all judgements I am the determining subject of that relation

which constitutes a judgement. But that the I which thinks, must be

considered as in thought always a subject, and as a thing which cannot

be a predicate to thought, is an apodeictic and identical proposition.

But this proposition does not signify that I, as an object, am, for

myself, a self-subsistent being or substance. This latter statement-

an ambitious one- requires to be supported by data which are not to be

discovered in thought; and are perhaps (in so far as I consider the

thinking self merely as such) not to be discovered in the thinking

self at all.

  2. That the I or Ego of apperception, and consequently in all

thought, is singular or simple, an;3 cannot be resolved into a

plurality of subjects, and therefore indicates a logically simple

subject- this is self-evident from the very conception of an Ego,

and is consequently an analytical proposition. But this is not

tantamount to declaring that the thinking Ego is a simple substance-

for this would be a synthetical proposition. The conception of

substance always relates to intuitions, which with me cannot be

other than sensuous, and which consequently lie completely out of

the sphere of the understanding and its thought: but to this sphere

belongs the affirmation that the Ego is simple in thought. It would

indeed be surprising, if the conception of "substance," which in other

cases requires so much labour to distinguish from the other elements

presented by intuition- so much trouble, too, to discover whether it

can be simple (as in the case of the parts of matter)- should be

presented immediately to me, as if by revelation, in the poorest

mental representation of all.

  3. The proposition of the identity of my Self amidst all the

manifold representations of which I am conscious, is likewise a

proposition lying in the conceptions themselves, and is consequently

analytical. But this identity of the subject, of which I am

conscious in all its representations, does not relate to or concern

the intuition of the subject, by which it is given as an object.

This proposition cannot therefore enounce the identity of the

person, by which is understood the consciousness of the identity of

its own substance as a thinking being in all change and variation of

circumstances. To prove this, we should require not a mere analysis of

the proposition, but synthetical judgements based upon a given

intuition.

  4. I distinguish my own existence, as that of a thinking being, from

that of other things external to me- among which my body also is

reckoned. This is also an analytical proposition, for other things are

exactly those which I think as different or distinguished from myself.

But whether this consciousness of myself is possible without things

external to me; and whether therefore I can exist merely as a thinking

being (without being man)- cannot be known or inferred from this

proposition.

  Thus we have gained nothing as regards the cognition of myself as

object, by the analysis of the consciousness of my Self in thought.

The logical exposition of thought in general is mistaken for a

metaphysical determination of the object.

  Our Critique would be an investigation utterly superfluous, if there

existed a possibility of proving a priori, that all thinking beings

are in themselves simple substances, as such, therefore, possess the

inseparable attribute of personality, and are conscious of their

existence apart from and unconnected with matter. For we should thus

have taken a step beyond the world of sense, and have penetrated

into the sphere of noumena; and in this case the right could not be

denied us of extending our knowledge in this sphere, of establishing

ourselves, and, under a favouring star, appropriating to ourselves

possessions in it. For the proposition: "Every thinking being, as

such, is simple substance," is an a priori synthetical proposition;

because in the first place it goes beyond the conception which is

the subject of it, and adds to the mere notion of a thinking being the

mode of its existence, and in the second place annexes a predicate

(that of simplicity) to the latter conception- a predicate which it

could not have discovered in the sphere of experience. It would follow

that a priori synthetical propositions are possible and legitimate,

not only, as we have maintained, in relation to objects of possible

experience, and as principles of the possibility of this experience

itself, but are applicable to things in themselves- an inference which

makes an end of the whole of this Critique, and obliges us to fall

back on the old mode of metaphysical procedure. But indeed the

danger is not so great, if we look a little closer into the question.

  There lurks in the procedure of rational Psychology a paralogism,

which is represented in the following syllogism:

  That which cannot be cogitated otherwise than as subject, does not

exist otherwise than as subject, and is therefore substance.

  A thinking being, considered merely as such, cannot be cogitated

otherwise than as subject.

  Therefore it exists also as such, that is, as substance.

  In the major we speak of a being that can be cogitated generally and

in every relation, consequently as it may be given in intuition. But

in the minor we speak of the same being only in so far as it regards

itself as subject, relatively to thought and the unity of

consciousness, but not in relation to intuition, by which it is

presented as an object to thought. Thus the conclusion is here arrived

at by a Sophisma figurae dictionis.*



  *Thought is taken in the two premisses in two totally different

senses. In the major it is considered as relating and applying to

objects in general, consequently to objects of intuition also. In

the minor, we understand it as relating merely to

self-consciousness. In this sense, we do not cogitate an object, but

merely the relation to the self-consciousness of the subject, as the

form of thought. In the former premiss we speak of things which cannot

be cogitated otherwise than as subjects. In the second, we do not

speak of things, but of thought all objects being abstracted), in

which the Ego is always the subject of consciousness. Hence the

conclusion cannot be, "I cannot exist otherwise than as subject";

but only "I can, in cogitating my existence, employ my Ego only as the

subject of the judgement." But this is an identical proposition, and

throws no light on the mode of my existence.



  That this famous argument is a mere paralogism, will be plain to any

one who will consider the general remark which precedes our exposition

of the principles of the pure understanding, and the section on

noumena. For it was there proved that the conception of a thing, which

can exist per se- only as a subject and never as a predicate,

possesses no objective reality; that is to say, we can never know

whether there exists any object to correspond to the conception;

consequently, the conception is nothing more than a conception, and

from it we derive no proper knowledge. If this conception is to

indicate by the term substance, an object that can be given, if it

is to become a cognition, we must have at the foundation of the

cognition a permanent intuition, as the indispensable condition of its

objective reality. For through intuition alone can an object be given.

But in internal intuition there is nothing permanent, for the Ego is

but the consciousness of my thought. If then, we appeal merely to

thought, we cannot discover the necessary condition of the application

of the conception of substance- that is, of a subject existing per se-

to the subject as a thinking being. And thus the conception of the

simple nature of substance, which is connected with the objective

reality of this conception, is shown to be also invalid, and to be, in

fact, nothing more than the logical qualitative unity of

self-consciousness in thought; whilst we remain perfectly ignorant

whether the subject is composite or not.



       Refutation of the Argument of Mendelssohn for the

          Substantiality or Permanence of the Soul.



  This acute philosopher easily perceived the insufficiency of the

common argument which attempts to prove that the soul- it being

granted that it is a simple being- cannot perish by dissolution or

decomposition; he saw it is not impossible for it to cease to be by

extinction, or disappearance. He endeavoured to prove in his Phaedo,

that the soul cannot be annihilated, by showing that a simple being

cannot cease to exist. Inasmuch as, be said, a simple existence cannot

diminish, nor gradually lose portions of its being, and thus be by

degrees reduced to nothing (for it possesses no parts, and therefore

no multiplicity), between the moment in which it is, and the moment in

which it is not, no time can be discovered- which is impossible. But

this philosopher did not consider that, granting the soul to possess

this simple nature, which contains no parts external to each other and

consequently no extensive quantity, we cannot refuse to it any less

than to any other being, intensive quantity, that is, a degree of

reality in regard to all its faculties, nay, to all that constitutes

its existence. But this degree of reality can become less and less

through an infinite series of smaller degrees. It follows,

therefore, that this supposed substance- this thing, the permanence of

which is not assured in any other way, may, if not by decomposition,

by gradual loss (remissio) of its powers (consequently by

elanguescence, if I may employ this expression), be changed into

nothing. For consciousness itself has always a degree, which may be

lessened.* Consequently the faculty of being conscious may be

diminished; and so with all other faculties. The permanence of the

soul, therefore, as an object of the internal sense, remains

undemonstrated, nay, even indemonstrable. Its permanence in life is

evident, per se, inasmuch as the thinking being (as man) is to itself,

at the same time, an object of the external senses. But this does

not authorize the rational psychologist to affirm, from mere

conceptions, its permanence beyond life.*[2]



  *Clearness is not, as logicians maintain, the consciousness of a

representation. For a certain degree of consciousness, which may

not, however, be sufficient for recollection, is to be met with in

many dim representations. For without any consciousness at all, we

should not be able to recognize any difference in the obscure

representations we connect; as we really can do with many conceptions,

such as those of right and justice, and those of the musician, who

strikes at once several notes in improvising a piece of music. But a

representation is clear, in which our consciousness is sufficient

for the consciousness of the difference of this representation from

others. If we are only conscious that there is a difference, but are

not conscious of the difference- that is, what the difference is-

the representation must be termed obscure. There is, consequently,

an infinite series of degrees of consciousness down to its entire

disappearance.

  *[2] There are some who think they have done enough to establish a

new possibility in the mode of the existence of souls, when they

have shown that there is no contradiction in their hypotheses on

this subject. Such are those who affirm the possibility of thought- of

which they have no other knowledge than what they derive from its

use in connecting empirical intuitions presented in this our human

life- after this life bas ceased. But it is very easy to embarrass

them by the introduction of counter-possibilities, which rest upon

quite as good a foundation. Such, for example, is the possibility of

the division of a simple substance into several substances; and

conversely, of the coalition of several into one simple substance.

For, although divisibility presupposes composition, it does not

necessarily require a composition of substances, but only of the

degrees (of the several faculties) of one and the same substance.

Now we can cogitate all the powers and faculties of the soul- even

that of consciousness- as diminished by one half, the substance

still remaining. In the same way we can represent to ourselves without

contradiction, this obliterated half as preserved, not in the soul,

but without it; and we can believe that, as in this case every.

thing that is real in the soul, and has a degree- consequently its

entire existence- has been halved, a particular substance would

arise out of the soul. For the multiplicity, which has been divided,

formerly existed, but not as a multiplicity of substances, but of

every reality as the quantum of existence in it; and the unity of

substance was merely a mode of existence, which by this division alone

has been transformed into a plurality of subsistence. In the same

manner several simple substances might coalesce into one, without

anything being lost except the plurality of subsistence, inasmuch as

the one substance would contain the degree of reality of all the

former substances. Perhaps, indeed, the simple substances, which

appear under the form of matter, might (not indeed by a mechanical

or chemical influence upon each other, but by an unknown influence, of

which the former would be but the phenomenal appearance), by means

of such a dynamical division of the parent-souls, as intensive

quantities, produce other souls, while the former repaired the loss

thus sustained with new matter of the same sort. I am far from

allowing any value to such chimeras; and the principles of our

analytic have clearly proved that no other than an empirical use of

the categories- that of substance, for example- is possible. But if

the rationalist is bold enough to construct, on the mere authority

of the faculty of thought- without any intuition, whereby an object is

given- a self-subsistent being, merely because the unity of

apperception in thought cannot allow him to believe it a composite

being, instead of declaring, as he ought to do, that he is unable to

explain the possibility of a thinking nature; what ought to hinder the

materialist, with as complete an independence of experience, to employ

the principle of the rationalist in a directly opposite manner-

still preserving the formal unity required by his opponent?



  If, now, we take the above propositions- as they must be accepted as

valid for all thinking beings in the system of rational psychology- in

synthetical connection, and proceed, from the category of relation,

with the proposition: "All thinking beings are, as such,

substances," backwards through the series, till the circle is

completed; we come at last to their existence, of which, in this

system of rational psychology, substances are held to be conscious,

independently of external things; nay, it is asserted that, in

relation to the permanence which is a necessary characteristic of

substance, they can of themselves determine external things. It

follows that idealism- at least problematical idealism, is perfectly

unavoidable in this rationalistic system. And, if the existence of

outward things is not held to be requisite to the determination of the

existence of a substance in time, the existence of these outward

things at all, is a gratuitous assumption which remains without the

possibility of a proof.

  But if we proceed analytically- the "I think" as a proposition

containing in itself an existence as given, consequently modality

being the principle- and dissect this proposition, in order to

ascertain its content, and discover whether and how this Ego

determines its existence in time and space without the aid of anything

external; the propositions of rationalistic psychology would not begin

with the conception of a thinking being, but with a reality, and the

properties of a thinking being in general would be deduced from the

mode in which this reality is cogitated, after everything empirical

had been abstracted; as is shown in the following table:



                        1

                      I think,



            2                             3

        as Subject,              as simple Subject,



                        4

               as identical Subject,

           in every state of my thought.



  Now, inasmuch as it is not determined in this second proposition,

whether I can exist and be cogitated only as subject, and not also

as a predicate of another being, the conception of a subject is here

taken in a merely logical sense; and it remains undetermined,

whether substance is to be cogitated under the conception or not.

But in the third proposition, the absolute unity of apperception-

the simple Ego in the representation to which all connection and

separation, which constitute thought, relate, is of itself

important; even although it presents us with no information about

the constitution or subsistence of the subject. Apperception is

something real, and the simplicity of its nature is given in the

very fact of its possibility. Now in space there is nothing real

that is at the same time simple; for points, which are the only simple

things in space, are merely limits, but not constituent parts of

space. From this follows the impossibility of a definition on the

basis of materialism of the constitution of my Ego as a merely

thinking subject. But, because my existence is considered in the first

proposition as given, for it does not mean, "Every thinking being

exists" (for this would be predicating of them absolute necessity),

but only, "I exist thinking"; the proposition is quite empirical,

and contains the determinability of my existence merely in relation to

my representations in time. But as I require for this purpose

something that is permanent, such as is not given in internal

intuition; the mode of my existence, whether as substance or as

accident, cannot be determined by means of this simple

self-consciousness. Thus, if materialism is inadequate to explain

the mode in which I exist, spiritualism is likewise as insufficient;

and the conclusion is that we are utterly unable to attain to any

knowledge of the constitution of the soul, in so far as relates to the

possibility of its existence apart from external objects.

  And, indeed, how should it be possible, merely by the aid of the

unity of consciousness- which we cognize only for the reason that it

is indispensable to the possibility of experience- to pass the

bounds of experience (our existence in this life); and to extend our

cognition to the nature of all thinking beings by means of the

empirical- but in relation to every sort of intuition, perfectly

undetermined- proposition, "I think"?

  There does not then exist any rational psychology as a doctrine

furnishing any addition to our knowledge of ourselves. It is nothing

more than a discipline, which sets impassable limits to speculative

reason in this region of thought, to prevent it, on the one hand, from

throwing itself into the arms of a soulless materialism, and, on the

other, from losing itself in the mazes of a baseless spiritualism.

It teaches us to consider this refusal of our reason to give any

satisfactory answer to questions which reach beyond the limits of this

our human life, as a hint to abandon fruitless speculation; and to

direct, to a practical use, our knowledge of ourselves- which,

although applicable only to objects of experience, receives its

principles from a higher source, and regulates its procedure as if our

destiny reached far beyond the boundaries of experience and life.

  From all this it is evident that rational psychology has its

origin in a mere misunderstanding. The unity of consciousness, which

lies at the basis of the categories, is considered to be an

intuition of the subject as an object; and the category of substance

is applied to the intuition. But this unity is nothing more than the

unity in thought, by which no object is given; to which therefore

the category of substance- which always presupposes a given intuition-

cannot be applied. Consequently, the subject cannot be cognized. The

subject of the categories cannot, therefore, for the very reason

that it cogitates these, frame any conception of itself as an object

of the categories; for, to cogitate these, it must lay at the

foundation its own pure self-consciousness- the very thing that it

wishes to explain and describe. In like manner, the subject, in

which the representation of time has its basis, cannot determine,

for this very reason, its own existence in time. Now, if the latter is

impossible, the former, as an attempt to determine itself by means

of the categories as a thinking being in general, is no less so.*



  *The "I think" is, as has been already stated, an empirical

proposition, and contains the proposition, "I exist." But I cannot

say, "Everything, which thinks, exists"; for in this case the property

of thought would constitute all beings possessing it, necessary

being Hence my existence cannot be considered as an inference from the

proposition, "I think," as Descartes maintained- because in this

case the major premiss, "Everything, which thinks, exists," must

precede- but the two propositions are identical. The proposition, "I

think," expresses an undetermined empirical intuition, that perception

(proving consequently that sensation, which must belong to

sensibility, lies at the foundation of this proposition); but it

precedes experience, whose province it is to determine an object of

perception by means of the categories in relation to time; and

existence in this proposition is not a category, as it does not

apply to an undetermined given object, but only to one of which we

have a conception, and about which we wish to know whether it does

or does not exist, out of, and apart from this conception. An

undetermined perception signifies here merely something real that

has been given, only, however, to thought in general- but not as a

phenomenon, nor as a thing in itself (noumenon), but only as something

that really exists, and is designated as such in the proposition, "I

think." For it must be remarked that, when I call the proposition,

"I think," an empirical proposition, I do not thereby mean that the

Ego in the proposition is an empirical representation; on the

contrary, it is purely intellectual, because it belongs to thought

in general. But without some empirical representation, which

presents to the mind material for thought, the mental act, "I

think," would not take place; and the empirical is only the

condition of the application or employment of the pure intellectual

faculty.



  Thus, then, appears the vanity of the hope of establishing a

cognition which is to extend its rule beyond the limits of experience-

a cognition which is one of the highest interests of humanity; and

thus is proved the futility of the attempt of speculative philosophy

in this region of thought. But, in this interest of thought, the

severity of criticism has rendered to reason a not unimportant

service, by the demonstration of the impossibility of making any

dogmatical affirmation concerning an object of experience beyond the

boundaries of experience. She has thus fortified reason against all

affirmations of the contrary. Now, this can be accomplished in only

two ways. Either our proposition must be proved apodeictically; or, if

this is unsuccessful, the sources of this inability must be sought

for, and, if these are discovered to exist in the natural and

necessary limitation of our reason, our opponents must submit to the

same law of renunciation and refrain from advancing claims to dogmatic

assertion.

  But the right, say rather the necessity to admit a future life, upon

principles of the practical conjoined with the speculative use of

reason, has lost nothing by this renunciation; for the merely

speculative proof has never had any influence upon the common reason

of men. It stands upon the point of a hair, so that even the schools

have been able to preserve it from falling only by incessantly

discussing it and spinning it like a top; and even in their eyes it

has never been able to present any safe foundation for the erection of

a theory. The proofs which have been current among men, preserve their

value undiminished; nay, rather gain in clearness and

unsophisticated power, by the rejection of the dogmatical

assumptions of speculative reason. For reason is thus confined

within her own peculiar province- the arrangement of ends or aims,

which is at the same time the arrangement of nature; and, as a

practical faculty, without limiting itself to the latter, it is

justified in extending the former, and with it our own existence,

beyond the boundaries of experience and life. If we turn our attention

to the analogy of the nature of living beings in this world, in the

consideration of which reason is obliged to accept as a principle that

no organ, no faculty, no appetite is useless, and that nothing is

superfluous, nothing disproportionate to its use, nothing unsuited

to its end; but that, on the contrary, everything is perfectly

conformed to its destination in life- we shall find that man, who

alone is the final end and aim of this order, is still the only animal

that seems to be excepted from it. For his natural gifts- not merely

as regards the talents and motives that may incite him to employ them,

but especially the moral law in him- stretch so far beyond all mere

earthly utility and advantage, that he feels himself bound to prize

the mere consciousness of probity, apart from all advantageous

consequences- even the shadowy gift of posthumous fame- above

everything; and he is conscious of an inward call to constitute

himself, by his conduct in this world- without regard to mere

sublunary interests- the citizen of a better. This mighty,

irresistible proof- accompanied by an ever-increasing knowledge of the

conformability to a purpose in everything we see around us, by the

conviction of the boundless immensity of creation, by the

consciousness of a certain illimitableness in the possible extension

of our knowledge, and by a desire commensurate therewith- remains to

humanity, even after the theoretical cognition of ourselves bas failed

to establish the necessity of an existence after death.



              Conclusion of the Solution of the

                 Psychological Paralogism.



  The dialectical illusion in rational psychology arises from our

confounding an idea of reason (of a pure intelligence) with the

conception- in every respect undetermined- of a thinking being in

general. I cogitate myself in behalf of a possible experience, at

the same time making abstraction of all actual experience; and infer

therefrom that I can be conscious of myself apart from experience

and its empirical conditions. I consequently confound the possible

abstraction of my empirically determined existence with the supposed

consciousness of a possible separate existence of my thinking self;

and I believe that I cognize what is substantial in myself as a

transcendental subject, when I have nothing more in thought than the

unity of consciousness, which lies at the basis of all determination

of cognition.

  The task of explaining the community of the soul with the body

does not properly belong to the psychology of which we are here

speaking; because it proposes to prove the personality of the soul

apart from this communion (after death), and is therefore transcendent

in the proper sense of the word, although occupying itself with an

object of experience- only in so far, however, as it ceases to be an

object of experience. But a sufficient answer may be found to the

question in our system. The difficulty which lies in the execution

of this task consists, as is well known, in the presupposed

heterogeneity of the object of the internal sense (the soul) and the

objects of the external senses; inasmuch as the formal condition of

the intuition of the one is time, and of that of the other space also.

But if we consider that both kinds of objects do not differ

internally, but only in so far as the one appears externally to the

other- consequently, that what lies at the basis of phenomena, as a

thing in itself, may not be heterogeneous; this difficulty disappears.

There then remains no other difficulty than is to be found in the

question- how a community of substances is possible; a question

which lies out of the region of psychology, and which the reader,

after what in our analytic has been said of primitive forces and

faculties, will easily judge to be also beyond the region of human

cognition.



                      GENERAL REMARK



     On the Transition from Rational Psychology to Cosmology.



  The proposition, "I think," or, "I exist thinking," is an

empirical proposition. But such a proposition must be based on

empirical intuition, and the object cogitated as a phenomenon; and

thus our theory appears to maintain that the soul, even in thought, is

merely a phenomenon; and in this way our consciousness itself, in

fact, abuts upon nothing.

  Thought, per se, is merely the purely spontaneous logical function

which operates to connect the manifold of a possible intuition; and it

does not represent the subject of consciousness as a phenomenon- for

this reason alone, that it pays no attention to the question whether

the mode of intuiting it is sensuous or intellectual. I therefore do

not represent myself in thought either as I am, or as I appear to

myself; I merely cogitate myself as an object in general, of the

mode of intuiting which I make abstraction. When I represent myself as

the subject of thought, or as the ground of thought, these modes of

representation are not related to the categories of substance or of

cause; for these are functions of thought applicable only to our

sensuous intuition. The application of these categories to the Ego

would, however, be necessary, if I wished to make myself an object

of knowledge. But I wish to be conscious of myself only as thinking;

in what mode my Self is given in intuition, I do not consider, and

it may be that I, who think, am a phenomenon- although not in so far

as I am a thinking being; but in the consciousness of myself in mere

thought I am a being, though this consciousness does not present to me

any property of this being as material for thought.

  But the proposition, "I think," in so far as it declares, "I exist

thinking," is not the mere representation of a logical function. It

determines the subject (which is in this case an object also) in

relation to existence; and it cannot be given without the aid of the

internal sense, whose intuition presents to us an object, not as a

thing in itself, but always as a phenomenon. In this proposition there

is therefore something more to be found than the mere spontaneity of

thought; there is also the receptivity of intuition, that is, my

thought of myself applied to the empirical intuition of myself. Now,

in this intuition the thinking self must seek the conditions of the

employment of its logical functions as categories of substance, cause,

and so forth; not merely for the purpose of distinguishing itself as

an object in itself by means of the representation "I," but also for

the purpose of determining the mode of its existence, that is, of

cognizing itself as noumenon. But this is impossible, for the internal

empirical intuition is sensuous, and presents us with nothing but

phenomenal data, which do not assist the object of pure

consciousness in its attempt to cognize itself as a separate

existence, but are useful only as contributions to experience.

  But, let it be granted that we could discover, not in experience,

but in certain firmly-established a priori laws of the use of pure

reason- laws relating to our existence, authority to consider

ourselves as legislating a priori in relation to our own existence and

as determining this existence; we should, on this supposition, find

ourselves possessed of a spontaneity, by which our actual existence

would be determinable, without the aid of the conditions of

empirical intuition. We should also become aware that in the

consciousness of our existence there was an a priori content, which

would serve to determine our own existence- an existence only

sensuously determinable- relatively, however, to a certain internal

faculty in relation to an intelligible world.

  But this would not give the least help to the attempts of rational

psychology. For this wonderful faculty, which the consciousness of the

moral law in me reveals, would present me with a principle of the

determination of my own existence which is purely intellectual- but by

what predicates? By none other than those which are given in

sensuous intuition. Thus I should find myself in the same position

in rational psychology which I formerly occupied, that is to say, I

should find myself still in need of sensuous intuitions, in order to

give significance to my conceptions of substance and cause, by means

of which alone I can possess a knowledge of myself: but these

intuitions can never raise me above the sphere of experience. I should

be justified, however, in applying these conceptions, in regard to

their practical use, which is always directed to objects of

experience- in conformity with their analogical significance when

employed theoretically- to freedom and its subject. At the same

time, I should understand by them merely the logical functions of

subject and predicate, of principle and consequence, in conformity

with which all actions are so determined, that they are capable of

being explained along with the laws of nature, conformably to the

categories of substance and cause, although they originate from a very

different principle. We have made these observations for the purpose

of guarding against misunderstanding, to which the doctrine of our

intuition of self as a phenomenon is exposed. We shall have occasion

to perceive their utility in the sequel.

            CHAPTER II. The Antinomy of Pure Reason.



  We showed in the introduction to this part of our work, that all

transcendental illusion of pure reason arose from dialectical

arguments, the schema of which logic gives us in its three formal

species of syllogisms- just as the categories find their logical

schema in the four functions of all judgements. The first kind of

these sophistical arguments related to the unconditioned unity of

the subjective conditions of all representations in general (of the

subject or soul), in correspondence with the categorical syllogisms,

the major of which, as the principle, enounces the relation of a

predicate to a subject. The second kind of dialectical argument will

therefore be concerned, following the analogy with hypothetical

syllogisms, with the unconditioned unity of the objective conditions

in the phenomenon; and, in this way, the theme of the third kind to be

treated of in the following chapter will be the unconditioned unity of

the objective conditions of the possibility of objects in general.

  But it is worthy of remark that the transcendental paralogism

produced in the mind only a one-third illusion, in regard to the

idea of the subject of our thought; and the conceptions of reason gave

no ground to maintain the contrary proposition. The advantage is

completely on the side of Pneumatism; although this theory itself

passes into naught, in the crucible of pure reason.

  Very different is the case when we apply reason to the objective

synthesis of phenomena. Here, certainly, reason establishes, with much

plausibility, its principle of unconditioned unity; but it very soon

falls into such contradictions that it is compelled, in relation to

cosmology, to renounce its pretensions.

  For here a new phenomenon of human reason meets us- a perfectly

natural antithetic, which does not require to be sought for by

subtle sophistry, but into which reason of itself unavoidably falls.

It is thereby preserved, to be sure, from the slumber of a fancied

conviction- which a merely one-sided illusion produces; but it is at

the same time compelled, either, on the one hand, to abandon itself to

a despairing scepticism, or, on the other, to assume a dogmatical

confidence and obstinate persistence in certain assertions, without

granting a fair hearing to the other side of the question. Either is

the death of a sound philosophy, although the former might perhaps

deserve the title of the euthanasia of pure reason.

  Before entering this region of discord and confusion, which the

conflict of the laws of pure reason (antinomy) produces, we shall

present the reader with some considerations, in explanation and

justification of the method we intend to follow in our treatment of

this subject. I term all transcendental ideas, in so far as they

relate to the absolute totality in the synthesis of phenomena,

cosmical conceptions; partly on account of this unconditioned

totality, on which the conception of the world-whole is based- a

conception, which is itself an idea- partly because they relate solely

to the synthesis of phenomena- the empirical synthesis; while, on

the other hand, the absolute totality in the synthesis of the

conditions of all possible things gives rise to an ideal of pure

reason, which is quite distinct from the cosmical conception, although

it stands in relation with it. Hence, as the paralogisms of pure

reason laid the foundation for a dialectical psychology, the

antinomy of pure reason will present us with the transcendental

principles of a pretended pure (rational) cosmology- not, however,

to declare it valid and to appropriate it, but- as the very term of

a conflict of reason sufficiently indicates, to present it as an

idea which cannot be reconciled with phenomena and experience.



           SECTION I. System of Cosmological Ideas.



  That We may be able to enumerate with systematic precision these

ideas according to a principle, we must remark, in the first place,

that it is from the understanding alone that pure and transcendental

conceptions take their origin; that the reason does not properly

give birth to any conception, but only frees the conception of the

understanding from the unavoidable limitation of a possible

experience, and thus endeavours to raise it above the empirical,

though it must still be in connection with it. This happens from the

fact that, for a given conditioned, reason demands absolute totality

on the side of the conditions (to which the understanding submits

all phenomena), and thus makes of the category a transcendental

idea. This it does that it may be able to give absolute completeness

to the empirical synthesis, by continuing it to the unconditioned

(which is not to be found in experience, but only in the idea). Reason

requires this according to the principle: If the conditioned is

given the whole of the conditions, and consequently the absolutely

unconditioned, is also given, whereby alone the former was possible.

First, then, the transcendental ideas are properly nothing but

categories elevated to the unconditioned; and they may be arranged

in a table according to the titles of the latter. But, secondly, all

the categories are not available for this purpose, but only those in

which the synthesis constitutes a series- of conditions subordinated

to, not co-ordinated with, each other. Absolute totality is required

of reason only in so far as concerns the ascending series of the

conditions of a conditioned; not, consequently, when the question

relates to the descending series of consequences, or to the

aggregate of the co-ordinated conditions of these consequences. For,

in relation to a given conditioned, conditions are presupposed and

considered to be given along with it. On the other hand, as the

consequences do not render possible their conditions, but rather

presuppose them- in the consideration of the procession of

consequences (or in the descent from the given condition to the

conditioned), we may be quite unconcerned whether the series ceases or

not; and their totality is not a necessary demand of reason.

  Thus we cogitate- and necessarily- a given time completely elapsed

up to a given moment, although that time is not determinable by us.

But as regards time future, which is not the condition of arriving

at the present, in order to conceive it; it is quite indifferent

whether we consider future time as ceasing at some point, or as

prolonging itself to infinity. Take, for example, the series m, n,

o, in which n is given as conditioned in relation to m, but at the

same time as the condition of o, and let the series proceed upwards

from the conditioned n to m (l, k, i, etc.), and also downwards from

the condition n to the conditioned o (p, q, r, etc.)- I must

presuppose the former series, to be able to consider n as given, and n

is according to reason (the totality of conditions) possible only by

means of that series. But its possibility does not rest on the

following series o, p, q, r, which for this reason cannot be

regarded as given, but only as capable of being given (dabilis).

  I shall term the synthesis of the series on the side of the

conditions- from that nearest to the given phenomenon up to the more

remote- regressive; that which proceeds on the side of the

conditioned, from the immediate consequence to the more remote, I

shall call the progressive synthesis. The former proceeds in

antecedentia, the latter in consequentia. The cosmological ideas are

therefore occupied with the totality of the regressive synthesis,

and proceed in antecedentia, not in consequentia. When the latter

takes place, it is an arbitrary and not a necessary problem of pure

reason; for we require, for the complete understanding of what is

given in a phenomenon, not the consequences which succeed, but the

grounds or principles which precede.

  In order to construct the table of ideas in correspondence with

the table of categories, we take first the two primitive quanta of all

our intuitions, time and space. Time is in itself a series (and the

formal condition of all series), and hence, in relation to a given

present, we must distinguish a priori in it the antecedentia as

conditions (time past) from the consequentia (time future).

Consequently, the transcendental idea of the absolute totality of

the series of the conditions of a given conditioned, relates merely to

all past time. According to the idea of reason, the whole past time,

as the condition of the given moment, is necessarily cogitated as

given. But, as regards space, there exists in it no distinction

between progressus and regressus; for it is an aggregate and not a

series- its parts existing together at the same time. I can consider a

given point of time in relation to past time only as conditioned,

because this given moment comes into existence only through the past

time rather through the passing of the preceding time. But as the

parts of space are not subordinated, but co-ordinated to each other,

one part cannot be the condition of the possibility of the other;

and space is not in itself, like time, a series. But the synthesis

of the manifold parts of space- (the syntheses whereby we apprehend

space)- is nevertheless successive; it takes place, therefore, in

time, and contains a series. And as in this series of aggregated

spaces (for example, the feet in a rood), beginning with a given

portion of space, those which continue to be annexed form the

condition of the limits of the former- the measurement of a space must

also be regarded as a synthesis of the series of the conditions of a

given conditioned. It differs, however, in this respect from that of

time, that the side of the conditioned is not in itself

distinguishable from the side of the condition; and, consequently,

regressus and progressus in space seem to be identical. But,

inasmuch as one part of space is not given, but only limited, by and

through another, we must also consider every limited space as

conditioned, in so far as it presupposes some other space as the

condition of its limitation, and so on. As regards limitation,

therefore, our procedure in space is also a regressus, and the

transcendental idea of the absolute totality of the synthesis in a

series of conditions applies to space also; and I am entitled to

demand the absolute totality of the phenomenal synthesis in space as

well as in time. Whether my demand can be satisfied is a question to

be answered in the sequel.

  Secondly, the real in space- that is, matter- is conditioned. Its

internal conditions are its parts, and the parts of parts its remote

conditions; so that in this case we find a regressive synthesis, the

absolute totality of which is a demand of reason. But this cannot be

obtained otherwise than by a complete division of parts, whereby the

real in matter becomes either nothing or that which is not matter,

that is to say, the simple. Consequently we find here also a series of

conditions and a progress to the unconditioned.

  Thirdly, as regards the categories of a real relation between

phenomena, the category of substance and its accidents is not suitable

for the formation of a transcendental idea; that is to say, reason has

no ground, in regard to it, to proceed regressively with conditions.

For accidents (in so far as they inhere in a substance) are

co-ordinated with each other, and do not constitute a series. And,

in relation to substance, they are not properly subordinated to it,

but are the mode of existence of the substance itself. The

conception of the substantial might nevertheless seem to be an idea of

the transcendental reason. But, as this signifies nothing more than

the conception of an object in general, which subsists in so far as we

cogitate in it merely a transcendental subject without any predicates;

and as the question here is of an unconditioned in the series of

phenomena- it is clear that the substantial can form no member

thereof. The same holds good of substances in community, which are

mere aggregates and do not form a series. For they are not

subordinated to each other as conditions of the possibility of each

other; which, however, may be affirmed of spaces, the limits of

which are never determined in themselves, but always by some other

space. It is, therefore, only in the category of causality that we can

find a series of causes to a given effect, and in which we ascend from

the latter, as the conditioned, to the former as the conditions, and

thus answer the question of reason.

  Fourthly, the conceptions of the possible, the actual, and the

necessary do not conduct us to any series- excepting only in so far as

the contingent in existence must always be regarded as conditioned,

and as indicating, according to a law of the understanding, a

condition, under which it is necessary to rise to a higher, till in

the totality of the series, reason arrives at unconditioned necessity.

  There are, accordingly, only four cosmological ideas,

corresponding with the four titles of the categories. For we can

select only such as necessarily furnish us with a series in the

synthesis of the manifold.



                      1

            The absolute Completeness

                    of the

                 COMPOSITION

     of the given totality of all phenomena.



                      2

            The absolute Completeness

                    of the

                   DIVISION

     of given totality in a phenomenon.



                       3

            The absolute Completeness

                     of the

                   ORIGINATION

                  of a phenomenon.



                       4

            The absolute Completeness

         of the DEPENDENCE of the EXISTENCE

        of what is changeable in a phenomenon.



  We must here remark, in the first place, that the idea of absolute

totality relates to nothing but the exposition of phenomena, and

therefore not to the pure conception of a totality of things.

Phenomena are here, therefore, regarded as given, and reason

requires the absolute completeness of the conditions of their

possibility, in so far as these conditions constitute a series-

consequently an absolutely (that is, in every respect) complete

synthesis, whereby a phenomenon can be explained according to the laws

of the understanding.

  Secondly, it is properly the unconditioned alone that reason seeks

in this serially and regressively conducted synthesis of conditions.

It wishes, to speak in another way, to attain to completeness in the

series of premisses, so as to render it unnecessary to presuppose

others. This unconditioned is always contained in the absolute

totality of the series, when we endeavour to form a representation

of it in thought. But this absolutely complete synthesis is itself but

an idea; for it is impossible, at least before hand, to know whether

any such synthesis is possible in the case of phenomena. When we

represent all existence in thought by means of pure conceptions of the

understanding, without any conditions of sensuous intuition, we may

say with justice that for a given conditioned the whole series of

conditions subordinated to each other is also given; for the former is

only given through the latter. But we find in the case of phenomena

a particular limitation of the mode in which conditions are given,

that is, through the successive synthesis of the manifold of

intuition, which must be complete in the regress. Now whether this

completeness is sensuously possible, is a problem. But the idea of

it lies in the reason- be it possible or impossible to connect with

the idea adequate empirical conceptions. Therefore, as in the absolute

totality of the regressive synthesis of the manifold in a phenomenon

(following the guidance of the categories, which represent it as a

series of conditions to a given conditioned) the unconditioned is

necessarily contained- it being still left unascertained whether and

how this totality exists; reason sets out from the idea of totality,

although its proper and final aim is the unconditioned- of the whole

series, or of a part thereof.

  This unconditioned may be cogitated- either as existing only in

the entire series, all the members of which therefore would be without

exception conditioned and only the totality absolutely

unconditioned- and in this case the regressus is called infinite; or

the absolutely unconditioned is only a part of the series, to which

the other members are subordinated, but which Is not itself

submitted to any other condition.* In the former case the series is

a parte priori unlimited (without beginning), that is, infinite, and

nevertheless completely given. But the regress in it is never

completed, and can only be called potentially infinite. In the

second case there exists a first in the series. This first is

called, in relation to past time, the beginning of the world; in

relation to space, the limit of the world; in relation to the parts of

a given limited whole, the simple; in relation to causes, absolute

spontaneity (liberty); and in relation to the existence of

changeable things, absolute physical necessity.



  *The absolute totality of the series of conditions to a given

conditioned is always unconditioned; because beyond it there exist

no other conditions, on which it might depend. But the absolute

totality of such a series is only an idea, or rather a problematical

conception, the possibility of which must be investigated-

particularly in relation to the mode in which the unconditioned, as

the transcendental idea which is the real subject of inquiry, may be

contained therein.



  We possess two expressions, world and nature, which are generally

interchanged. The first denotes the mathematical total of all

phenomena and the totality of their synthesis- in its progress by

means of composition, as well as by division. And the world is

termed nature,* when it is regarded as a dynamical whole- when our

attention is not directed to the aggregation in space and time, for

the purpose of cogitating it as a quantity, but to the unity in the

existence of phenomena. In this case the condition of that which

happens is called a cause; the unconditioned causality of the cause in

a phenomenon is termed liberty; the conditioned cause is called in a

more limited sense a natural cause. The conditioned in existence is

termed contingent, and the unconditioned necessary. The

unconditioned necessity of phenomena may be called natural necessity.



  *Nature, understood adjective (formaliter), signifies the complex of

the determinations of a thing, connected according to an internal

principle of causality. On the other hand, we understand by nature,

substantive (materialiter), the sum total of phenomena, in so far as

they, by virtue of an internal principle of causality, are connected

with each other throughout. In the former sense we speak of the nature

of liquid matter, of fire, etc., and employ the word only adjective;

while, if speaking of the objects of nature, we have in our minds

the idea of a subsisting whole.



  The ideas which we are at present engaged in discussing I have

called cosmological ideas; partly because by the term world is

understood the entire content of all phenomena, and our ideas are

directed solely to the unconditioned among phenomena; partly also,

because world, in the transcendental sense, signifies the absolute

totality of the content of existing things, and we are directing our

attention only to the completeness of the synthesis- although,

properly, only in regression. In regard to the fact that these ideas

are all transcendent. and, although they do not transcend phenomena as

regards their mode, but are concerned solely with the world of sense

(and not with noumena), nevertheless carry their synthesis to a degree

far above all possible experience- it still seems to me that we can,

with perfect propriety, designate them cosmical conceptions. As

regards the distinction between the mathematically and the dynamically

unconditioned which is the aim of the regression of the synthesis, I

should call the two former, in a more limited signification,

cosmical conceptions, the remaining two transcendent physical

conceptions. This distinction does not at present seem to be of

particular importance, but we shall afterwards find it to be of some

value.





           SECTION II. Antithetic of Pure Reason.



  Thetic is the term applied to every collection of dogmatical

propositions. By antithetic I do not understand dogmatical

assertions of the opposite, but the self-contradiction of seemingly

dogmatical cognitions (thesis cum antithesis, in none of which we

can discover any decided superiority. Antithetic is not, therefore,

occupied with one-sided statements, but is engaged in considering

the contradictory nature of the general cognitions of reason and its

causes. Transcendental antithetic is an investigation into the

antinomy of pure reason, its causes and result. If we employ our

reason not merely in the application of the principles of the

understanding to objects of experience, but venture with it beyond

these boundaries, there arise certain sophistical propositions or

theorems. These assertions have the following peculiarities: They

can find neither confirmation nor confutation in experience; and

each is in itself not only self-consistent, but possesses conditions

of its necessity in the very nature of reason- only that, unluckily,

there exist just as valid and necessary grounds for maintaining the

contrary proposition.

  The questions which naturally arise in the consideration of this

dialectic of pure reason, are therefore: 1st. In what propositions

is pure reason unavoidably subject to an antinomy? 2nd. What are the

causes of this antinomy? 3rd. Whether and in what way can reason

free itself from this self-contradiction?

  A dialectical proposition or theorem of pure reason must,

according to what has been said, be distinguishable from all

sophistical propositions, by the fact that it is not an answer to an

arbitrary question, which may be raised at the mere pleasure of any

person, but to one which human reason must necessarily encounter in

its progress. In the second place, a dialectical proposition, with its

opposite, does not carry the appearance of a merely artificial

illusion, which disappears as soon as it is investigated, but a

natural and unavoidable illusion, which, even when we are no longer

deceived by it, continues to mock us and, although rendered

harmless, can never be completely removed.

  This dialectical doctrine will not relate to the unity of

understanding in empirical conceptions, but to the unity of reason

in pure ideas. The conditions of this doctrine are- inasmuch as it

must, as a synthesis according to rules, be conformable to the

understanding, and at the same time as the absolute unity of the

synthesis, to the reason- that, if it is adequate to the unity of

reason, it is too great for the understanding, if according with the

understanding, it is too small for the reason. Hence arises a mutual

opposition, which cannot be avoided, do what we will.

  These sophistical assertions of dialectic open, as it were, a

battle-field, where that side obtains the victory which has been

permitted to make the attack, and he is compelled to yield who has

been unfortunately obliged to stand on the defensive. And hence,

champions of ability, whether on the right or on the wrong side, are

certain to carry away the crown of victory, if they only take care

to have the right to make the last attack, and are not obliged to

sustain another onset from their opponent. We can easily believe

that this arena has been often trampled by the feet of combatants,

that many victories have been obtained on both sides, but that the

last victory, decisive of the affair between the contending parties,

was won by him who fought for the right, only if his adversary was

forbidden to continue the tourney. As impartial umpires, we must lay

aside entirely the consideration whether the combatants are fighting

for the right or for the wrong side, for the true or for the false,

and allow the combat to be first decided. Perhaps, after they have

wearied more than injured each other, they will discover the

nothingness of their cause of quarrel and part good friends.

  This method of watching, or rather of originating, a conflict of

assertions, not for the purpose of finally deciding in favour of

either side, but to discover whether the object of the struggle is not

a mere illusion, which each strives in vain to reach, but which

would be no gain even when reached- this procedure, I say, may be

termed the sceptical method. It is thoroughly distinct from

scepticism- the principle of a technical and scientific ignorance,

which undermines the foundations of all knowledge, in order, if

possible, to destroy our belief and confidence therein. For the

sceptical method aims at certainty, by endeavouring to discover in a

conflict of this kind, conducted honestly and intelligently on both

sides, the point of misunderstanding; just as wise legislators derive,

from the embarrassment of judges in lawsuits, information in regard to

the defective and ill-defined parts of their statutes. The antinomy

which reveals itself in the application of laws, is for our limited

wisdom the best criterion of legislation. For the attention of reason,

which in abstract speculation does not easily become conscious of

its errors, is thus roused to the momenta in the determination of

its principles.

  But this sceptical method is essentially peculiar to

transcendental philosophy, and can perhaps be dispensed with in

every other field of investigation. In mathematics its use would be

absurd; because in it no false assertions can long remain hidden,

inasmuch as its demonstrations must always proceed under the

guidance of pure intuition, and by means of an always evident

synthesis. In experimental philosophy, doubt and delay may be very

useful; but no misunderstanding is possible, which cannot be easily

removed; and in experience means of solving the difficulty and putting

an end to the dissension must at last be found, whether sooner or

later. Moral philosophy can always exhibit its principles, with

their practical consequences, in concreto- at least in possible

experiences, and thus escape the mistakes and ambiguities of

abstraction. But transcendental propositions, which lay claim to

insight beyond the region of possible experience, cannot, on the one

hand, exhibit their abstract synthesis in any a priori intuition, nor,

on the other, expose a lurking error by the help of experience.

Transcendental reason, therefore, presents us with no other

criterion than that of an attempt to reconcile such assertions, and

for this purpose to permit a free and unrestrained conflict between

them. And this we now proceed to arrange.*



  *The antinomies stand in the order of the four transcendental

ideas above detailed.





          FIRST CONFLICT OF THE TRANSCENDENTAL IDEAS.



                          THESIS.



     The world has a beginning in time, and is also limited in

regard to space.



                          PROOF.



  Granted that the world has no beginning in time; up to every given

moment of time, an eternity must have elapsed, and therewith passed

away an infinite series of successive conditions or states of things

in the world. Now the infinity of a series consists in the fact that

it never can be completed by means of a successive synthesis. It

follows that an infinite series already elapsed is impossible and

that, consequently, a beginning of the world is a necessary

condition of its existence. And this was the first thing to be proved.

  As regards the second, let us take the opposite for granted. In this

case, the world must be an infinite given total of coexistent

things. Now we cannot cogitate the dimensions of a quantity, which

is not given within certain limits of an intuition,* in any other

way than by means of the synthesis of its parts, and the total of such

a quantity only by means of a completed synthesis, or the repeated

addition of unity to itself. Accordingly, to cogitate the world, which

fills all spaces, as a whole, the successive synthesis of the parts of

an infinite world must be looked upon as completed, that is to say, an

infinite time must be regarded as having elapsed in the enumeration of

all co-existing things; which is impossible. For this reason an

infinite aggregate of actual things cannot be considered as a given

whole, consequently, not as a contemporaneously given whole. The world

is consequently, as regards extension in space, not infinite, but

enclosed in limits. And this was the second thing to be proved.



  *We may consider an undetermined quantity as a whole, when it is

enclosed within limits, although we cannot construct or ascertain

its totality by measurement, that is, by the successive synthesis of

its parts. For its limits of themselves determine its completeness

as a whole.



                        ANTITHESIS.



  The world has no beginning, and no limits in space, but is, in

relation both to time and space, infinite.



                          PROOF.



  For let it be granted that it has a beginning. A beginning is an

existence which is preceded by a time in which the thing does not

exist. On the above supposition, it follows that there must have

been a time in which the world did not exist, that is, a void time.

But in a void time the origination of a thing is impossible; because

no part of any such time contains a distinctive condition of being, in

preference to that of non-being (whether the supposed thing

originate of itself, or by means of some other cause). Consequently,

many series of things may have a beginning in the world, but the world

itself cannot have a beginning, and is, therefore, in relation to past

time, infinite.

  As regards the second statement, let us first take the opposite

for granted- that the world is finite and limited in space; it follows

that it must exist in a void space, which is not limited. We should

therefore meet not only with a relation of things in space, but also a

relation of things to space. Now, as the world is an absolute whole,

out of and beyond which no object of intuition, and consequently no

correlate to which can be discovered, this relation of the world to

a void space is merely a relation to no object. But such a relation,

and consequently the limitation of the world by void space, is

nothing. Consequently, the world, as regards space, is not limited,

that is, it is infinite in regard to extension.*



  *Space is merely the form of external intuition (formal

intuition), and not a real object which can be externally perceived.

Space, prior to all things which determine it (fill or limit it),

or, rather, which present an empirical intuition conformable to it,

is, under the title of absolute space, nothing but the mere

possibility of external phenomena, in so far as they either exist in

themselves, or can annex themselves to given intuitions. Empirical

intuition is therefore not a composition of phenomena and space (of

perception and empty intuition). The one is not the correlate of the

other in a synthesis, but they are vitally connected in the same

empirical intuition, as matter and form. If we wish to set one of

these two apart from the other- space from phenomena- there arise

all sorts of empty determinations of external intuition, which are

very far from being possible perceptions. For example, motion or

rest of the world in an infinite empty space, or a determination of

the mutual relation of both, cannot possibly be perceived, and is

therefore merely the predicate of a notional entity.





            OBSERVATIONS ON THE FIRST ANTINOMY.



                     ON THE THESIS.



  In bringing forward these conflicting arguments, I have not been

on the search for sophisms, for the purpose of availing myself of

special pleading, which takes advantage of the carelessness of the

opposite party, appeals to a misunderstood statute, and erects its

unrighteous claims upon an unfair interpretation. Both proofs

originate fairly from the nature of the case, and the advantage

presented by the mistakes of the dogmatists of both parties has been

completely set aside.

  The thesis might also have been unfairly demonstrated, by the

introduction of an erroneous conception of the infinity of a given

quantity. A quantity is infinite, if a greater than itself cannot

possibly exist. The quantity is measured by the number of given units-

which are taken as a standard- contained in it. Now no number can be

the greatest, because one or more units can always be added. It

follows that an infinite given quantity, consequently an infinite

world (both as regards time and extension) is impossible. It is,

therefore, limited in both respects. In this manner I might have

conducted my proof; but the conception given in it does not agree with

the true conception of an infinite whole. In this there is no

representation of its quantity, it is not said how large it is;

consequently its conception is not the conception of a maximum. We

cogitate in it merely its relation to an arbitrarily assumed unit,

in relation to which it is greater than any number. Now, just as the

unit which is taken is greater or smaller, the infinite will be

greater or smaller; but the infinity, which consists merely in the

relation to this given unit, must remain always the same, although the

absolute quantity of the whole is not thereby cognized.

  The true (transcendental) conception of infinity is: that the

successive synthesis of unity in the measurement of a given quantum

can never be completed.* Hence it follows, without possibility of

mistake, that an eternity of actual successive states up to a given

(the present) moment cannot have elapsed, and that the world must

therefore have a beginning.



  *The quantum in this sense contains a congeries of given units,

which is greater than any number- and this is the mathematical

conception of the infinite.



  In regard to the second part of the thesis, the difficulty as to

an infinite and yet elapsed series disappears; for the manifold of a

world infinite in extension is contemporaneously given. But, in

order to cogitate the total of this manifold, as we cannot have the

aid of limits constituting by themselves this total in intuition, we

are obliged to give some account of our conception, which in this case

cannot proceed from the whole to the determined quantity of the parts,

but must demonstrate the possibility of a whole by means of a

successive synthesis of the parts. But as this synthesis must

constitute a series that cannot be completed, it is impossible for

us to cogitate prior to it, and consequently not by means of it, a

totality. For the conception of totality itself is in the present case

the representation of a completed synthesis of the parts; and this

completion, and consequently its conception, is impossible.



                   ON THE ANTITHESIS.



  The proof in favour of the infinity of the cosmical succession and

the cosmical content is based upon the consideration that, in the

opposite case, a void time and a void space must constitute the limits

of the world. Now I am not unaware, that there are some ways of

escaping this conclusion. It may, for example, be alleged, that a

limit to the world, as regards both space and time, is quite possible,

without at the same time holding the existence of an absolute time

before the beginning of the world, or an absolute space extending

beyond the actual world- which is impossible. I am quite well

satisfied with the latter part of this opinion of the philosophers

of the Leibnitzian school. Space is merely the form of external

intuition, but not a real object which can itself be externally

intuited; it is not a correlate of phenomena, it is the form of

phenomena itself. Space, therefore, cannot be regarded as absolutely

and in itself something determinative of the existence of things,

because it is not itself an object, but only the form of possible

objects. Consequently, things, as phenomena, determine space; that

is to say, they render it possible that, of all the possible

predicates of space (size and relation), certain may belong to

reality. But we cannot affirm the converse, that space, as something

self-subsistent, can determine real things in regard to size or shape,

for it is in itself not a real thing. Space (filled or void)* may

therefore be limited by phenomena, but phenomena cannot be limited

by an empty space without them. This is true of time also. All this

being granted, it is nevertheless indisputable, that we must assume

these two nonentities, void space without and void time before the

world, if we assume the existence of cosmical limits, relatively to

space or time.



  *It is evident that what is meant here is, that empty space, in so

far as it is limited by phenomena- space, that is, within the world-

does not at least contradict transcendental principles, and may

therefore, as regards them, be admitted, although its possibility

cannot on that account be affirmed.



  For, as regards the subterfuge adopted by those who endeavour to

evade the consequence- that, if the world is limited as to space and

time, the infinite void must determine the existence of actual

things in regard to their dimensions- it arises solely from the fact

that instead of a sensuous world, an intelligible world- of which

nothing is known- is cogitated; instead of a real beginning (an

existence, which is preceded by a period in which nothing exists),

an existence which presupposes no other condition than that of time;

and, instead of limits of extension, boundaries of the universe. But

the question relates to the mundus phaenomenon, and its quantity;

and in this case we cannot make abstraction of the conditions of

sensibility, without doing away with the essential reality of this

world itself. The world of sense, if it is limited, must necessarily

lie in the infinite void. If this, and with it space as the a priori

condition of the possibility of phenomena, is left out of view, the

whole world of sense disappears. In our problem is this alone

considered as given. The mundus intelligibilis is nothing but the

general conception of a world, in which abstraction has been made of

all conditions of intuition, and in relation to which no synthetical

proposition- either affirmative or negative- is possible.





         SECOND CONFLICT OF TRANSCENDENTAL IDEAS.



                        THESIS.



  Every composite substance in the world consists of simple parts; and

there exists nothing that is not either itself simple, or composed

of simple parts.



                         PROOF.



  For, grant that composite substances do not consist of simple parts;

in this case, if all combination or composition were annihilated in

thought, no composite part, and (as, by the supposition, there do

not exist simple parts) no simple part would exist. Consequently, no

substance; consequently, nothing would exist. Either, then, it is

impossible to annihilate composition in thought; or, after such

annihilation, there must remain something that subsists without

composition, that is, something that is simple. But in the former case

the composite could not itself consist of substances, because with

substances composition is merely a contingent relation, apart from

which they must still exist as self-subsistent beings. Now, as this

case contradicts the supposition, the second must contain the truth-

that the substantial composite in the world consists of simple parts.

  It follows, as an immediate inference, that the things in the

world are all, without exception, simple beings- that composition is

merely an external condition pertaining to them- and that, although we

never can separate and isolate the elementary substances from the

state of composition, reason must cogitate these as the primary

subjects of all composition, and consequently, as prior thereto- and

as simple substances.



                      ANTITHESIS.



  No composite thing in the world consists of simple parts; and

there does not exist in the world any simple substance.



                             PROOF.



  Let it be supposed that a composite thing (as substance) consists of

simple parts. Inasmuch as all external relation, consequently all

composition of substances, is possible only in space; the space,

occupied by that which is composite, must consist of the same number

of parts as is contained in the composite. But space does not

consist of simple parts, but of spaces. Therefore, every part of the

composite must occupy a space. But the absolutely primary parts of

what is composite are simple. It follows that what is simple

occupies a space. Now, as everything real that occupies a space,

contains a manifold the parts of which are external to each other, and

is consequently composite- and a real composite, not of accidents (for

these cannot exist external to each other apart from substance), but

of substances- it follows that the simple must be a substantial

composite, which is self-contradictory.

  The second proposition of the antithesis- that there exists in the

world nothing that is simple- is here equivalent to the following: The

existence of the absolutely simple cannot be demonstrated from any

experience or perception either external or internal; and the

absolutely simple is a mere idea, the objective reality of which

cannot be demonstrated in any possible experience; it is consequently,

in the exposition of phenomena, without application and object. For,

let us take for granted that an object may be found in experience

for this transcendental idea; the empirical intuition of such an

object must then be recognized to contain absolutely no manifold

with its parts external to each other, and connected into unity.

Now, as we cannot reason from the non-consciousness of such a manifold

to the impossibility of its existence in the intuition of an object,

and as the proof of this impossibility is necessary for the

establishment and proof of absolute simplicity; it follows that this

simplicity cannot be inferred from any perception whatever. As,

therefore, an absolutely simple object cannot be given in any

experience, and the world of sense must be considered as the sum total

of all possible experiences: nothing simple exists in the world.

  This second proposition in the antithesis has a more extended aim

than the first. The first merely banishes the simple from the

intuition of the composite; while the second drives it entirely out of

nature. Hence we were unable to demonstrate it from the conception

of a given object of external intuition (of the composite), but we

were obliged to prove it from the relation of a given object to a

possible experience in general.





            OBSERVATIONS ON THE SECOND ANTINOMY.



                          THESIS.



  When I speak of a whole, which necessarily consists of simple parts,

I understand thereby only a substantial whole, as the true

composite; that is to say, I understand that contingent unity of the

manifold which is given as perfectly isolated (at least in thought),

placed in reciprocal connection, and thus constituted a unity. Space

ought not to be called a compositum but a totum, for its parts are

possible in the whole, and not the whole by means of the parts. It

might perhaps be called a compositum ideale, but not a compositum

reale. But this is of no importance. As space is not a composite of

substances (and not even of real accidents), if I abstract all

composition therein- nothing, not even a point, remains; for a point

is possible only as the limit of a space- consequently of a composite.

Space and time, therefore, do not consist of simple parts. That

which belongs only to the condition or state of a substance, even

although it possesses a quantity (motion or change, for example),

likewise does not consist of simple parts. That is to say, a certain

degree of change does not originate from the addition of many simple

changes. Our inference of the simple from the composite is valid

only of self-subsisting things. But the accidents of a state are not

self-subsistent. The proof, then, for the necessity of the simple,

as the component part of all that is substantial and composite, may

prove a failure, and the whole case of this thesis be lost, if we

carry the proposition too far, and wish to make it valid of everything

that is composite without distinction- as indeed has really now and

then happened. Besides, I am here speaking only of the simple, in so

far as it is necessarily given in the composite- the latter being

capable of solution into the former as its component parts. The proper

signification of the word monas (as employed by Leibnitz) ought to

relate to the simple, given immediately as simple substance (for

example, in consciousness), and not as an element of the composite. As

an clement, the term atomus would be more appropriate. And as I wish

to prove the existence of simple substances, only in relation to,

and as the elements of, the composite, I might term the antithesis

of the second Antinomy, transcendental Atomistic. But as this word has

long been employed to designate a particular theory of corporeal

phenomena (moleculae), and thus presupposes a basis of empirical

conceptions, I prefer calling it the dialectical principle of

Monadology.



                        ANTITHESIS.



  Against the assertion of the infinite subdivisibility of matter

whose ground of proof is purely mathematical, objections have been

alleged by the Monadists. These objections lay themselves open, at

first sight, to suspicion, from the fact that they do not recognize

the clearest mathematical proofs as propositions relating to the

constitution of space, in so far as it is really the formal

condition of the possibility of all matter, but regard them merely

as inferences from abstract but arbitrary conceptions, which cannot

have any application to real things. just as if it were possible to

imagine another mode of intuition than that given in the primitive

intuition of space; and just as if its a priori determinations did not

apply to everything, the existence of which is possible, from the fact

alone of its filling space. If we listen to them, we shall find

ourselves required to cogitate, in addition to the mathematical point,

which is simple- not, however, a part, but a mere limit of space-

physical points, which are indeed likewise simple, but possess the

peculiar property, as parts of space, of filling it merely by their

aggregation. I shall not repeat here the common and clear

refutations of this absurdity, which are to be found everywhere in

numbers: every one knows that it is impossible to undermine the

evidence of mathematics by mere discursive conceptions; I shall only

remark that, if in this case philosophy endeavours to gain an

advantage over mathematics by sophistical artifices, it is because

it forgets that the discussion relates solely to Phenomena and their

conditions. It is not sufficient to find the conception of the

simple for the pure conception of the composite, but we must

discover for the intuition of the composite (matter), the intuition of

the simple. Now this, according to the laws of sensibility, and

consequently in the case of objects of sense, is utterly impossible.

In the case of a whole composed of substances, which is cogitated

solely by the pure understanding, it may be necessary to be in

possession of the simple before composition is possible. But this does

not hold good of the Totum substantiale phaenomenon, which, as an

empirical intuition in space, possesses the necessary property of

containing no simple part, for the very reason that no part of space

is simple. Meanwhile, the Monadists have been subtle enough to

escape from this difficulty, by presupposing intuition and the

dynamical relation of substances as the condition of the possibility

of space, instead of regarding space as the condition of the

possibility of the objects of external intuition, that is, of

bodies. Now we have a conception of bodies only as phenomena, and,

as such, they necessarily presuppose space as the condition of all

external phenomena. The evasion is therefore in vain; as, indeed, we

have sufficiently shown in our Aesthetic. If bodies were things in

themselves, the proof of the Monadists would be unexceptionable.

  The second dialectical assertion possesses the peculiarity of having

opposed to it a dogmatical proposition, which, among all such

sophistical statements, is the only one that undertakes to prove in

the case of an object of experience, that which is properly a

transcendental idea- the absolute simplicity of substance. The

proposition is that the object of the internal sense, the thinking

Ego, is an absolute simple substance. Without at present entering upon

this subject- as it has been considered at length in a former chapter-

I shall merely remark that, if something is cogitated merely as an

object, without the addition of any synthetical determination of its

intuition- as happens in the case of the bare representation, I- it is

certain that no manifold and no composition can be perceived in such a

representation. As, moreover, the predicates whereby I cogitate this

object are merely intuitions of the internal sense, there cannot be

discovered in them anything to prove the existence of a manifold whose

parts are external to each other, and, consequently, nothing to

prove the existence of real composition. Consciousness, therefore,

is so constituted that, inasmuch as the thinking subject is at the

same time its own object, it cannot divide itself- although it can

divide its inhering determinations. For every object in relation to

itself is absolute unity. Nevertheless, if the subject is regarded

externally, as an object of intuition, it must, in its character of

phenomenon, possess the property of composition. And it must always be

regarded in this manner, if we wish to know whether there is or is not

contained in it a manifold whose parts are external to each other.





          THIRD CONFLICT OF THE TRANSCENDENTAL IDEAS.



                            THESIS.



  Causality according to the laws of nature, is not the only causality

operating to originate the phenomena of the world. A causality of

freedom is also necessary to account fully for these phenomena.



                             PROOF.



  Let it be supposed, that there is no other kind of causality than

that according to the laws of nature. Consequently, everything that

happens presupposes a previous condition, which it follows with

absolute certainty, in conformity with a rule. But this previous

condition must itself be something that has happened (that has

arisen in time, as it did not exist before), for, if it has always

been in existence, its consequence or effect would not thus

originate for the first time, but would likewise have always

existed. The causality, therefore, of a cause, whereby something

happens, is itself a thing that has happened. Now this again

presupposes, in conformity with the law of nature, a previous

condition and its causality, and this another anterior to the

former, and so on. If, then, everything happens solely in accordance

with the laws of nature, there cannot be any real first beginning of

things, but only a subaltern or comparative beginning. There cannot,

therefore, be a completeness of series on the side of the causes which

originate the one from the other. But the law of nature is that

nothing can happen without a sufficient a priori determined cause. The

proposition therefore- if all causality is possible only in accordance

with the laws of nature- is, when stated in this unlimited and general

manner, self-contradictory. It follows that this cannot be the only

kind of causality.

  From what has been said, it follows that a causality must be

admitted, by means of which something happens, without its cause being

determined according to necessary laws by some other cause

preceding. That is to say, there must exist an absolute spontaneity of

cause, which of itself originates a series of phenomena which proceeds

according to natural laws- consequently transcendental freedom,

without which even in the course of nature the succession of phenomena

on the side of causes is never complete.



                        ANTITHESIS.



  There is no such thing as freedom, but everything in the world

happens solely according to the laws of nature.



                          PROOF.



  Granted, that there does exist freedom in the transcendental

sense, as a peculiar kind of causality, operating to produce events in

the world- a faculty, that is to say, of originating a state, and

consequently a series of consequences from that state. In this case,

not only the series originated by this spontaneity, but the

determination of this spontaneity itself to the production of the

series, that is to say, the causality itself must have an absolute

commencement, such that nothing can precede to determine this action

according to unvarying laws. But every beginning of action presupposes

in the acting cause a state of inaction; and a dynamically primal

beginning of action presupposes a state, which has no connection- as

regards causality- with the preceding state of the cause- which does

not, that is, in any wise result from it. Transcendental freedom is

therefore opposed to the natural law of cause and effect, and such a

conjunction of successive states in effective causes is destructive of

the possibility of unity in experience and for that reason not to be

found in experience- is consequently a mere fiction of thought.

  We have, therefore, nothing but nature to which we must look for

connection and order in cosmical events. Freedom- independence of

the laws of nature- is certainly a deliverance from restraint, but

it is also a relinquishing of the guidance of law and rule. For it

cannot be alleged that, instead of the laws of nature, laws of freedom

may be introduced into the causality of the course of nature. For,

if freedom were determined according to laws, it would be no longer

freedom, but merely nature. Nature, therefore, and transcendental

freedom are distinguishable as conformity to law and lawlessness.

The former imposes upon understanding the difficulty of seeking the

origin of events ever higher and higher in the series of causes,

inasmuch as causality is always conditioned thereby; while it

compensates this labour by the guarantee of a unity complete and in

conformity with law. The latter, on the contrary, holds out to the

understanding the promise of a point of rest in the chain of causes,

by conducting it to an unconditioned causality, which professes to

have the power of spontaneous origination, but which, in its own utter

blindness, deprives it of the guidance of rules, by which alone a

completely connected experience is possible.





             OBSERVATIONS ON THE THIRD ANTINOMY.



                       ON THE THESIS.



  The transcendental idea of freedom is far from constituting the

entire content of the psychological conception so termed, which is for

the most part empirical. It merely presents us with the conception

of spontaneity of action, as the proper ground for imputing freedom to

the cause of a certain class of objects. It is, however, the true

stumbling-stone to philosophy, which meets with unconquerable

difficulties in the way of its admitting this kind of unconditioned

causality. That element in the question of the freedom of the will,

which bas for so long a time placed speculative reason in such

perplexity, is properly only transcendental, and concerns the

question, whether there must be held to exist a faculty of spontaneous

origination of a series of successive things or states. How such a

faculty is possible is not a necessary inquiry; for in the case of

natural causality itself, we are obliged to content ourselves with the

a priori knowledge that such a causality must be presupposed, although

we are quite incapable of comprehending how the being of one thing

is possible through the being of another, but must for this

information look entirely to experience. Now we have demonstrated this

necessity of a free first beginning of a series of phenomena, only

in so far as it is required for the comprehension of an origin of

the world, all following states being regarded as a succession

according to laws of nature alone. But, as there has thus been

proved the existence of a faculty which can of itself originate a

series in time- although we are unable to explain how it can exist- we

feel ourselves authorized to admit, even in the midst of the natural

course of events, a beginning, as regards causality, of different

successions of phenomena, and at the same time to attribute to all

substances a faculty of free action. But we ought in this case not

to allow ourselves to fall into a common misunderstanding, and to

suppose that, because a successive series in the world can only have a

comparatively first beginning- another state or condition of things

always preceding- an absolutely first beginning of a series in the

course of nature is impossible. For we are not speaking here of an

absolutely first beginning in relation to time, but as regards

causality alone. When, for example, I, completely of my own free will,

and independently of the necessarily determinative influence of

natural causes, rise from my chair, there commences with this event,

including its material consequences in infinitum, an absolutely new

series; although, in relation to time, this event is merely the

continuation of a preceding series. For this resolution and act of

mine do not form part of the succession of effects in nature, and

are not mere continuations of it; on the contrary, the determining

causes of nature cease to operate in reference to this event, which

certainly succeeds the acts of nature, but does not proceed from them.

For these reasons, the action of a free agent must be termed, in

regard to causality, if not in relation to time, an absolutely

primal beginning of a series of phenomena.

  The justification of this need of reason to rest upon a free act

as the first beginning of the series of natural causes is evident from

the fact, that all philosophers of antiquity (with the exception of

the Epicurean school) felt themselves obliged, when constructing a

theory of the motions of the universe, to accept a prime mover, that

is, a freely acting cause, which spontaneously and prior to all

other causes evolved this series of states. They always felt the

need of going beyond mere nature, for the purpose of making a first

beginning comprehensible.



                    ON THE ANTITHESIS.



  The assertor of the all-sufficiency of nature in regard to causality

(transcendental Physiocracy), in opposition to the doctrine of

freedom, would defend his view of the question somewhat in the

following manner. He would say, in answer to the sophistical arguments

of the opposite party: If you do not accept a mathematical first, in

relation to time, you have no need to seek a dynamical first, in

regard to causality. Who compelled you to imagine an absolutely primal

condition of the world, and therewith an absolute beginning of the

gradually progressing successions of phenomena- and, as some

foundation for this fancy of yours, to set bounds to unlimited nature?

Inasmuch as the substances in the world have always existed- at

least the unity of experience renders such a supposition quite

necessary- there is no difficulty in believing also, that the

changes in the conditions of these substances have always existed;

and, consequently, that a first beginning, mathematical or

dynamical, is by no means required. The possibility of such an

infinite derivation, without any initial member from which all the

others result, is certainly quite incomprehensible. But, if you are

rash enough to deny the enigmatical secrets of nature for this reason,

you will find yourselves obliged to deny also the existence of many

fundamental properties of natural objects (such as fundamental

forces), which you can just as little comprehend; and even the

possibility of so simple a conception as that of change must present

to you insuperable difficulties. For if experience did not teach you

that it was real, you never could conceive a priori the possibility of

this ceaseless sequence of being and non-being.

  But if the existence of a transcendental faculty of freedom is

granted- a faculty of originating changes in the world- this faculty

must at least exist out of and apart from the world; although it is

certainly a bold assumption, that, over and above the complete content

of all possible intuitions, there still exists an object which

cannot be presented in any possible perception. But, to attribute to

substances in the world itself such a faculty, is quite

inadmissible; for, in this case; the connection of phenomena

reciprocally determining and determined according to general laws,

which is termed nature, and along with it the criteria of empirical

truth, which enable us to distinguish experience from mere visionary

dreaming, would almost entirely disappear. In proximity with such a

lawless faculty of freedom, a system of nature is hardly cogitable;

for the laws of the latter would be continually subject to the

intrusive influences of the former, and the course of phenomena, which

would otherwise proceed regularly and uniformly, would become

thereby confused and disconnected.





        FOURTH CONFLICT OF THE TRANSCENDENTAL IDEAS.



                         THESIS.



  There exists either in, or in connection with the world- either as a

part of it, or as the cause of it-an absolutely necessary being.



                          PROOF.



  The world of sense, as the sum total of all phenomena, contains a

series of changes. For, without such a series, the mental

representation of the series of time itself, as the condition of the

possibility of the sensuous world, could not be presented to us.*

But every change stands under its condition, which precedes it in time

and renders it necessary. Now the existence of a given condition

presupposes a complete series of conditions up to the absolutely

unconditioned, which alone is absolutely necessary. It follows that

something that is absolutely necessary must exist, if change exists as

its consequence. But this necessary thing itself belongs to the

sensuous world. For suppose it to exist out of and apart from it,

the series of cosmical changes would receive from it a beginning,

and yet this necessary cause would not itself belong to the world of

sense. But this is impossible. For, as the beginning of a series in

time is determined only by that which precedes it in time, the supreme

condition of the beginning of a series of changes must exist in the

time in which this series itself did not exist; for a beginning

supposes a time preceding, in which the thing that begins to be was

not in existence. The causality of the necessary cause of changes, and

consequently the cause itself, must for these reasons belong to

time- and to phenomena, time being possible only as the form of

phenomena. Consequently, it cannot be cogitated as separated from

the world of sense- the sum total of all phenomena. There is,

therefore, contained in the world, something that is absolutely

necessary- whether it be the whole cosmical series itself, or only a

part of it.



  *Objectively, time, as the formal condition of the possibility of

change, precedes all changes; but subjectively, and in

consciousness, the representation of time, like every other, is

given solely by occasion of perception.



                         ANTITHESIS.



  An absolutely necessary being does not exist, either in the world,

or out of it- as its cause.



                           PROOF.



  Grant that either the world itself is necessary, or that there is

contained in it a necessary existence. Two cases are possible.

First, there must either be in the series of cosmical changes a

beginning, which is unconditionally necessary, and therefore uncaused-

which is at variance with the dynamical law of the determination of

all phenomena in time; or, secondly, the series itself is without

beginning, and, although contingent and conditioned in all its

parts, is nevertheless absolutely necessary and unconditioned as a

whole- which is self-contradictory. For the existence of an

aggregate cannot be necessary, if no single part of it possesses

necessary existence.

  Grant, on the other band, that an absolutely necessary cause

exists out of and apart from the world. This cause, as the highest

member in the series of the causes of cosmical changes, must originate

or begin* the existence of the latter and their series. In this case

it must also begin to act, and its causality would therefore belong to

time, and consequently to the sum total of phenomena, that is, to

the world. It follows that the cause cannot be out of the world; which

is contradictory to the hypothesis. Therefore, neither in the world,

nor out of it (but in causal connection with it), does there exist any

absolutely necessary being.



  *The word begin is taken in two senses. The first is active- the

cause being regarded as beginning a series of conditions as its effect

(infit). The second is passive- the causality in the cause itself

beginning to operate (fit). I reason here from the first to the

second.





             OBSERVATIONS ON THE FOURTH ANTINOMY.



                      ON THE THESIS.



  To demonstrate the existence of a necessary being, I cannot be

permitted in this place to employ any other than the cosmological

argument, which ascends from the conditioned in phenomena to the

unconditioned in conception- the unconditioned being considered the

necessary condition of the absolute totality of the series. The proof,

from the mere idea of a supreme being, belongs to another principle of

reason and requires separate discussion.

  The pure cosmological proof demonstrates the existence of a

necessary being, but at the same time leaves it quite unsettled,

whether this being is the world itself, or quite distinct from it.

To establish the truth of the latter view, principles are requisite,

which are not cosmological and do not proceed in the series of

phenomena. We should require to introduce into our proof conceptions

of contingent beings- regarded merely as objects of the understanding,

and also a principle which enables us to connect these, by means of

mere conceptions, with a necessary being. But the proper place for all

such arguments is a transcendent philosophy, which has unhappily not

yet been established.

  But, if we begin our proof cosmologically, by laying at the

foundation of it the series of phenomena, and the regress in it

according to empirical laws of causality, we are not at liberty to

break off from this mode of demonstration and to pass over to

something which is not itself a member of the series. The condition

must be taken in exactly the same signification as the relation of the

conditioned to its condition in the series has been taken, for the

series must conduct us in an unbroken regress to this supreme

condition. But if this relation is sensuous, and belongs to the

possible empirical employment of understanding, the supreme

condition or cause must close the regressive series according to the

laws of sensibility and consequently, must belong to the series of

time. It follows that this necessary existence must be regarded as the

highest member of the cosmical series.

  Certain philosophers have, nevertheless, allowed themselves the

liberty of making such a saltus (metabasis eis allo gonos). From the

changes in the world they have concluded their empirical

contingency, that is, their dependence on empirically-determined

causes, and they thus admitted an ascending series of empirical

conditions: and in this they are quite right. But as they could not

find in this series any primal beginning or any highest member, they

passed suddenly from the empirical conception of contingency to the

pure category, which presents us with a series- not sensuous, but

intellectual- whose completeness does certainly rest upon the

existence of an absolutely necessary cause. Nay, more, this

intellectual series is not tied to any sensuous conditions; and is

therefore free from the condition of time, which requires it

spontaneously to begin its causality in time. But such a procedure

is perfectly inadmissible, as will be made plain from what follows.

  In the pure sense of the categories, that is contingent the

contradictory opposite of which is possible. Now we cannot reason from

empirical contingency to intellectual. The opposite of that which is

changed- the opposite of its state- is actual at another time, and

is therefore possible. Consequently, it is not the contradictory

opposite of the former state. To be that, it is necessary that, in the

same time in which the preceding state existed, its opposite could

have existed in its place; but such a cognition is not given us in the

mere phenomenon of change. A body that was in motion = A, comes into a

state of rest = non-A. Now it cannot be concluded from the fact that a

state opposite to the state A follows it, that the contradictory

opposite of A is possible; and that A is therefore contingent. To

prove this, we should require to know that the state of rest could

have existed in the very same time in which the motion took place. Now

we know nothing more than that the state of rest was actual in the

time that followed the state of motion; consequently, that it was also

possible. But motion at one time, and rest at another time, are not

contradictorily opposed to each other. It follows from what has been

said that the succession of opposite determinations, that is,

change, does not demonstrate the fact of contingency as represented in

the conceptions of the pure understanding; and that it cannot,

therefore, conduct us to the fact of the existence of a necessary

being. Change proves merely empirical contingency, that is to say,

that the new state could not have existed without a cause, which

belongs to the preceding time. This cause- even although it is

regarded as absolutely necessary- must be presented to us in time, and

must belong to the series of phenomena.



                       ON THE ANTITHESIS.



  The difficulties which meet us, in our attempt to rise through the

series of phenomena to the existence of an absolutely necessary

supreme cause, must not originate from our inability to establish

the truth of our mere conceptions of the necessary existence of a

thing. That is to say, our objections not be ontological, but must

be directed against the causal connection with a series of phenomena

of a condition which is itself unconditioned. In one word, they must

be cosmological and relate to empirical laws. We must show that the

regress in the series of causes (in the world of sense) cannot

conclude with an empirically unconditioned condition, and that the

cosmological argument from the contingency of the cosmical state- a

contingency alleged to arise from change- does not justify us in

accepting a first cause, that is, a prime originator of the cosmical

series.

  The reader will observe in this antinomy a very remarkable contrast.

The very same grounds of proof which established in the thesis the

existence of a supreme being, demonstrated in the antithesis- and with

equal strictness- the non-existence of such a being. We found,

first, that a necessary being exists, because the whole time past

contains the series of all conditions, and with it, therefore, the

unconditioned (the necessary); secondly, that there does not exist any

necessary being, for the same reason, that the whole time past

contains the series of all conditions- which are themselves,

therefore, in the aggregate, conditioned. The cause of this seeming

incongruity is as follows. We attend, in the first argument, solely to

the absolute totality of the series of conditions, the one of which

determines the other in time, and thus arrive at a necessary

unconditioned. In the second, we consider, on the contrary, the

contingency of everything that is determined in the series of time-

for every event is preceded by a time, in which the condition itself

must be determined as conditioned- and thus everything that is

unconditioned or absolutely necessary disappears. In both, the mode of

proof is quite in accordance with the common procedure of human

reason, which often falls into discord with itself, from considering

an object from two different points of view. Herr von Mairan

regarded the controversy between two celebrated astronomers, which

arose from a similar difficulty as to the choice of a proper

standpoint, as a phenomenon of sufficient importance to warrant a

separate treatise on the subject. The one concluded: the moon revolves

on its own axis, because it constantly presents the same side to the

earth; the other declared that the moon does not revolve on its own

axis, for the same reason. Both conclusions were perfectly correct,

according to the point of view from which the motions of the moon were

considered.





        SECTION III. Of the Interest of Reason in these

                     Self-contradictions.



  We have thus completely before us the dialectical procedure of the

cosmological ideas. No possible experience can present us with an

object adequate to them in extent. Nay, more, reason itself cannot

cogitate them as according with the general laws of experience. And

yet they are not arbitrary fictions of thought. On the contrary,

reason, in its uninterrupted progress in the empirical synthesis, is

necessarily conducted to them, when it endeavours to free from all

conditions and to comprehend in its unconditioned totality that

which can only be determined conditionally in accordance with the laws

of experience. These dialectical propositions are so many attempts

to solve four natural and unavoidable problems of reason. There are

neither more, nor can there be less, than this number, because there

are no other series of synthetical hypotheses, limiting a priori the

empirical synthesis.

  The brilliant claims of reason striving to extend its dominion

beyond the limits of experience, have been represented above only in

dry formulae, which contain merely the grounds of its pretensions.

They have, besides, in conformity with the character of a

transcendental philosophy, been freed from every empirical element;

although the full splendour of the promises they hold out, and the

anticipations they excite, manifests itself only when in connection

with empirical cognitions. In the application of them, however, and in

the advancing enlargement of the employment of reason, while

struggling to rise from the region of experience and to soar to

those sublime ideas, philosophy discovers a value and a dignity,

which, if it could but make good its assertions, would raise it far

above all other departments of human knowledge- professing, as it

does, to present a sure foundation for our highest hopes and the

ultimate aims of all the exertions of reason. The questions: whether

the world has a beginning and a limit to its extension in space;

whether there exists anywhere, or perhaps, in my own thinking Self, an

indivisible and indestructible unity- or whether nothing but what is

divisible and transitory exists; whether I am a free agent, or, like

other beings, am bound in the chains of nature and fate; whether,

finally, there is a supreme cause of the world, or all our thought and

speculation must end with nature and the order of external things- are

questions for the solution of which the mathematician would

willingly exchange his whole science; for in it there is no

satisfaction for the highest aspirations and most ardent desires of

humanity. Nay, it may even be said that the true value of mathematics-

that pride of human reason- consists in this: that she guides reason

to the knowledge of nature- in her greater as well as in her less

manifestations- in her beautiful order and regularity- guides her,

moreover, to an insight into the wonderful unity of the moving

forces in the operations of nature, far beyond the expectations of a

philosophy building only on experience; and that she thus encourages

philosophy to extend the province of reason beyond all experience, and

at the same time provides it with the most excellent materials for

supporting its investigations, in so far as their nature admits, by

adequate and accordant intuitions.

  Unfortunately for speculation- but perhaps fortunately for the

practical interests of humanity- reason, in the midst of her highest

anticipations, finds herself hemmed in by a press of opposite and

contradictory conclusions, from which neither her honour nor her

safety will permit her to draw back. Nor can she regard these

conflicting trains of reasoning with indifference as mere passages

at arms, still less can she command peace; for in the subject of the

conflict she has a deep interest. There is no other course left open

to her than to reflect with herself upon the origin of this disunion

in reason- whether it may not arise from a mere misunderstanding.

After such an inquiry, arrogant claims would have to be given up on

both sides; but the sovereignty of reason over understanding and sense

would be based upon a sure foundation.

  We shall at present defer this radical inquiry and, in the meantime,

consider for a little what side in the controversy we should most

willingly take, if we were obliged to become partisans at all. As,

in this case, we leave out of sight altogether the logical criterion

of truth, and merely consult our own interest in reference to the

question, these considerations, although inadequate to settle the

question of right in either party, will enable us to comprehend how

those who have taken part in the struggle, adopt the one view rather

than the other- no special insight into the subject, however, having

influenced their choice. They will, at the same time, explain to us

many other things by the way- for example, the fiery zeal on the one

side and the cold maintenance of their cause on the other; why the one

party has met with the warmest approbations, and the other has

always been repulsed by irreconcilable prejudices.

  There is one thing, however, that determines the proper point of

view, from which alone this preliminary inquiry can be instituted

and carried on with the proper completeness- and that is the

comparison of the principles from which both sides, thesis and

antithesis, proceed. My readers would remark in the propositions of

the antithesis a complete uniformity in the mode of thought and a

perfect unity of principle. Its principle was that of pure empiricism,

not only in the explication of the phenomena in the world, but also in

the solution of the transcendental ideas, even of that of the universe

itself. The affirmations of the thesis, on the contrary, were based,

in addition to the empirical mode of explanation employed in the

series of phenomena, on intellectual propositions; and its

principles were in so far not simple. I shall term the thesis, in view

of its essential characteristic, the dogmatism of pure reason.

  On the side of Dogmatism, or of the thesis, therefore, in the

determination of the cosmological ideas, we find:

  1. A practical interest, which must be very dear to every

right-thinking man. That the word has a beginning- that the nature

of my thinking self is simple, and therefore indestructible- that I am

a free agent, and raised above the compulsion of nature and her

laws- and, finally, that the entire order of things, which form the

world, is dependent upon a Supreme Being, from whom the whole receives

unity and connection- these are so many foundation-stones of

morality and religion. The antithesis deprives us of all these

supports- or, at least, seems so to deprive us.

  2. A speculative interest of reason manifests itself on this side.

For, if we take the transcendental ideas and employ them in the manner

which the thesis directs, we can exhibit completely a priori the

entire chain of conditions, and understand the derivation of the

conditioned- beginning from the unconditioned. This the antithesis

does not do; and for this reason does not meet with so welcome a

reception. For it can give no answer to our question respecting the

conditions of its synthesis- except such as must be supplemented by

another question, and so on to infinity. According to it, we must rise

from a given beginning to one still higher; every part conducts us

to a still smaller one; every event is preceded by another event which

is its cause; and the conditions of existence rest always upon other

and still higher conditions, and find neither end nor basis in some

self-subsistent thing as the primal being.

  3. This side has also the advantage of popularity; and this

constitutes no small part of its claim to favour. The common

understanding does not find the least difficulty in the idea of the

unconditioned beginning of all synthesis- accustomed, as it is, rather

to follow our consequences than to seek for a proper basis for

cognition. In the conception of an absolute first, moreover- the

possibility of which it does not inquire into- it is highly

gratified to find a firmly-established point of departure for its

attempts at theory; while in the restless and continuous ascent from

the conditioned to the condition, always with one foot in the air,

it can find no satisfaction.

  On the side of the antithesis, or Empiricism, in the determination

of the cosmological ideas:

  1. We cannot discover any such practical interest arising from

pure principles of reason as morality and religion present. On the

contrary, pure empiricism seems to empty them of all their power and

influence. If there does not exist a Supreme Being distinct from the

world- if the world is without beginning, consequently without a

Creator- if our wills are not free, and the soul is divisible and

subject to corruption just like matter- the ideas and principles of

morality lose all validity and fall with the transcendental ideas

which constituted their theoretical support.

  2. But empiricism, in compensation, holds out to reason, in its

speculative interests, certain important advantages, far exceeding any

that the dogmatist can promise us. For, when employed by the

empiricist, understanding is always upon its proper ground of

investigation- the field of possible experience, the laws of which

it can explore, and thus extend its cognition securely and with

clear intelligence without being stopped by limits in any direction.

Here can it and ought it to find and present to intuition its proper

object- not only in itself, but in all its relations; or, if it employ

conceptions, upon this ground it can always present the

corresponding images in clear and unmistakable intuitions. It is quite

unnecessary for it to renounce the guidance of nature, to attach

itself to ideas, the objects of which it cannot know; because, as mere

intellectual entities, they cannot be presented in any intuition. On

the contrary, it is not even permitted to abandon its proper

occupation, under the pretence that it has been brought to a

conclusion (for it never can be), and to pass into the region of

idealizing reason and transcendent conceptions, which it is not

required to observe and explore the laws of nature, but merely to

think and to imagine- secure from being contradicted by facts, because

they have not been called as witnesses, but passed by, or perhaps

subordinated to the so-called higher interests and considerations of

pure reason.

  Hence the empiricist will never allow himself to accept any epoch of

nature for the first- the absolutely primal state; he will not believe

that there can be limits to his outlook into her wide domains, nor

pass from the objects of nature, which he can satisfactorily explain

by means of observation and mathematical thought- which he can

determine synthetically in intuition, to those which neither sense nor

imagination can ever present in concreto; he will not concede the

existence of a faculty in nature, operating independently of the

laws of nature- a concession which would introduce uncertainty into

the procedure of the understanding, which is guided by necessary

laws to the observation of phenomena; nor, finally, will he permit

himself to seek a cause beyond nature, inasmuch as we know nothing but

it, and from it alone receive an objective basis for all our

conceptions and instruction in the unvarying laws of things.

  In truth, if the empirical philosopher had no other purpose in the

establishment of his antithesis than to check the presumption of a

reason which mistakes its true destination, which boasts of its

insight and its knowledge, just where all insight and knowledge

cease to exist, and regards that which is valid only in relation to

a practical interest, as an advancement of the speculative interests

of the mind (in order, when it is convenient for itself, to break

the thread of our physical investigations, and, under pretence of

extending our cognition, connect them with transcendental ideas, by

means of which we really know only that we know nothing)- if, I say,

the empiricist rested satisfied with this benefit, the principle

advanced by him would be a maxim recommending moderation in the

pretensions of reason and modesty in its affirmations, and at the same

time would direct us to the right mode of extending the province of

the understanding, by the help of the only true teacher, experience.

In obedience to this advice, intellectual hypotheses and faith would

not be called in aid of our practical interests; nor should we

introduce them under the pompous titles of science and insight. For

speculative cognition cannot find an objective basis any other where

than in experience; and, when we overstep its limits our synthesis,

which requires ever new cognitions independent of experience, has no

substratum of intuition upon which to build.

  But if- as often happens- empiricism, in relation to ideas,

becomes itself dogmatic and boldly denies that which is above the

sphere of its phenomenal cognition, it falls itself into the error

of intemperance- an error which is here all the more reprehensible, as

thereby the practical interest of reason receives an irreparable

injury.

  And this constitutes the opposition between Epicureanism* and

Platonism.



  *It is, however, still a matter of doubt whether Epicurus ever

propounded these principles as directions for the objective employment

of the understanding. If, indeed, they were nothing more than maxims

for the speculative exercise of reason, he gives evidence therein a

more genuine philosophic spirit than any of the philosophers of

antiquity. That, in the explanation of phenomena, we must proceed as

if the field of inquiry had neither limits in space nor commencement

in time; that we must be satisfied with the teaching of experience

in reference to the material of which the world is posed; that we must

not look for any other mode of the origination of events than that

which is determined by the unalterable laws of nature; and finally,

that we not employ the hypothesis of a cause distinct from the world

to account for a phenomenon or for the world itself- are principles

for the extension of speculative philosophy, and the discovery of

the true sources of the principles of morals, which, however little

conformed to in the present day, are undoubtedly correct. At the

same time, any one desirous of ignoring, in mere speculation, these

dogmatical propositions, need not for that reason be accused of

denying them.



  Both Epicurus and Plato assert more in their systems than they know.

The former encourages and advances science- although to the

prejudice of the practical; the latter presents us with excellent

principles for the investigation of the practical, but, in relation to

everything regarding which we can attain to speculative cognition,

permits reason to append idealistic explanations of natural phenomena,

to the great injury of physical investigation.

  3. In regard to the third motive for the preliminary choice of a

party in this war of assertions, it seems very extraordinary that

empiricism should be utterly unpopular. We should be inclined to

believe that the common understanding would receive it with

pleasure- promising as it does to satisfy it without passing the

bounds of experience and its connected order; while transcendental

dogmatism obliges it to rise to conceptions which far surpass the

intelligence and ability of the most practised thinkers. But in

this, in truth, is to be found its real motive. For the common

understanding thus finds itself in a situation where not even the most

learned can have the advantage of it. If it understands little or

nothing about these transcendental conceptions, no one can boast of

understanding any more; and although it may not express itself in so

scholastically correct a manner as others, it can busy itself with

reasoning and arguments without end, wandering among mere ideas, about

which one can always be very eloquent, because we know nothing about

them; while, in the observation and investigation of nature, it

would be forced to remain dumb and to confess its utter ignorance.

Thus indolence and vanity form of themselves strong recommendations of

these principles. Besides, although it is a hard thing for a

philosopher to assume a principle, of which he can give to himself

no reasonable account, and still more to employ conceptions, the

objective reality of which cannot be established, nothing is more

usual with the common understanding. It wants something which will

allow it to go to work with confidence. The difficulty of even

comprehending a supposition does not disquiet it, because- not knowing

what comprehending means- it never even thinks of the supposition it

may be adopting as a principle; and regards as known that with which

it has become familiar from constant use. And, at last, all

speculative interests disappear before the practical interests which

it holds dear; and it fancies that it understands and knows what its

necessities and hopes incite it to assume or to believe. Thus the

empiricism of transcendentally idealizing reason is robbed of all

popularity; and, however prejudicial it may be to the highest

practical principles, there is no fear that it will ever pass the

limits of the schools, or acquire any favour or influence in society

or with the multitude a

  Human reason is by nature architectonic. That is to say, it

regards all cognitions as parts of a possible system, and hence

accepts only such principles as at least do not incapacitate a

cognition to which we may have attained from being placed along with

others in a general system. But the propositions of the antithesis are

of a character which renders the completion of an edifice of

cognitions impossible. According to these, beyond one state or epoch

of the world there is always to be found one more ancient; in every

part always other parts themselves divisible; preceding every event

another, the origin of which must itself be sought still higher; and

everything in existence is conditioned, and still not dependent on

an unconditioned and primal existence. As, therefore, the antithesis

will not concede the existence of a first beginning which might be

available as a foundation, a complete edifice of cognition, in the

presence of such hypothesis, is utterly impossible. Thus the

architectonic interest of reason, which requires a unity- not

empirical, but a priori and rational- forms a natural recommendation

for the assertions of the thesis in our antinomy.

  But if any one could free himself entirely from all considerations

of interest, and weigh without partiality the assertions of reason,

attending only to their content, irrespective of the consequences

which follow from them; such a person, on the supposition that he knew

no other way out of the confusion than to settle the truth of one or

other of the conflicting doctrines, would live in a state of continual

hesitation. Today, he would feel convinced that the human will is

free; to-morrow, considering the indissoluble chain of nature, he

would look on freedom as a mere illusion and declare nature to be

all-in-all. But, if he were called to action, the play of the merely

speculative reason would disappear like the shapes of a dream, and

practical interest would dictate his choice of principles. But, as

it well befits a reflective and inquiring being to devote certain

periods of time to the examination of its own reason- to divest itself

of all partiality, and frankly to communicate its observations for the

judgement and opinion of others; so no one can be blamed for, much

less prevented from, placing both parties on their trial, with

permission to end themselves, free from intimidation, before

intimidation, before a sworn jury of equal condition with

themselves- the condition of weak and fallible men.





       SECTION IV. Of the necessity imposed upon Pure Reason

           of presenting a Solution of its Transcendental

                           Problems.



  To avow an ability to solve all problems and to answer all questions

would be a profession certain to convict any philosopher of

extravagant boasting and self-conceit, and at once to destroy the

confidence that might otherwise have been reposed in him. There are,

however, sciences so constituted that every question arising within

their sphere must necessarily be capable of receiving an answer from

the knowledge already possessed, for the answer must be received

from the same sources whence the question arose. In such sciences it

is not allowable to excuse ourselves on the plea of necessary and

unavoidable ignorance; a solution is absolutely requisite. The rule of

right and wrong must help us to the knowledge of what is right or

wrong in all possible cases; otherwise, the idea of obligation or duty

would be utterly null, for we cannot have any obligation to that which

we cannot know. On the other hand, in our investigations of the

phenomena of nature, much must remain uncertain, and many questions

continue insoluble; because what we know of nature is far from being

sufficient to explain all the phenomena that are presented to our

observation. Now the question is: "Whether there is in

transcendental philosophy any question, relating to an object

presented to pure reason, which is unanswerable by this reason; and

whether we must regard the subject of the question as quite uncertain,

so far as our knowledge extends, and must give it a place among

those subjects, of which we have just so much conception as is

sufficient to enable us to raise a question- faculty or materials

failing us, however, when we attempt an answer. the world

  Now I maintain that, among all speculative cognition, the

peculiarity of transcendental philosophy is that there is no question,

relating to an object presented to pure reason, which is insoluble

by this reason; and that the profession of unavoidable ignorance-

the problem being alleged to be beyond the reach of our faculties-

cannot free us from the obligation to present a complete and

satisfactory answer. For the very conception which enables us to raise

the question must give us the power of answering it; inasmuch as the

object, as in the case of right and wrong, is not to be discovered out

of the conception.

  But, in transcendental philosophy, it is only the cosmological

questions to which we can demand a satisfactory answer in relation

to the constitution of their object; and the philosopher is not

permitted to avail himself of the pretext of necessary ignorance and

impenetrable obscurity. These questions relate solely to the

cosmological ideas. For the object must be given in experience, and

the question relates to the adequateness of the object to an idea.

If the object is transcendental and therefore itself unknown; if the

question, for example, is whether the object- the something, the

phenomenon of which (internal- in ourselves) is thought- that is to

say, the soul, is in itself a simple being; or whether there is a

cause of all things, which is absolutely necessary- in such cases we

are seeking for our idea an object, of which we may confess that it is

unknown to us, though we must not on that account assert that it is

impossible.* The cosmological ideas alone posses the peculiarity

that we can presuppose the object of them and the empirical

synthesis requisite for the conception of that object to be given; and

the question, which arises from these ideas, relates merely to the

progress of this synthesis, in so far as it must contain absolute

totality- which, however, is not empirical, as it cannot be given in

any experience. Now, as the question here is solely in regard to a

thing as the object of a possible experience and not as a thing in

itself, the answer to the transcendental cosmological question need

not be sought out of the idea, for the question does not regard an

object in itself. The question in relation to a possible experience is

not, "What can be given in an experience in concreto" but "what is

contained in the idea, to which the empirical synthesis must

approximate." The question must therefore be capable of solution

from the idea alone. For the idea is a creation of reason itself,

which therefore cannot disclaim the obligation to answer or refer us

to the unknown object.



  *The question, "What is the constitution of a transcendental

object?" is unanswerable- we are unable to say what it is; but we

can perceive that the question itself is nothing; because it does

not relate to any object that can be presented to us. For this reason,

we must consider all the questions raised in transcendental psychology

as answerable and as really answered; for they relate to the

transcendental subject of all internal phenomena, which is not

itself phenomenon and consequently not given as an object, in which,

moreover, none of the categories- and it is to them that the

question is properly directed- find any conditions of its application.

Here, therefore, is a case where no answer is the only proper

answer. For a question regarding the constitution of a something which

cannot be cogitated by any determined predicate, being completely

beyond the sphere of objects and experience, is perfectly null and

void.



  It is not so extraordinary, as it at first sight appears, that a

science should demand and expect satisfactory answers to all the

questions that may arise within its own sphere (questiones

domesticae), although, up to a certain time, these answers may not

have been discovered. There are, in addition to transcendental

philosophy, only two pure sciences of reason; the one with a

speculative, the other with a practical content- pure mathematics

and pure ethics. Has any one ever heard it alleged that, from our

complete and necessary ignorance of the conditions, it is uncertain

what exact relation the diameter of a circle bears to the circle in

rational or irrational numbers? By the former the sum cannot be

given exactly, by the latter only approximately; and therefore we

decide that the impossibility of a solution of the question is

evident. Lambert presented us with a demonstration of this. In the

general principles of morals there can be nothing uncertain, for the

propositions are either utterly without meaning, or must originate

solely in our rational conceptions. On the other hand, there must be

in physical science an infinite number of conjectures, which can never

become certainties; because the phenomena of nature are not given as

objects dependent on our conceptions. The key to the solution of

such questions cannot, therefore, be found in our conceptions, or in

pure thought, but must lie without us and for that reason is in many

cases not to be discovered; and consequently a satisfactory

explanation cannot be expected. The questions of transcendental

analytic, which relate to the deduction of our pure cognition, are not

to be regarded as of the same kind as those mentioned above; for we

are not at present treating of the certainty of judgements in relation

to the origin of our conceptions, but only of that certainty in

relation to objects.

  We cannot, therefore, escape the responsibility of at least a

critical solution of the questions of reason, by complaints of the

limited nature of our faculties, and the seemingly humble confession

that it is beyond the power of our reason to decide, whether the world

has existed from all eternity or had a beginning- whether it is

infinitely extended, or enclosed within certain limits- whether

anything in the world is simple, or whether everything must be capable

of infinite divisibility- whether freedom can originate phenomena,

or whether everything is absolutely dependent on the laws and order of

nature- and, finally, whether there exists a being that is

completely unconditioned and necessary, or whether the existence of

everything is conditioned and consequently dependent on something

external to itself, and therefore in its own nature contingent. For

all these questions relate to an object, which can be given nowhere

else than in thought. This object is the absolutely unconditioned

totality of the synthesis of phenomena. If the conceptions in our

minds do not assist us to some certain result in regard to these

problems, we must not defend ourselves on the plea that the object

itself remains hidden from and unknown to us. For no such thing or

object can be given- it is not to be found out of the idea in our

minds. We must seek the cause of our failure in our idea itself, which

is an insoluble problem and in regard to which we obstinately assume

that there exists a real object corresponding and adequate to it. A

clear explanation of the dialectic which lies in our conception,

will very soon enable us to come to a satisfactory decision in

regard to such a question.

  The pretext that we are unable to arrive at certainty in regard to

these problems may be met with this question, which requires at

least a plain answer: "From what source do the ideas originate, the

solution of which involves you in such difficulties? Are you seeking

for an explanation of certain phenomena; and do you expect these ideas

to give you the principles or the rules of this explanation?" Let it

be granted, that all nature was laid open before you; that nothing was

hid from your senses and your consciousness. Still, you could not

cognize in concreto the object of your ideas in any experience. For

what is demanded is not only this full and complete intuition, but

also a complete synthesis and the consciousness of its absolute

totality; and this is not possible by means of any empirical

cognition. It follows that your question- your idea- is by no means

necessary for the explanation of any phenomenon; and the idea cannot

have been in any sense given by the object itself. For such an

object can never be presented to us, because it cannot be given by any

possible experience. Whatever perceptions you may attain to, you are

still surrounded by conditions- in space, or in time- and you cannot

discover anything unconditioned; nor can you decide whether this

unconditioned is to be placed in an absolute beginning of the

synthesis, or in an absolute totality of the series without beginning.

A whole, in the empirical signification of the term, is always

merely comparative. The absolute whole of quantity (the universe),

of division, of derivation, of the condition of existence, with the

question- whether it is to be produced by finite or infinite

synthesis, no possible experience can instruct us concerning. You will

not, for example, be able to explain the phenomena of a body in the

least degree better, whether you believe it to consist of simple, or

of composite parts; for a simple phenomenon- and just as little an

infinite series of composition- can never be presented to your

perception. Phenomena require and admit of explanation, only in so far

as the conditions of that explanation are given in perception; but the

sum total of that which is given in phenomena, considered as an

absolute whole, is itself a perception- and we cannot therefore seek

for explanations of this whole beyond itself, in other perceptions.

The explanation of this whole is the proper object of the

transcendental problems of pure reason.

  Although, therefore, the solution of these problems is

unattainable through experience, we must not permit ourselves to say

that it is uncertain how the object of our inquiries is constituted.

For the object is in our own mind and cannot be discovered in

experience; and we have only to take care that our thoughts are

consistent with each other, and to avoid falling into the amphiboly of

regarding our idea as a representation of an object empirically given,

and therefore to be cognized according to the laws of experience. A

dogmatical solution is therefore not only unsatisfactory but

impossible. The critical solution, which may be a perfectly certain

one, does not consider the question objectively, but proceeds by

inquiring into the basis of the cognition upon which the question

rests.



     SECTION V. Sceptical Exposition of the Cosmological Problems

           presented in the four Transcendental Ideas.



  We should be quite willing to desist from the demand of a dogmatical

answer to our questions, if we understood beforehand that, be the

answer what it may, it would only serve to increase our ignorance,

to throw us from one incomprehensibility into another, from one

obscurity into another still greater, and perhaps lead us into

irreconcilable contradictions. If a dogmatical affirmative or negative

answer is demanded, is it at all prudent to set aside the probable

grounds of a solution which lie before us and to take into

consideration what advantage we shall gain, if the answer is to favour

the one side or the other? If it happens that in both cases the answer

is mere nonsense, we have in this an irresistible summons to institute

a critical investigation of the question, for the purpose of

discovering whether it is based on a groundless presupposition and

relates to an idea, the falsity of which would be more easily

exposed in its application and consequences than in the mere

representation of its content. This is the great utility of the

sceptical mode of treating the questions addressed by pure reason to

itself. By this method we easily rid ourselves of the confusions of

dogmatism, and establish in its place a temperate criticism, which, as

a genuine cathartic, will successfully remove the presumptuous notions

of philosophy and their consequence- the vain pretension to

universal science.

  If, then, I could understand the nature of a cosmological idea and

perceive, before I entered on the discussion of the subject at all,

that, whatever side of the question regarding the unconditioned of the

regressive synthesis of phenomena it favoured- it must either be too

great or too small for every conception of the understanding- I

would be able to comprehend how the idea, which relates to an object

of experience- an experience which must be adequate to and in

accordance with a possible conception of the understanding- must be

completely void and without significance, inasmuch as its object is

inadequate, consider it as we may. And this is actually the case

with all cosmological conceptions, which, for the reason above

mentioned, involve reason, so long as it remains attached to them,

in an unavoidable antinomy. For suppose:

  First, that the world has no beginning- in this case it is too large

for our conception; for this conception, which consists in a

successive regress, cannot overtake the whole eternity that has

elapsed. Grant that it has a beginning, it is then too small for the

conception of the understanding. For, as a beginning presupposes a

time preceding, it cannot be unconditioned; and the law of the

empirical employment of the understanding imposes the necessity of

looking for a higher condition of time; and the world is, therefore,

evidently too small for this law.

  The same is the case with the double answer to the question

regarding the extent, in space, of the world. For, if it is infinite

and unlimited, it must be too large for every possible empirical

conception. If it is finite and limited, we have a right to ask: "What

determines these limits?" Void space is not a self-subsistent

correlate of things, and cannot be a final condition- and still less

an empirical condition, forming a part of a possible experience. For

how can we have any experience or perception of an absolute void?

But the absolute totality of the empirical synthesis requires that the

unconditioned be an empirical conception. Consequently, a finite world

is too small for our conception.

  Secondly, if every phenomenon (matter) in space consists of an

infinite number of parts, the regress of the division is always too

great for our conception; and if the division of space must cease with

some member of the division (the simple), it is too small for the idea

of the unconditioned. For the member at which we have discontinued our

division still admits a regress to many more parts contained in the

object.

  Thirdly, suppose that every event in the world happens in accordance

with the laws of nature; the causality of a cause must itself be an

event and necessitates a regress to a still higher cause, and

consequently the unceasing prolongation of the series of conditions

a parte priori. Operative nature is therefore too large for every

conception we can form in the synthesis of cosmical events.

  If we admit the existence of spontaneously produced events, that is,

of free agency, we are driven, in our search for sufficient reasons,

on an unavoidable law of nature and are compelled to appeal to the

empirical law of causality, and we find that any such totality of

connection in our synthesis is too small for our necessary empirical

conception.

  Fourthly, if we assume the existence of an absolutely necessary

being- whether it be the world or something in the world, or the cause

of the world- we must place it in a time at an infinite distance

from any given moment; for, otherwise, it must be dependent on some

other and higher existence. Such an existence is, in this case, too

large for our empirical conception, and unattainable by the

continued regress of any synthesis.

  But if we believe that everything in the world- be it condition or

conditioned- is contingent; every given existence is too small for our

conception. For in this case we are compelled to seek for some other

existence upon which the former depends.

  We have said that in all these cases the cosmological idea is either

too great or too small for the empirical regress in a synthesis, and

consequently for every possible conception of the understanding. Why

did we not express ourselves in a manner exactly the reverse of this

and, instead of accusing the cosmological idea of over stepping or

of falling short of its true aim, possible experience, say that, in

the first case, the empirical conception is always too small for the

idea, and in the second too great, and thus attach the blame of

these contradictions to the empirical regress? The reason is this.

Possible experience can alone give reality to our conceptions; without

it a conception is merely an idea, without truth or relation to an

object. Hence a possible empirical conception must be the standard

by which we are to judge whether an idea is anything more than an idea

and fiction of thought, or whether it relates to an object in the

world. If we say of a thing that in relation to some other thing it is

too large or too small, the former is considered as existing for the

sake of the latter, and requiring to be adapted to it. Among the

trivial subjects of discussion in the old schools of dialectics was

this question: "If a ball cannot pass through a hole, shall we say

that the ball is too large or the hole too small?" In this case it

is indifferent what expression we employ; for we do not know which

exists for the sake of the other. On the other hand, we cannot say:

"The man is too long for his coat"; but: "The coat is too short for

the man."

  We are thus led to the well-founded suspicion that the

cosmological ideas, and all the conflicting sophistical assertions

connected with them, are based upon a false and fictitious

conception of the mode in which the object of these ideas is presented

to us; and this suspicion will probably direct us how to expose the

illusion that has so long led us astray from the truth.



      SECTION VI. Transcendental Idealism as the Key to the

            Solution of Pure Cosmological Dialectic.



  In the transcendental aesthetic we proved that everything intuited

in space and time, all objects of a possible experience, are nothing

but phenomena, that is, mere representations; and that these, as

presented to us- as extended bodies, or as series of changes- have

no self-subsistent existence apart from human thought. This doctrine I

call Transcendental Idealism.* The realist in the transcendental sense

regards these modifications of our sensibility, these mere

representations, as things subsisting in themselves.



  *I have elsewhere termed this theory formal idealism, to distinguish

it from material idealism, which doubts or denies the existence of

external things. To avoid ambiguity, it seems advisable in many

cases to employ this term instead of that mentioned in the text.



  It would be unjust to accuse us of holding the long-decried theory

of empirical idealism, which, while admitting the reality of space,

denies, or at least doubts, the existence of bodies extended in it,

and thus leaves us without a sufficient criterion of reality and

illusion. The supporters of this theory find no difficulty in

admitting the reality of the phenomena of the internal sense in

time; nay, they go the length of maintaining that this internal

experience is of itself a sufficient proof of the real existence of

its object as a thing in itself.

  Transcendental idealism allows that the objects of external

intuition- as intuited in space, and all changes in time- as

represented by the internal sense, are real. For, as space is the form

of that intuition which we call external, and, without objects in

space, no empirical representation could be given us, we can and ought

to regard extended bodies in it as real. The case is the same with

representations in time. But time and space, with all phenomena

therein, are not in themselves things. They are nothing but

representations and cannot exist out of and apart from the mind.

Nay, the sensuous internal intuition of the mind (as the object of

consciousness), the determination of which is represented by the

succession of different states in time, is not the real, proper

self, as it exists in itself- not the transcendental subject- but only

a phenomenon, which is presented to the sensibility of this, to us,

unknown being. This internal phenomenon cannot be admitted to be a

self-subsisting thing; for its condition is time, and time cannot be

the condition of a thing in itself. But the empirical truth of

phenomena in space and time is guaranteed beyond the possibility of

doubt, and sufficiently distinguished from the illusion of dreams or

fancy- although both have a proper and thorough connection in an

experience according to empirical laws. The objects of experience then

are not things in themselves, but are given only in experience, and

have no existence apart from and independently of experience. That

there may be inhabitants in the moon, although no one has ever

observed them, must certainly be admitted; but this assertion means

only, that we may in the possible progress of experience discover them

at some future time. For that which stands in connection with a

perception according to the laws of the progress of experience is

real. They are therefore really existent, if they stand in empirical

connection with my actual or real consciousness, although they are not

in themselves real, that is, apart from the progress of experience.

  There is nothing actually given- we can be conscious of nothing as

real, except a perception and the empirical progression from it to

other possible perceptions. For phenomena, as mere representations,

are real only in perception; and perception is, in fact, nothing but

the reality of an empirical representation, that is, a phenomenon.

To call a phenomenon a real thing prior to perception means either

that we must meet with this phenomenon in the progress of

experience, or it means nothing at all. For I can say only of a

thing in itself that it exists without relation to the senses and

experience. But we are speaking here merely of phenomena in space

and time, both of which are determinations of sensibility, and not

of things in themselves. It follows that phenomena are not things in

themselves, but are mere representations, which if not given in us- in

perception- are non-existent.

  The faculty of sensuous intuition is properly a receptivity- a

capacity of being affected in a certain manner by representations, the

relation of which to each other is a pure intuition of space and time-

the pure forms of sensibility. These representations, in so far as

they are connected and determinable in this relation (in space and

time) according to laws of the unity of experience, are called

objects. The non-sensuous cause of these representations is completely

unknown to us and hence cannot be intuited as an object. For such an

object could not be represented either in space or in time; and

without these conditions intuition or representation is impossible. We

may, at the same time, term the non-sensuous cause of phenomena the

transcendental object- but merely as a mental correlate to

sensibility, considered as a receptivity. To this transcendental

object we may attribute the whole connection and extent of our

possible perceptions, and say that it is given and exists in itself

prior to all experience. But the phenomena, corresponding to it, are

not given as things in themselves, but in experience alone. For they

are mere representations, receiving from perceptions alone

significance and relation to a real object, under the condition that

this or that perception- indicating an object- is in complete

connection with all others in accordance with the rules of the unity

of experience. Thus we can say: "The things that really existed in

past time are given in the transcendental object of experience." But

these are to me real objects, only in so far as I can represent to

my own mind, that a regressive series of possible perceptions-

following the indications of history, or the footsteps of cause and

effect- in accordance with empirical laws- that, in one word, the

course of the world conducts us to an elapsed series of time as the

condition of the present time. This series in past time is represented

as real, not in itself, but only in connection with a possible

experience. Thus, when I say that certain events occurred in past

time, I merely assert the possibility of prolonging the chain of

experience, from the present perception, upwards to the conditions

that determine it according to time.

  If I represent to myself all objects existing in all space and time,

I do not thereby place these in space and time prior to all

experience; on the contrary, such a representation is nothing more

than the notion of a possible experience, in its absolute

completeness. In experience alone are those objects, which are nothing

but representations, given. But, when I say they existed prior to my

experience, this means only that I must begin with the perception

present to me and follow the track indicated until I discover them

in some part or region of experience. The cause of the empirical

condition of this progression- and consequently at what member therein

I must stop, and at what point in the regress I am to find this

member- is transcendental, and hence necessarily incognizable. But

with this we have not to do; our concern is only with the law of

progression in experience, in which objects, that is, phenomena, are

given. It is a matter of indifference, whether I say, "I may in the

progress of experience discover stars, at a hundred times greater

distance than the most distant of those now visible," or, "Stars at

this distance may be met in space, although no one has, or ever will

discover them." For, if they are given as things in themselves,

without any relation to possible experience, they are for me

non-existent, consequently, are not objects, for they are not

contained in the regressive series of experience. But, if these

phenomena must be employed in the construction or support of the

cosmological idea of an absolute whole, and when we are discussing a

question that oversteps the limits of possible experience, the

proper distinction of the different theories of the reality of

sensuous objects is of great importance, in order to avoid the

illusion which must necessarily arise from the misinterpretation of

our empirical conceptions.



    SECTION VII. Critical Solution of the Cosmological Problem.



  The antinomy of pure reason is based upon the following

dialectical argument: "If that which is conditioned is given, the

whole series of its conditions is also given; but sensuous objects are

given as conditioned; consequently..." This syllogism, the major of

which seems so natural and evident, introduces as many cosmological

ideas as there are different kinds of conditions in the synthesis of

phenomena, in so far as these conditions constitute a series. These

ideas require absolute totality in the series, and thus place reason

in inextricable embarrassment. Before proceeding to expose the fallacy

in this dialectical argument, it will be necessary to have a correct

understanding of certain conceptions that appear in it.

  In the first place, the following proposition is evident, and

indubitably certain: "If the conditioned is given, a regress in the

series of all its conditions is thereby imperatively required." For

the very conception of a conditioned is a conception of something

related to a condition, and, if this condition is itself

conditioned, to another condition- and so on through all the members

of the series. This proposition is, therefore, analytical and has

nothing to fear from transcendental criticism. It is a logical

postulate of reason: to pursue, as far as possible, the connection

of a conception with its conditions.

  If, in the second place, both the conditioned and the condition

are things in themselves, and if the former is given, not only is

the regress to the latter requisite, but the latter is really given

with the former. Now, as this is true of all the members of the

series, the entire series of conditions, and with them the

unconditioned, is at the same time given in the very fact of the

conditioned, the existence of which is possible only in and through

that series, being given. In this case, the synthesis of the

conditioned with its condition, is a synthesis of the understanding

merely, which represents things as they are, without regarding whether

and how we can cognize them. But if I have to do with phenomena,

which, in their character of mere representations, are not given, if I

do not attain to a cognition of them (in other words, to themselves,

for they are nothing more than empirical cognitions), I am not

entitled to say: "If the conditioned is given, all its conditions

(as phenomena) are also given." I cannot, therefore, from the fact

of a conditioned being given, infer the absolute totality of the

series of its conditions. For phenomena are nothing but an empirical

synthesis in apprehension or perception, and are therefore given

only in it. Now, in speaking of phenomena it does not follow that,

if the conditioned is given, the synthesis which constitutes its

empirical condition is also thereby given and presupposed; such a

synthesis can be established only by an actual regress in the series

of conditions. But we are entitled to say in this case that a

regress to the conditions of a conditioned, in other words, that a

continuous empirical synthesis is enjoined; that, if the conditions

are not given, they are at least required; and that we are certain

to discover the conditions in this regress.

  We can now see that the major, in the above cosmological

syllogism, takes the conditioned in the transcendental signification

which it has in the pure category, while the minor speaks of it in the

empirical signification which it has in the category as applied to

phenomena. There is, therefore, a dialectical fallacy in the

syllogism- a sophisma figurae dictionis. But this fallacy is not a

consciously devised one, but a perfectly natural illusion of the

common reason of man. For, when a thing is given as conditioned, we

presuppose in the major its conditions and their series,

unperceived, as it were, and unseen; because this is nothing more than

the logical requirement of complete and satisfactory premisses for a

given conclusion. In this case, time is altogether left out in the

connection of the conditioned with the condition; they are supposed to

be given in themselves, and contemporaneously. It is, moreover, just

as natural to regard phenomena (in the minor) as things in

themselves and as objects presented to the pure understanding, as in

the major, in which complete abstraction was made of all conditions of

intuition. But it is under these conditions alone that objects are

given. Now we overlooked a remarkable distinction between the

conceptions. The synthesis of the conditioned with its condition,

and the complete series of the latter (in the major) are not limited

by time, and do not contain the conception of succession. On the

contrary, the empirical synthesis and the series of conditions in

the phenomenal world- subsumed in the minor- are necessarily

successive and given in time alone. It follows that I cannot

presuppose in the minor, as I did in the major, the absolute

totality of the synthesis and of the series therein represented; for

in the major all the members of the series are given as things in

themselves- without any limitations or conditions of time, while in

the minor they are possible only in and through a successive

regress, which cannot exist, except it be actually carried into

execution in the world of phenomena.

  After this proof of the viciousness of the argument commonly

employed in maintaining cosmological assertions, both parties may

now be justly dismissed, as advancing claims without grounds or title.

But the process has not been ended by convincing them that one or both

were in the wrong and had maintained an assertion which was without

valid grounds of proof. Nothing seems to be clearer than that, if

one maintains: "The world has a beginning," and another: "The world

has no beginning," one of the two must be right. But it is likewise

clear that, if the evidence on both sides is equal, it is impossible

to discover on what side the truth lies; and the controversy

continues, although the parties have been recommended to peace

before the tribunal of reason. There remains, then, no other means

of settling the question than to convince the parties, who refute each

other with such conclusiveness and ability, that they are disputing

about nothing, and that a transcendental illusion has been mocking

them with visions of reality where there is none. The mode of

adjusting a dispute which cannot be decided upon its own merits, we

shall now proceed to lay before our readers.



  Zeno of Elea, a subtle dialectician, was severely reprimanded by

Plato as a sophist, who, merely from the base motive of exhibiting his

skill in discussion, maintained and subverted the same proposition

by arguments as powerful and convincing on the one side as on the

other. He maintained, for example, that God (who was probably

nothing more, in his view, than the world) is neither finite nor

infinite, neither in motion nor in rest, neither similar nor

dissimilar to any other thing. It seemed to those philosophers who

criticized his mode of discussion that his purpose was to deny

completely both of two self-contradictory propositions- which is

absurd. But I cannot believe that there is any justice in this

accusation. The first of these propositions I shall presently consider

in a more detailed manner. With regard to the others, if by the word

of God he understood merely the Universe, his meaning must have

been- that it cannot be permanently present in one place- that is,

at rest- nor be capable of changing its place- that is, of moving-

because all places are in the universe, and the universe itself is,

therefore, in no place. Again, if the universe contains in itself

everything that exists, it cannot be similar or dissimilar to any

other thing, because there is, in fact, no other thing with which it

can be compared. If two opposite judgements presuppose a contingent

impossible, or arbitrary condition, both- in spite of their opposition

(which is, however, not properly or really a contradiction)- fall

away; because the condition, which ensured the validity of both, has

itself disappeared.

  If we say: "Everybody has either a good or a bad smell," we have

omitted a third possible judgement- it has no smell at all; and thus

both conflicting statements may be false. If we say: "It is either

good-smelling or not good-smelling (vel suaveolens vel

non-suaveolens)," both judgements are contradictorily opposed; and the

contradictory opposite of the former judgement- some bodies are not

good-smelling- embraces also those bodies which have no smell at

all. In the preceding pair of opposed judgements (per disparata),

the contingent condition of the conception of body (smell) attached to

both conflicting statements, instead of having been omitted in the

latter, which is consequently not the contradictory opposite of the

former.

  If, accordingly, we say: "The world is either infinite in extension,

or it is not infinite (non est infinitus)"; and if the former

proposition is false, its contradictory opposite- the world is not

infinite- must be true. And thus I should deny the existence of an

infinite, without, however affirming the existence of a finite

world. But if we construct our proposition thus: "The world is

either infinite or finite (non-infinite)," both statements may be

false. For, in this case, we consider the world as per se determined

in regard to quantity, and while, in the one judgement, we deny its

infinite and consequently, perhaps, its independent existence; in

the other, we append to the world, regarded as a thing in itself, a

certain determination- that of finitude; and the latter may be false

as well as the former, if the world is not given as a thing in itself,

and thus neither as finite nor as infinite in quantity. This kind of

opposition I may be allowed to term dialectical; that of

contradictories may be called analytical opposition. Thus then, of two

dialectically opposed judgements both may be false, from the fact,

that the one is not a mere contradictory of the other, but actually

enounces more than is requisite for a full and complete contradiction.

  When we regard the two propositions- "The world is infinite in

quantity," and, "The world is finite in quantity," as contradictory

opposites, we are assuming that the world- the complete series of

phenomena- is a thing in itself. For it remains as a permanent

quantity, whether I deny the infinite or the finite regress in the

series of its phenomena. But if we dismiss this assumption- this

transcendental illusion- and deny that it is a thing in itself, the

contradictory opposition is metamorphosed into a merely dialectical

one; and the world, as not existing in itself- independently of the

regressive series of my representations- exists in like manner neither

as a whole which is infinite nor as a whole which is finite in itself.

The universe exists for me only in the empirical regress of the series

of phenomena and not per se. If, then, it is always conditioned, it is

never completely or as a whole; and it is, therefore, not an

unconditioned whole and does not exist as such, either with an

infinite, or with a finite quantity.

  What we have here said of the first cosmological idea- that of the

absolute totality of quantity in phenomena- applies also to the

others. The series of conditions is discoverable only in the

regressive synthesis itself, and not in the phenomenon considered as a

thing in itself- given prior to all regress. Hence I am compelled to

say: "The aggregate of parts in a given phenomenon is in itself

neither finite nor infinite; and these parts are given only in the

regressive synthesis of decomposition- a synthesis which is never

given in absolute completeness, either as finite, or as infinite." The

same is the case with the series of subordinated causes, or of the

conditioned up to the unconditioned and necessary existence, which can

never be regarded as in itself, ind in its totality, either as

finite or as infinite; because, as a series of subordinate

representations, it subsists only in the dynamical regress and

cannot be regarded as existing previously to this regress, or as a

self-subsistent series of things.

  Thus the antinomy of pure reason in its cosmological ideas

disappears. For the above demonstration has established the fact

that it is merely the product of a dialectical and illusory

opposition, which arises from the application of the idea of

absolute totality- admissible only as a condition of things in

themselves- to phenomena, which exist only in our representations,

and- when constituting a series- in a successive regress. This

antinomy of reason may, however, be really profitable to our

speculative interests, not in the way of contributing any dogmatical

addition, but as presenting to us another material support in our

critical investigations. For it furnishes us with an indirect proof of

the transcendental ideality of phenomena, if our minds were not

completely satisfied with the direct proof set forth in the

Trancendental Aesthetic. The proof would proceed in the following

dilemma. If the world is a whole existing in itself, it must be either

finite or infinite. But it is neither finite nor infinite- as has been

shown, on the one side, by the thesis, on the other, by the

antithesis. Therefore the world- the content of all phenomena- is

not a whole existing in itself. It follows that phenomena are nothing,

apart from our representations. And this is what we mean by

transcendental ideality.

  This remark is of some importance. It enables us to see that the

proofs of the fourfold antinomy are not mere sophistries- are not

fallacious, but grounded on the nature of reason, and valid- under the

supposition that phenomena are things in themselves. The opposition of

the judgements which follow makes it evident that a fallacy lay in the

initial supposition, and thus helps us to discover the true

constitution of objects of sense. This transcendental dialectic does

not favour scepticism, although it presents us with a triumphant

demonstration of the advantages of the sceptical method, the great

utility of which is apparent in the antinomy, where the arguments of

reason were allowed to confront each other in undiminished force.

And although the result of these conflicts of reason is not what we

expected- although we have obtained no positive dogmatical addition to

metaphysical science- we have still reaped a great advantage in the

correction of our judgements on these subjects of thought.



     SECTION VIII. Regulative Principle of Pure Reason in relation

                   to the Cosmological Ideas.



  The cosmological principle of totality could not give us any certain

knowledge in regard to the maximum in the series of conditions in

the world of sense, considered as a thing in itself. The actual

regress in the series is the only means of approaching this maximum.

This principle of pure reason, therefore, may still be considered as

valid- not as an axiom enabling us to cogitate totality in the

object as actual, but as a problem for the understanding, which

requires it to institute and to continue, in conformity with the

idea of totality in the mind, the regress in the series of the

conditions of a given conditioned. For in the world of sense, that is,

in space and time, every condition which we discover in our

investigation of phenomena is itself conditioned; because sensuous

objects are not things in themselves (in which case an absolutely

unconditioned might be reached in the progress of cognition), but

are merely empirical representations the conditions of which must

always be found in intuition. The principle of reason is therefore

properly a mere rule- prescribing a regress in the series of

conditions for given phenomena, and prohibiting any pause or rest on

an absolutely unconditioned. It is, therefore, not a principle of

the possibility of experience or of the empirical cognition of

sensuous objects- consequently not a principle of the understanding;

for every experience is confined within certain proper limits

determined by the given intuition. Still less is it a constitutive

principle of reason authorizing us to extend our conception of the

sensuous world beyond all possible experience. It is merely a

principle for the enlargement and extension of experience as far as is

possible for human faculties. It forbids us to consider any

empirical limits as absolute. It is, hence, a principle of reason,

which, as a rule, dictates how we ought to proceed in our empirical

regress, but is unable to anticipate or indicate prior to the

empirical regress what is given in the object itself. I have termed it

for this reason a regulative principle of reason; while the

principle of the absolute totality of the series of conditions, as

existing in itself and given in the object, is a constitutive

cosmological principle. This distinction will at once demonstrate

the falsehood of the constitutive principle, and prevent us from

attributing (by a transcendental subreptio) objective reality to an

idea, which is valid only as a rule.

  In order to understand the proper meaning of this rule of pure

reason, we must notice first that it cannot tell us what the object

is, but only how the empirical regress is to be proceeded with in

order to attain to the complete conception of the object. If it gave

us any information in respect to the former statement, it would be a

constitutive principle- a principle impossible from the nature of pure

reason. It will not therefore enable us to establish any such

conclusions as: "The series of conditions for a given conditioned is

in itself finite." or, "It is infinite." For, in this case, we

should be cogitating in the mere idea of absolute totality, an

object which is not and cannot be given in experience; inasmuch as

we should be attributing a reality objective and independent of the

empirical synthesis, to a series of phenomena. This idea of reason

cannot then be regarded as valid- except as a rule for the

regressive synthesis in the series of conditions, according to which

we must proceed from the conditioned, through all intermediate and

subordinate conditions, up to the unconditioned; although this goal is

unattained and unattainable. For the absolutely unconditioned cannot

be discovered in the sphere of experience.

  We now proceed to determine clearly our notion of a synthesis

which can never be complete. There are two terms commonly employed for

this purpose. These terms are regarded as expressions of different and

distinguishable notions, although the ground of the distinction has

never been clearly exposed. The term employed by the mathematicians is

progressus in infinitum. The philosophers prefer the expression

progressus in indefinitum. Without detaining the reader with an

examination of the reasons for such a distinction, or with remarks

on the right or wrong use of the terms, I shall endeavour clearly to

determine these conceptions, so far as is necessary for the purpose in

this Critique.

  We may, with propriety, say of a straight line, that it may be

produced to infinity. In this case the distinction between a

progressus in infinitum and a progressus in indefinitum is a mere

piece of subtlety. For, although when we say, "Produce a straight

line," it is more correct to say in indefinitum than in infinitum;

because the former means, "Produce it as far as you please," the

second, "You must not cease to produce it"; the expression in

infinitum is, when we are speaking of the power to do it, perfectly

correct, for we can always make it longer if we please- on to

infinity. And this remark holds good in all cases, when we speak of

a progressus, that is, an advancement from the condition to the

conditioned; this possible advancement always proceeds to infinity. We

may proceed from a given pair in the descending line of generation

from father to son, and cogitate a never-ending line of descendants

from it. For in such a case reason does not demand absolute totality

in the series, because it does not presuppose it as a condition and as

given (datum), but merely as conditioned, and as capable of being

given (dabile).

  Very different is the case with the problem: "How far the regress,

which ascends from the given conditioned to the conditions, must

extend"; whether I can say: "It is a regress in infinitum," or only

"in indefinitum"; and whether, for example, setting out from the human

beings at present alive in the world, I may ascend in the series of

their ancestors, in infinitum- mr whether all that can be said is,

that so far as I have proceeded, I have discovered no empirical ground

for considering the series limited, so that I am justified, and

indeed, compelled to search for ancestors still further back, although

I am not obliged by the idea of reason to presuppose them.

  My answer to this question is: "If the series is given in

empirical intuition as a whole, the regress in the series of its

internal conditions proceeds in infinitum; but, if only one member

of the series is given, from which the regress is to proceed to

absolute totality, the regress is possible only in indefinitum." For

example, the division of a portion of matter given within certain

limits- of a body, that is- proceeds in infinitum. For, as the

condition of this whole is its part, and the condition of the part a

part of the part, and so on, and as in this regress of decomposition

an unconditioned indivisible member of the series of conditions is not

to be found; there are no reasons or grounds in experience for

stopping in the division, but, on the contrary, the more remote

members of the division are actually and empirically given prior to

this division. That is to say, the division proceeds to infinity. On

the other hand, the series of ancestors of any given human being is

not given, in its absolute totality, in any experience, and yet the

regress proceeds from every genealogical member of this series to

one still higher, and does not meet with any empirical limit

presenting an absolutely unconditioned member of the series. But as

the members of such a series are not contained in the empirical

intuition of the whole, prior to the regress, this regress does not

proceed to infinity, but only in indefinitum, that is, we are called

upon to discover other and higher members, which are themselves always

conditioned.

  In neither case- the regressus in infinitum, nor the regressus in

indefinitum, is the series of conditions to be considered as

actually infinite in the object itself. This might be true of things

in themselves, but it cannot be asserted of phenomena, which, as

conditions of each other, are only given in the empirical regress

itself. Hence, the question no longer is, "What is the quantity of

this series of conditions in itself- is it finite or infinite?" for it

is nothing in itself; but, "How is the empirical regress to be

commenced, and how far ought we to proceed with it?" And here a signal

distinction in the application of this rule becomes apparent. If the

whole is given empirically, it is possible to recede in the series

of its internal conditions to infinity. But if the whole is not given,

and can only be given by and through the empirical regress, I can only

say: "It is possible to infinity, to proceed to still higher

conditions in the series." In the first case, I am justified in

asserting that more members are empirically given in the object than I

attain to in the regress (of decomposition). In the second case, I

am justified only in saying, that I can always proceed further in

the regress, because no member of the series. is given as absolutely

conditioned, and thus a higher member is possible, and an inquiry with

regard to it is necessary. In the one case it is necessary to find

other members of the series, in the other it is necessary to inquire

for others, inasmuch as experience presents no absolute limitation

of the regress. For, either you do not possess a perception which

absolutely limits your empirical regress, and in this case the regress

cannot be regarded as complete; or, you do possess such a limitative

perception, in which case it is not a part of your series (for that

which limits must be distinct from that which is limited by it), and

it is incumbent you to continue your regress up to this condition, and

so on.

  These remarks will be placed in their proper light by their

application in the following section.



    SECTION IX. Of the Empirical Use of the Regulative Principle

         of Reason with regard to the Cosmological Ideas.



  We have shown that no transcendental use can be made either of the

conceptions of reason or of understanding. We have shown, likewise,

that the demand of absolute totality in the series of conditions in

the world of sense arises from a transcendental employment of

reason, resting on the opinion that phenomena are to be regarded as

things in themselves. It follows that we are not required to answer

the question respecting the absolute quantity of a series- whether

it is in itself limited or unlimited. We are only called upon to

determine how far we must proceed in the empirical regress from

condition to condition, in order to discover, in conformity with the

rule of reason, a full and correct answer to the questions proposed by

reason itself.

  This principle of reason is hence valid only as a rule for the

extension of a possible experience- its invalidity as a principle

constitutive of phenomena in themselves having been sufficiently

demonstrated. And thus, too, the antinomial conflict of reason with

itself is completely put an end to; inasmuch as we have not only

presented a critical solution of the fallacy lurking in the opposite

statements of reason, but have shown the true meaning of the ideas

which gave rise to these statements. The dialectical principle of

reason has, therefore, been changed into a doctrinal principle. But in

fact, if this principle, in the subjective signification which we have

shown to be its only true sense, may be guaranteed as a principle of

the unceasing extension of the employment of our understanding, its

influence and value are just as great as if it were an axiom for the a

priori determination of objects. For such an axiom could not exert a

stronger influence on the extension and rectification of our

knowledge, otherwise than by procuring for the principles of the

understanding the most widely expanded employment in the field of

experience.



  I. Solution of the Cosmological Idea of the Totality of the

          Composition of Phenomena in the Universe.



  Here, as well as in the case of the other cosmological problems, the

ground of the regulative principle of reason is the proposition that

in our empirical regress no experience of an absolute limit, and

consequently no experience of a condition, which is itself

absolutely unconditioned, is discoverable. And the truth of this

proposition itself rests upon the consideration that such an

experience must represent to us phenomena as limited by nothing or the

mere void, on which our continued regress by means of perception

must abut- which is impossible.

  Now this proposition, which declares that every condition attained

in the empirical regress must itself be considered empirically

conditioned, contains the rule in terminis, which requires me, to

whatever extent I may have proceeded in the ascending series, always

to look for some higher member in the series- whether this member is

to become known to me through experience, or not.

  Nothing further is necessary, then, for the solution of the first

cosmological problem, than to decide, whether, in the regress to the

unconditioned quantity of the universe (as regards space and time),

this never limited ascent ought to be called a regressus in

infinitum or indefinitum.

  The general representation which we form in our minds of the

series of all past states or conditions of the world, or of all the

things which at present exist in it, is itself nothing more than a

possible empirical regress, which is cogitated- although in an

undetermined manner- in the mind, and which gives rise to the

conception of a series of conditions for a given object.* Now I have a

conception of the universe, but not an intuition- that is, not an

intuition of it as a whole. Thus I cannot infer the magnitude of the

regress from the quantity or magnitude of the world, and determine the

former by means of the latter; on the contrary, I must first of all

form a conception of the quantity or magnitude of the world from the

magnitude of the empirical regress. But of this regress I know nothing

more than that I ought to proceed from every given member of the

series of conditions to one still higher. But the quantity of the

universe is not thereby determined, and we cannot affirm that this

regress proceeds in infinitum. Such an affirmation would anticipate

the members of the series which have not yet been reached, and

represent the number of them as beyond the grasp of any empirical

synthesis; it would consequently determine the cosmical quantity prior

to the regress (although only in a negative manner)- which is

impossible. For the world is not given in its totality in any

intuition: consequently, its quantity cannot be given prior to the

regress. It follows that we are unable to make any declaration

respecting the cosmical quantity in itself- not even that the

regress in it is a regress in infinitum; we must only endeavour to

attain to a conception of the quantity of the universe, in

conformity with the rule which determines the empirical regress in it.

But this rule merely requires us never to admit an absolute limit to

our series- how far soever we may have proceeded in it, but always, on

the contrary, to subordinate every phenomenon to some other as its

condition, and consequently to proceed to this higher phenomenon. Such

a regress is, therefore, the regressus in indefinitum, which, as not

determining a quantity in the object, is clearly distinguishable

from the regressus in infinitum.



  *The cosmical series can neither be greater nor smaller than the

possible empirical regress, upon which its conception is based. And as

this regress cannot be a determinate infinite regress, still less a

determinate finite (absolutely limited), it is evident that we

cannot regard the world as either finite or infinite, because the

regress, which gives us the representation of the world, is neither

finite nor infinite.



  It follows from what we have said that we are not justified in

declaring the world to be infinite in space, or as regards past

time. For this conception of an infinite given quantity is

empirical; but we cannot apply the conception of an infinite

quantity to the world as an object of the senses. I cannot say, "The

regress from a given perception to everything limited either in

space or time, proceeds in infinitum," for this presupposes an

infinite cosmical quantity; neither can I say, "It is finite," for

an absolute limit is likewise impossible in experience. It follows

that I am not entitled to make any assertion at all respecting the

whole object of experience- the world of sense; I must limit my

declarations to the rule according to which experience or empirical

knowledge is to be attained.

  To the question, therefore, respecting the cosmical quantity, the

first and negative answer is: "The world has no beginning in time, and

no absolute limit in space."

  For, in the contrary case, it would be limited by a void time on the

one hand, and by a void space on the other. Now, since the world, as a

phenomenon, cannot be thus limited in itself for a phenomenon is not a

thing in itself; it must be possible for us to have a perception of

this limitation by a void time and a void space. But such a

perception- such an experience is impossible; because it has no

content. Consequently, an absolute cosmical limit is empirically,

and therefore absolutely, impossible.*



  *The reader will remark that the proof presented above is very

different from the dogmatical demonstration given in the antithesis of

the first antinomy. In that demonstration, it was taken for granted

that the world is a thing in itself- given in its totality prior to

all regress, and a determined position in space and time was denied to

it- if it was not considered as occupying all time and all space.

Hence our conclusion differed from that given above; for we inferred

in the antithesis the actual infinity of the world.



  From this follows the affirmative answer: "The regress in the series

of phenomena- as a determination of the cosmical quantity, proceeds in

indefinitum." This is equivalent to saying: "The world of sense has no

absolute quantity, but the empirical regress (through which alone

the world of sense is presented to us on the side of its conditions)

rests upon a rule, which requires it to proceed from every member of

the series, as conditioned, to one still more remote (whether

through personal experience, or by means of history, or the chain of

cause and effect), and not to cease at any point in this extension

of the possible empirical employment of the understanding." And this

is the proper and only use which reason can make of its principles.

  The above rule does not prescribe an unceasing regress in one kind

of phenomena. It does not, for example, forbid us, in our ascent

from an individual human being through the line of his ancestors, to

expect that we shall discover at some point of the regress a

primeval pair, or to admit, in the series of heavenly bodies, a sun at

the farthest possible distance from some centre. All that it demands

is a perpetual progress from phenomena to phenomena, even although

an actual perception is not presented by them (as in the case of our

perceptions being so weak as that we are unable to become conscious of

them), since they, nevertheless, belong to possible experience.

  Every beginning is in time, and all limits to extension are in

space. But space and time are in the world of sense. Consequently

phenomena in the world are conditionally limited, but the world itself

is not limited, either conditionally or unconditionally.

  For this reason, and because neither the world nor the cosmical

series of conditions to a given conditioned can be completely given,

our conception of the cosmical quantity is given only in and through

the regress and not prior to it- in a collective intuition. But the

regress itself is really nothing more than the determining of the

cosmical quantity, and cannot therefore give us any determined

conception of it- still less a conception of a quantity which is, in

relation to a certain standard, infinite. The regress does not,

therefore, proceed to infinity (an infinity given), but only to an

indefinite extent, for or the of presenting to us a quantity- realized

only in and through the regress itself.



    II. Solution of the Cosmological Idea of the Totality of

        the Division of a Whole given in Intuition.



  When I divide a whole which is given in intuition, I proceed from

a conditioned to its conditions. The division of the parts of the

whole (subdivisio or decompositio) is a regress in the series of these

conditions. The absolute totality of this series would be actually

attained and given to the mind, if the regress could arrive at

simple parts. But if all the parts in a continuous decomposition are

themselves divisible, the division, that is to say, the regress,

proceeds from the conditioned to its conditions in infinitum;

because the conditions (the parts) are themselves contained in the

conditioned, and, as the latter is given in a limited intuition, the

former are all given along with it. This regress cannot, therefore, be

called a regressus in indefinitum, as happened in the case of the

preceding cosmological idea, the regress in which proceeded from the

conditioned to the conditions not given contemporaneously and along

with it, but discoverable only through the empirical regress. We are

not, however, entitled to affirm of a whole of this kind, which is

divisible in infinitum, that it consists of an infinite number of

parts. For, although all the parts are contained in the intuition of

the whole, the whole division is not contained therein. The division

is contained only in the progressing decomposition- in the regress

itself, which is the condition of the possibility and actuality of the

series. Now, as this regress is infinite, all the members (parts) to

which it attains must be contained in the given whole as an aggregate.

But the complete series of division is not contained therein. For this

series, being infinite in succession and always incomplete, cannot

represent an infinite number of members, and still less a

composition of these members into a whole.

  To apply this remark to space. Every limited part of space presented

to intuition is a whole, the parts of which are always spaces- to

whatever extent subdivided. Every limited space is hence divisible

to infinity.

  Let us again apply the remark to an external phenomenon enclosed

in limits, that is, a body. The divisibility of a body rests upon

the divisibility of space, which is the condition of the possibility

of the body as an extended whole. A body is consequently divisible

to infinity, though it does not, for that reason, consist of an

infinite number of parts.

  It certainly seems that, as a body must be cogitated as substance in

space, the law of divisibility would not be applicable to it as

substance. For we may and ought to grant, in the case of space, that

division or decomposition, to any extent, never can utterly annihilate

composition (that is to say, the smallest part of space must still

consist of spaces); otherwise space would entirely cease to exist-

which is impossible. But, the assertion on the other band that when

all composition in matter is annihilated in thought, nothing

remains, does not seem to harmonize with the conception of

substance, which must be properly the subject of all composition and

must remain, even after the conjunction of its attributes in space-

which constituted a body- is annihilated in thought. But this is not

the case with substance in the phenomenal world, which is not a

thing in itself cogitated by the pure category. Phenomenal substance

is not an absolute subject; it is merely a permanent sensuous image,

and nothing more than an intuition, in which the unconditioned is

not to be found.

  But, although this rule of progress to infinity is legitimate and

applicable to the subdivision of a phenomenon, as a mere occupation or

filling of space, it is not applicable to a whole consisting of a

number of distinct parts and constituting a quantum discretum- that is

to say, an organized body. It cannot be admitted that every part in an

organized whole is itself organized, and that, in analysing it to

infinity, we must always meet with organized parts; although we may

allow that the parts of the matter which we decompose in infinitum,

may be organized. For the infinity of the division of a phenomenon

in space rests altogether on the fact that the divisibility of a

phenomenon is given only in and through this infinity, that is, an

undetermined number of parts is given, while the parts themselves

are given and determined only in and through the subdivision; in a

word, the infinity of the division necessarily presupposes that the

whole is not already divided in se. Hence our division determines a

number of parts in the whole- a number which extends just as far as

the actual regress in the division; while, on the other hand, the very

notion of a body organized to infinity represents the whole as already

and in itself divided. We expect, therefore, to find in it a

determinate, but at the same time, infinite, number of parts- which is

self-contradictory. For we should thus have a whole containing a

series of members which could not be completed in any regress- which

is infinite, and at the same time complete in an organized

composite. Infinite divisibility is applicable only to a quantum

continuum, and is based entirely on the infinite divisibility of

space, But in a quantum discretum the multitude of parts or units is

always determined, and hence always equal to some number. To what

extent a body may be organized, experience alone can inform us; and

although, so far as our experience of this or that body has

extended, we may not have discovered any inorganic part, such parts

must exist in possible experience. But how far the transcendental

division of a phenomenon must extend, we cannot know from

experience- it is a question which experience cannot answer; it is

answered only by the principle of reason which forbids us to

consider the empirical regress, in the analysis of extended body, as

ever absolutely complete.



     Concluding Remark on the Solution of the Transcendental

          Mathematical Ideas- and Introductory to the

               Solution of the Dynamical Ideas.



  We presented the antinomy of pure reason in a tabular form, and we

endeavoured to show the ground of this self-contradiction on the

part of reason, and the only means of bringing it to a conclusion-

znamely, by declaring both contradictory statements to be false. We

represented in these antinomies the conditions of phenomena as

belonging to the conditioned according to relations of space and time-

which is the usual supposition of the common understanding. In this

respect, all dialectical representations of totality, in the series of

conditions to a given conditioned, were perfectly homogeneous. The

condition was always a member of the series along with the

conditioned, and thus the homogeneity of the whole series was assured.

In this case the regress could never be cogitated as complete; or,

if this was the case, a member really conditioned was falsely regarded

as a primal member, consequently as unconditioned. In such an

antinomy, therefore, we did not consider the object, that is, the

conditioned, but the series of conditions belonging to the object, and

the magnitude of that series. And thus arose the difficulty- a

difficulty not to be settled by any decision regarding the claims of

the two parties, but simply by cutting the knot- by declaring the

series proposed by reason to be either too long or too short for the

understanding, which could in neither case make its conceptions

adequate with the ideas.

  But we have overlooked, up to this point, an essential difference

existing between the conceptions of the understanding which reason

endeavours to raise to the rank of ideas- two of these indicating a

mathematical, and two a dynamical synthesis of phenomena. Hitherto, it

was necessary to signalize this distinction; for, just as in our

general representation of all transcendental ideas, we considered them

under phenomenal conditions, so, in the two mathematical ideas, our

discussion is concerned solely with an object in the world of

phenomena. But as we are now about to proceed to the consideration

of the dynamical conceptions of the understanding, and their

adequateness with ideas, we must not lose sight of this distinction.

We shall find that it opens up to us an entirely new view of the

conflict in which reason is involved. For, while in the first two

antinomies, both parties were dismissed, on the ground of having

advanced statements based upon false hypothesis; in the present case

the hope appears of discovering a hypothesis which may be consistent

with the demands of reason, and, the judge completing the statement of

the grounds of claim, which both parties had left in an unsatisfactory

state, the question may be settled on its own merits, not by

dismissing the claimants, but by a comparison of the arguments on both

sides. If we consider merely their extension, and whether they are

adequate with ideas, the series of conditions may be regarded as all

homogeneous. But the conception of the understanding which lies at the

basis of these ideas, contains either a synthesis of the homogeneous

(presupposed in every quantity- in its composition as well as in its

division) or of the heterogeneous, which is the case in the

dynamical synthesis of cause and effect, as well as of the necessary

and the contingent.

  Thus it happens that in the mathematical series of phenomena no

other than a sensuous condition is admissible- a condition which is

itself a member of the series; while the dynamical series of

sensuous conditions admits a heterogeneous condition, which is not a

member of the series, but, as purely intelligible, lies out of and

beyond it. And thus reason is satisfied, and an unconditioned placed

at the head of the series of phenomena, without introducing

confusion into or discontinuing it, contrary to the principles of

the understanding.

  Now, from the fact that the dynamical ideas admit a condition of

phenomena which does not form a part of the series of phenomena,

arises a result which we should not have expected from an antinomy. In

former cases, the result was that both contradictory dialectical

statements were declared to be false. In the present case, we find the

conditioned in the dynamical series connected with an empirically

unconditioned, but non-sensuous condition; and thus satisfaction is

done to the understanding on the one hand and to the reason on the

other.* While, moreover, the dialectical arguments for unconditioned

totality in mere phenomena fall to the ground, both propositions of

reason may be shown to be true in their proper signification. This

could not happen in the case of the cosmological ideas which

demanded a mathematically unconditioned unity; for no condition

could be placed at the head of the series of phenomena, except one

which was itself a phenomenon and consequently a member of the series.



  *For the understanding cannot admit among phenomena a condition

which is itself empirically unconditioned. But if it is possible to

cogitate an intelligible condition- one which is not a member of the

series of phenomena- for a conditioned phenomenon, without breaking

the series of empirical conditions, such a condition may be admissible

as empirically unconditioned, and the empirical regress continue

regular, unceasing, and intact.



    III. Solution of the Cosmological Idea of the Totality of

       the Deduction of Cosmical Events from their Causes.



  There are only two modes of causality cogitable- the causality of

nature or of freedom. The first is the conjunction of a particular

state with another preceding it in the world of sense, the former

following the latter by virtue of a law. Now, as the causality of

phenomena is subject to conditions of time, and the preceding state,

if it had always existed, could not have produced an effect which

would make its first appearance at a particular time, the causality of

a cause must itself be an effect- must itself have begun to be, and

therefore, according to the principle of the understanding, itself

requires a cause.

  We must understand, on the contrary, by the term freedom, in the

cosmological sense, a faculty of the spontaneous origination of a

state; the causality of which, therefore, is not subordinated to

another cause determining it in time. Freedom is in this sense a

pure transcendental idea, which, in the first place, contains no

empirical element; the object of which, in the second place, cannot be

given or determined in any experience, because it is a universal law

of the very possibility of experience, that everything which happens

must have a cause, that consequently the causality of a cause, being

itself something that has happened, must also have a cause. In this

view of the case, the whole field of experience, how far soever it may

extend, contains nothing that is not subject to the laws of nature.

But, as we cannot by this means attain to an absolute totality of

conditions in reference to the series of causes and effects, reason

creates the idea of a spontaneity, which can begin to act of itself,

and without any external cause determining it to action, according

to the natural law of causality.

  It is especially remarkable that the practical conception of freedom

is based upon the transcendental idea, and that the question of the

possibility of the former is difficult only as it involves the

consideration of the truth of the latter. Freedom, in the practical

sense, is the independence of the will of coercion by sensuous

impulses. A will is sensuous, in so far as it is pathologically

affected (by sensuous impulses); it is termed animal (arbitrium

brutum), when it is pathologically necessitated. The human will is

certainly an arbitrium sensitivum, not brutum, but liberum; because

sensuousness does not necessitate its action, a faculty existing in

man of self-determination, independently of all sensuous coercion.

  It is plain that, if all causality in the world of sense were

natural- and natural only- every event would be determined by

another according to necessary laws, and that, consequently,

phenomena, in so far as they determine the will, must necessitate

every action as a natural effect from themselves; and thus all

practical freedom would fall to the ground with the transcendental

idea. For the latter presupposes that although a certain thing has not

happened, it ought to have happened, and that, consequently, its

phenomenal cause was not so powerful and determinative as to exclude

the causality of our will- a causality capable of producing effects

independently of and even in opposition to the power of natural

causes, and capable, consequently, of spontaneously originating a

series of events.

  Here, too, we find it to be the case, as we generally found in the

self-contradictions and perplexities of a reason which strives to pass

the bounds of possible experience, that the problem is properly not

physiological, but transcendental. The question of the possibility

of freedom does indeed concern psychology; but, as it rests upon

dialectical arguments of pure reason, its solution must engage the

attention of transcendental philosophy. Before attempting this

solution, a task which transcendental philosophy cannot decline, it

will be advisable to make a remark with regard to its procedure in the

settlement of the question.

  If phenomena were things in themselves, and time and space forms

of the existence of things, condition and conditioned would always

be members of the same series; and thus would arise in the present

case the antinomy common to all transcendental ideas- that their

series is either too great or too small for the understanding. The

dynamical ideas, which we are about to discuss in this and the

following section, possess the peculiarity of relating to an object,

not considered as a quantity, but as an existence; and thus, in the

discussion of the present question, we may make abstraction of the

quantity of the series of conditions, and consider merely the

dynamical relation of the condition to the conditioned. The

question, then, suggests itself, whether freedom is possible; and,

if it is, whether it can consist with the universality of the

natural law of causality; and, consequently, whether we enounce a

proper disjunctive proposition when we say: "Every effect must have

its origin either in nature or in freedom," or whether both cannot

exist together in the same event in different relations. The principle

of an unbroken connection between all events in the phenomenal

world, in accordance with the unchangeable laws of nature, is a

well-established principle of transcendental analytic which admits

of no exception. The question, therefore, is: "Whether an effect,

determined according to the laws of nature, can at the same time be

produced by a free agent, or whether freedom and nature mutually

exclude each other?" And here, the common but fallacious hypothesis of

the absolute reality of phenomena manifests its injurious influence in

embarrassing the procedure of reason. For if phenomena are things in

themselves, freedom is impossible. In this case, nature is the

complete and all-sufficient cause of every event; and condition and

conditioned, cause and effect are contained in the same series, and

necessitated by the same law. If, on the contrary, phenomena are

held to be, as they are in fact, nothing more than mere

representations, connected with each other in accordance with

empirical laws, they must have a ground which is not phenomenal. But

the causality of such an intelligible cause is not determined or

determinable by phenomena; although its effects, as phenomena, must be

determined by other phenomenal existences. This cause and its

causality exist therefore out of and apart from the series of

phenomena; while its effects do exist and are discoverable in the

series of empirical conditions. Such an effect may therefore be

considered to be free in relation to its intelligible cause, and

necessary in relation to the phenomena from which it is a necessary

consequence- a distinction which, stated in this perfectly general and

abstract manner, must appear in the highest degree subtle and obscure.

The sequel will explain. It is sufficient, at present, to remark that,

as the complete and unbroken connection of phenomena is an unalterable

law of nature, freedom is impossible- on the supposition that

phenomena are absolutely real. Hence those philosophers who adhere

to the common opinion on this subject can never succeed in reconciling

the ideas of nature and freedom.



     Possibility of Freedom in Harmony with the Universal Law

                     of Natural Necessity.



  That element in a sensuous object which is not itself sensuous, I

may be allowed to term intelligible. If, accordingly, an object

which must be regarded as a sensuous phenomenon possesses a faculty

which is not an object of sensuous intuition, but by means of which it

is capable of being the cause of phenomena, the causality of an object

or existence of this kind may be regarded from two different points of

view. It may be considered to be intelligible, as regards its

action- the action of a thing which is a thing in itself, and

sensuous, as regards its effects- the effects of a phenomenon

belonging to the sensuous world. We should accordingly, have to form

both an empirical and an intellectual conception of the causality of

such a faculty or power- both, however, having reference to the same

effect. This twofold manner of cogitating a power residing in a

sensuous object does not run counter to any of the conceptions which

we ought to form of the world of phenomena or of a possible

experience. Phenomena- not being things in themselves- must have a

transcendental object as a foundation, which determines them as mere

representations; and there seems to be no reason why we should not

ascribe to this transcendental object, in addition to the property

of self-phenomenization, a causality whose effects are to be met

with in the world of phenomena, although it is not itself a

phenomenon. But every effective cause must possess a character, that

is to say, a law of its causality, without which it would cease to

be a cause. In the above case, then, every sensuous object would

possess an empirical character, which guaranteed that its actions,

as phenomena, stand in complete and harmonious connection, conformably

to unvarying natural laws, with all other phenomena, and can be

deduced from these, as conditions, and that they do thus, in

connection with these, constitute a series in the order of nature.

This sensuous object must, in the second place, possess an

intelligible character, which guarantees it to be the cause of those

actions, as phenomena, although it is not itself a phenomenon nor

subordinate to the conditions of the world of sense. The former may be

termed the character of the thing as a phenomenon, the latter the

character of the thing as a thing in itself.

  Now this active subject would, in its character of intelligible

subject, be subordinate to no conditions of time, for time is only a

condition of phenomena, and not of things in themselves. No action

would begin or cease to be in this subject; it would consequently be

free from the law of all determination of time- the law of change,

namely, that everything which happens must have a cause in the

phenomena of a preceding state. In one word, the causality of the

subject, in so far as it is intelligible, would not form part of the

series of empirical conditions which determine and necessitate an

event in the world of sense. Again, this intelligible character of a

thing cannot be immediately cognized, because we can perceive

nothing but phenomena, but it must be capable of being cogitated in

harmony with the empirical character; for we always find ourselves

compelled to place, in thought, a transcendental object at the basis

of phenomena although we can never know what this object is in itself.

  In virtue of its empirical character, this subject would at the same

time be subordinate to all the empirical laws of causality, and, as

a phenomenon and member of the sensuous world, its effects would

have to be accounted for by a reference to preceding phenomena.

Eternal phenomena must be capable of influencing it; and its

actions, in accordance with natural laws, must explain to us how its

empirical character, that is, the law of its causality, is to be

cognized in and by means of experience. In a word, all requisites

for a complete and necessary determination of these actions must be

presented to us by experience.

  In virtue of its intelligible character, on the other hand (although

we possess only a general conception of this character), the subject

must be regarded as free from all sensuous influences, and from all

phenomenal determination. Moreover, as nothing happens in this

subject- for it is a noumenon, and there does not consequently exist

in it any change, demanding the dynamical determination of time, and

for the same reason no connection with phenomena as causes- this

active existence must in its actions be free from and independent of

natural necessity, for or necessity exists only in the world of

phenomena. It would be quite correct to say that it originates or

begins its effects in the world of sense from itself, although the

action productive of these effects does not begin in itself. We should

not be in this case affirming that these sensuous effects began to

exist of themselves, because they are always determined by prior

empirical conditions- by virtue of the empirical character, which is

the phenomenon of the intelligible character- and are possible only as

constituting a continuation of the series of natural causes. And

thus nature and freedom, each in the complete and absolute

signification of these terms, can exist, without contradiction or

disagreement, in the same action to



    Exposition of the Cosmological Idea of Freedom in Harmony

        with the Universal Law of Natural Necessity.



  I have thought it advisable to lay before the reader at first merely

a sketch of the solution of this transcendental problem, in order to

enable him to form with greater ease a clear conception of the

course which reason must adopt in the solution. I shall now proceed to

exhibit the several momenta of this solution, and to consider them

in their order.

  The natural law that everything which happens must have a cause,

that the causality of this cause, that is, the action of the cause

(which cannot always have existed, but must be itself an event, for it

precedes in time some effect which it has originated), must have

itself a phenomenal cause, by which it is determined and, and,

consequently, all events are empirically determined in an order of

nature- this law, I say, which lies at the foundation of the

possibility of experience, and of a connected system of phenomena or

nature is a law of the understanding, from which no departure, and

to which no exception, can be admitted. For to except even a single

phenomenon from its operation is to exclude it from the sphere of

possible experience and thus to admit it to be a mere fiction of

thought or phantom of the brain.

  Thus we are obliged to acknowledge the existence of a chain of

causes, in which, however, absolute totality cannot be found. But we

need not detain ourselves with this question, for it has already

been sufficiently answered in our discussion of the antinomies into

which reason falls, when it attempts to reach the unconditioned in the

series of phenomena. If we permit ourselves to be deceived by the

illusion of transcendental idealism, we shall find that neither nature

nor freedom exists. Now the question is: "Whether, admitting the

existence of natural necessity in the world of phenomena, it is

possible to consider an effect as at the same time an effect of nature

and an effect of freedom- or, whether these two modes of causality are

contradictory and incompatible?"

  No phenomenal cause can absolutely and of itself begin a series.

Every action, in so far as it is productive of an event, is itself

an event or occurrence, and presupposes another preceding state, in

which its cause existed. Thus everything that happens is but a

continuation of a series, and an absolute beginning is impossible in

the sensuous world. The actions of natural causes are, accordingly,

themselves effects, and presuppose causes preceding them in time. A

primal action which forms an absolute beginning, is beyond the

causal power of phenomena.

  Now, is it absolutely necessary that, granting that all effects

are phenomena, the causality of the cause of these effects must also

be a phenomenon and belong to the empirical world? Is it not rather

possible that, although every effect in the phenomenal world must be

connected with an empirical cause, according to the universal law of

nature, this empirical causality may be itself the effect of a

non-empirical and intelligible causality- its connection with

natural causes remaining nevertheless intact? Such a causality would

be considered, in reference to phenomena, as the primal action of a

cause, which is in so far, therefore, not phenomenal, but, by reason

of this faculty or power, intelligible; although it must, at the

same time, as a link in the chain of nature, be regarded as

belonging to the sensuous world.

  A belief in the reciprocal causality of phenomena is necessary, if

we are required to look for and to present the natural conditions of

natural events, that is to say, their causes. This being admitted as

unexceptionably valid, the requirements of the understanding, which

recognizes nothing but nature in the region of phenomena, are

satisfied, and our physical explanations of physical phenomena may

proceed in their regular course, without hindrance and without

opposition. But it is no stumbling-block in the way, even assuming the

idea to be a pure fiction, to admit that there are some natural causes

in the possession of a faculty which is not empirical, but

intelligible, inasmuch as it is not determined to action by

empirical conditions, but purely and solely upon grounds brought

forward by the understanding- this action being still, when the

cause is phenomenized, in perfect accordance with the laws of

empirical causality. Thus the acting subject, as a causal

phenomenon, would continue to preserve a complete connection with

nature and natural conditions; and the phenomenon only of the

subject (with all its phenomenal causality) would contain certain

conditions, which, if we ascend from the empirical to the

transcendental object, must necessarily be regarded as intelligible.

For, if we attend, in our inquiries with regard to causes in the world

of phenomena, to the directions of nature alone, we need not trouble

ourselves about the relation in which the transcendental subject,

which is completely unknown to us, stands to these phenomena and their

connection in nature. The intelligible ground of phenomena in this

subject does not concern empirical questions. It has to do only with

pure thought; and, although the effects of this thought and action

of the pure understanding are discoverable in phenomena, these

phenomena must nevertheless be capable of a full and complete

explanation, upon purely physical grounds and in accordance with

natural laws. And in this case we attend solely to their empirical and

omit all consideration of their intelligible character (which is the

transcendental cause of the former) as completely unknown, except in

so far as it is exhibited by the latter as its empirical symbol. Now

let us apply this to experience. Man is a phenomenon of the sensuous

world and, at the same time, therefore, a natural cause, the causality

of which must be regulated by empirical laws. As such, he must possess

an empirical character, like all other natural phenomena. We remark

this empirical character in his actions, which reveal the presence

of certain powers and faculties. If we consider inanimate or merely

animal nature, we can discover no reason for ascribing to ourselves

any other than a faculty which is determined in a purely sensuous

manner. But man, to whom nature reveals herself only through sense,

cognizes himself not only by his senses, but also through pure

apperception; and this in actions and internal determinations, which

he cannot regard as sensuous impressions. He is thus to himself, on

the one hand, a phenomenon, but on the other hand, in respect of

certain faculties, a purely intelligible object- intelligible, because

its action cannot be ascribed to sensuous receptivity. These faculties

are understanding and reason. The latter, especially, is in a peculiar

manner distinct from all empirically-conditioned faculties, for it

employs ideas alone in the consideration of its objects, and by

means of these determines the understanding, which then proceeds to

make an empirical use of its own conceptions, which, like the ideas of

reason, are pure and non-empirical.

  That reason possesses the faculty of causality, or that at least

we are compelled so to represent it, is evident from the

imperatives, which in the sphere of the practical we impose on many of

our executive powers. The words I ought express a species of

necessity, and imply a connection with grounds which nature does not

and cannot present to the mind of man. Understanding knows nothing

in nature but that which is, or has been, or will be. It would be

absurd to say that anything in nature ought to be other than it is

in the relations of time in which it stands; indeed, the ought, when

we consider merely the course of nature, bas neither application nor

meaning. The question, "What ought to happen in the sphere of nature?"

is just as absurd as the question, "What ought to be the properties of

a circle?" All that we are entitled to ask is, "What takes place in

nature?" or, in the latter case, "What are the properties of a

circle?"

  But the idea of an ought or of duty indicates a possible action, the

ground of which is a pure conception; while the ground of a merely

natural action is, on the contrary, always a phenomenon. This action

must certainly be possible under physical conditions, if it is

prescribed by the moral imperative ought; but these physical or

natural conditions do not concern the determination of the will

itself, they relate to its effects alone, and the consequences of

the effect in the world of phenomena. Whatever number of motives

nature may present to my will, whatever sensuous impulses- the moral

ought it is beyond their power to produce. They may produce a

volition, which, so far from being necessary, is always conditioned- a

volition to which the ought enunciated by reason, sets an aim and a

standard, gives permission or prohibition. Be the object what it

may, purely sensuous- as pleasure, or presented by pure reason- as

good, reason will not yield to grounds which have an empirical origin.

Reason will not follow the order of things presented by experience,

but, with perfect spontaneity, rearranges them according to ideas,

with which it compels empirical conditions to agree. It declares, in

the name of these ideas, certain actions to be necessary which

nevertheless have not taken place and which perhaps never will take

place; and yet presupposes that it possesses the faculty of

causality in relation to these actions. For, in the absence of this

supposition, it could not expect its ideas to produce certain

effects in the world of experience.

  Now, let us stop here and admit it to be at least possible that

reason does stand in a really causal relation to phenomena. In this

case it must- pure reason as it is- exhibit an empirical character.

For every cause supposes a rule, according to which certain

phenomena follow as effects from the cause, and every rule requires

uniformity in these effects; and this is the proper ground of the

conception of a cause- as a faculty or power. Now this conception

(of a cause) may be termed the empirical character of reason; and this

character is a permanent one, while the effects produced appear, in

conformity with the various conditions which accompany and partly

limit them, in various forms.

  Thus the volition of every man has an empirical character, which

is nothing more than the causality of his reason, in so far as its

effects in the phenomenal world manifest the presence of a rule,

according to which we are enabled to examine, in their several kinds

and degrees, the actions of this causality and the rational grounds

for these actions, and in this way to decide upon the subjective

principles of the volition. Now we learn what this empirical character

is only from phenomenal effects, and from the rule of these which is

presented by experience; and for this reason all the actions of man in

the world of phenomena are determined by his empirical character,

and the co-operative causes of nature. If, then, we could

investigate all the phenomena of human volition to their lowest

foundation in the mind, there would be no action which we could not

anticipate with certainty, and recognize to be absolutely necessary

from its preceding conditions. So far as relates to this empirical

character, therefore, there can be no freedom; and it is only in the

light of this character that we can consider the human will, when we

confine ourselves to simple observation and, as is the case in

anthropology, institute a physiological investigation of the motive

causes of human actions.

  But when we consider the same actions in relation to reason- not for

the purpose of explaining their origin, that is, in relation to

speculative reason, but to practical reason, as the producing cause of

these actions- we shall discover a rule and an order very different

from those of nature and experience. For the declaration of this

mental faculty may be that what has and could not but take place in

the course of nature, ought not to have taken place. Sometimes, too,

we discover, or believe that we discover, that the ideas of reason did

actually stand in a causal relation to certain actions of man; and

that these actions have taken place because they were determined,

not by empirical causes, but by the act of the will upon grounds of

reason.

  Now, granting that reason stands in a causal relation to

phenomena; can an action of reason be called free, when we know

that, sensuously, in its empirical character, it is completely

determined and absolutely necessary? But this empirical character is

itself determined by the intelligible character. The latter we

cannot cognize; we can only indicate it by means of phenomena, which

enable us to have an immediate cognition only of the empirical

character.* An action, then, in so far as it is to be ascribed to an

intelligible cause, does not result from it in accordance with

empirical laws. That is to say, not the conditions of pure reason, but

only their effects in the internal sense, precede the act. Pure

reason, as a purely intelligible faculty, is not subject to the

conditions of time. The causality of reason in its intelligible

character does not begin to be; it does not make its appearance at a

certain time, for the purpose of producing an effect. If this were not

the case, the causality of reason would be subservient to the

natural law of phenomena, which determines them according to time, and

as a series of causes and effects in time; it would consequently cease

to be freedom and become a part of nature. We are therefore

justified in saying: "If reason stands in a causal relation to

phenomena, it is a faculty which originates the sensuous condition

of an empirical series of effects." For the condition, which resides

in the reason, is non-sensuous, and therefore cannot be originated, or

begin to be. And thus we find- what we could not discover in any

empirical series- a condition of a successive series of events

itself empirically unconditioned. For, in the present case, the

condition stands out of and beyond the series of phenomena- it is

intelligible, and it consequently cannot be subjected to any

sensuous condition, or to any time-determination by a preceding cause.



  *The real morality of actions- their merit or demerit, and even that

of our own conduct, is completely unknown to us. Our estimates can

relate only to their empirical character. How much is the result of

the action of free will, how much is to be ascribed to nature and to

blameless error, or to a happy constitution of temperament (merito

fortunae), no one can discover, nor, for this reason, determine with

perfect justice.



  But, in another respect, the same cause belongs also to the series

of phenomena. Man is himself a phenomenon. His will has an empirical

character, which is the empirical cause of all his actions. There is

no condition- determining man and his volition in conformity with this

character- which does not itself form part of the series of effects in

nature, and is subject to their law- the law according to which an

empirically undetermined cause of an event in time cannot exist. For

this reason no given action can have an absolute and spontaneous

origination, all actions being phenomena, and belonging to the world

of experience. But it cannot be said of reason, that the state in

which it determines the will is always preceded by some other state

determining it. For reason is not a phenomenon, and therefore not

subject to sensuous conditions; and, consequently, even in relation to

its causality, the sequence or conditions of time do not influence

reason, nor can the dynamical law of nature, which determines the

sequence of time according to certain rules, be applied to it.

  Reason is consequently the permanent condition of all actions of the

human will. Each of these is determined in the empirical character

of the man, even before it has taken place. The intelligible

character, of which the former is but the sensuous schema, knows no

before or after; and every action, irrespective of the time-relation

in which it stands with other phenomena, is the immediate effect of

the intelligible character of pure reason, which, consequently, enjoys

freedom of action, and is not dynamically determined either by

internal or external preceding conditions. This freedom must not be

described, in a merely negative manner, as independence of empirical

conditions, for in this case the faculty of reason would cease to be a

cause of phenomena; but it must be regarded, positively, as a

faculty which can spontaneously originate a series of events. At the

same time, it must not be supposed that any beginning can take place

in reason; on the contrary, reason, as the unconditioned condition

of all action of the will, admits of no time-conditions, although

its effect does really begin in a series of phenomena- a beginning

which is not, however, absolutely primal.

  I shall illustrate this regulative principle of reason by an

example, from its employment in the world of experience; proved it

cannot be by any amount of experience, or by any number of facts,

for such arguments cannot establish the truth of transcendental

propositions. Let us take a voluntary action- for example, a

falsehood- by means of which a man has introduced a certain degree

of confusion into the social life of humanity, which is judged

according to the motives from which it originated, and the blame of

which and of the evil consequences arising from it, is imputed to

the offender. We at first proceed to examine the empirical character

of the offence, and for this purpose we endeavour to penetrate to

the sources of that character, such as a defective education, bad

company, a shameless and wicked disposition, frivolity, and want of

reflection- not forgetting also the occasioning causes which prevailed

at the moment of the transgression. In this the procedure is exactly

the same as that pursued in the investigation of the series of

causes which determine a given physical effect. Now, although we

believe the action to have been determined by all these circumstances,

we do not the less blame the offender. We do not blame him for his

unhappy disposition, nor for the circumstances which influenced him,

nay, not even for his former course of life; for we presuppose that

all these considerations may be set aside, that the series of

preceding conditions may be regarded as having never existed, and that

the action may be considered as completely unconditioned in relation

to any state preceding, just as if the agent commenced with it an

entirely new series of effects. Our blame of the offender is

grounded upon a law of reason, which requires us to regard this

faculty as a cause, which could have and ought to have otherwise

determined the behaviour of the culprit, independently of all

empirical conditions. This causality of reason we do not regard as a

co-operating agency, but as complete in itself. It matters not whether

the sensuous impulses favoured or opposed the action of this

causality, the offence is estimated according to its intelligible

character- the offender is decidedly worthy of blame, the moment he

utters a falsehood. It follows that we regard reason, in spite of

the empirical conditions of the act, as completely free, and

therefore, therefore, as in the present case, culpable.

  The above judgement is complete evidence that we are accustomed to

think that reason is not affected by sensuous conditions, that in it

no change takes place- although its phenomena, in other words, the

mode in which it appears in its effects, are subject to change- that

in it no preceding state determines the following, and,

consequently, that it does not form a member of the series of sensuous

conditions which necessitate phenomena according to natural laws.

Reason is present and the same in all human actions and at all

times; but it does not itself exist in time, and therefore does not

enter upon any state in which it did not formerly exist. It is,

relatively to new states or conditions, determining, but not

determinable. Hence we cannot ask: "Why did not reason determine

itself in a different manner?" The question ought to be thus stated:

"Why did not reason employ its power of causality to determine certain

phenomena in a different manner?" "But this is a question which admits

of no answer. For a different intelligible character would have

exhibited a different empirical character; and, when we say that, in

spite of the course which his whole former life has taken, the

offender could have refrained from uttering the falsehood, this

means merely that the act was subject to the power and authority-

permissive or prohibitive- of reason. Now, reason is not subject in

its causality to any conditions of phenomena or of time; and a

difference in time may produce a difference in the relation of

phenomena to each other- for these are not things and therefore not

causes in themselves- but it cannot produce any difference in the

relation in which the action stands to the faculty of reason.

  Thus, then, in our investigation into free actions and the causal

power which produced them, we arrive at an intelligible cause,

beyond which, however, we cannot go; although we can recognize that it

is free, that is, independent of all sensuous conditions, and that, in

this way, it may be the sensuously unconditioned condition of

phenomena. But for what reason the intelligible character generates

such and such phenomena and exhibits such and such an empirical

character under certain circumstances, it is beyond the power of our

reason to decide. The question is as much above the power and the

sphere of reason as the following would be: "Why does the

transcendental object of our external sensuous intuition allow of no

other form than that of intuition in space?" But the problem, which we

were called upon to solve, does not require us to entertain any such

questions. The problem was merely this- whether freedom and natural

necessity can exist without opposition in the same action. To this

question we have given a sufficient answer; for we have shown that, as

the former stands in a relation to a different kind of condition

from those of the latter, the law of the one does not affect the law

of the other and that, consequently, both can exist together in

independence of and without interference with each other.



  The reader must be careful to remark that my intention in the

above remarks has not been to prove the actual existence of freedom,

as a faculty in which resides the cause of certain sensuous phenomena.

For, not to mention that such an argument would not have a

transcendental character, nor have been limited to the discussion of

pure conceptions- all attempts at inferring from experience what

cannot be cogitated in accordance with its laws, must ever be

unsuccessful. Nay, more, I have not even aimed at demonstrating the

possibility of freedom; for this too would have been a vain endeavour,

inasmuch as it is beyond the power of the mind to cognize the

possibility of a reality or of a causal power by the aid of mere a

priori conceptions. Freedom has been considered in the foregoing

remarks only as a transcendental idea, by means of which reason aims

at originating a series of conditions in the world of phenomena with

the help of that which is sensuously unconditioned, involving

itself, however, in an antinomy with the laws which itself

prescribes for the conduct of the understanding. That this antinomy is

based upon a mere illusion, and that nature and freedom are at least

not opposed- this was the only thing in our power to prove, and the

question which it was our task to solve.



    IV. Solution of the Cosmological Idea of the Totality of

          the Dependence of Phenomenal Existences.



  In the preceding remarks, we considered the changes in the world

of sense as constituting a dynamical series, in which each member is

subordinated to another- as its cause. Our present purpose is to avail

ourselves of this series of states or conditions as a guide to an

existence which may be the highest condition of all changeable

phenomena, that is, to a necessary being. Our endeavour to reach,

not the unconditioned causality, but the unconditioned existence, of

substance. The series before us is therefore a series of

conceptions, and not of intuitions (in which the one intuition is

the condition of the other).

  But it is evident that, as all phenomena are subject to change and

conditioned in their existence, the series of dependent existences

cannot embrace an unconditioned member, the existence of which would

be absolutely necessary. It follows that, if phenomena were things

in themselves, and- as an immediate consequence from this supposition-

condition and conditioned belonged to the same series of phenomena,

the existence of a necessary being, as the condition of the

existence of sensuous phenomena, would be perfectly impossible.

  An important distinction, however, exists between the dynamical

and the mathematical regress. The latter is engaged solely with the

combination of parts into a whole, or with the division of a whole

into its parts; and therefore are the conditions of its series parts

of the series, and to be consequently regarded as homogeneous, and for

this reason, as consisting, without exception, of phenomena. If the

former regress, on the contrary, the aim of which is not to

establish the possibility of an unconditioned whole consisting of

given parts, or of an unconditioned part of a given whole, but to

demonstrate the possibility of the deduction of a certain state from

its cause, or of the contingent existence of substance from that which

exists necessarily, it is not requisite that the condition should form

part of an empirical series along with the conditioned.

  In the case of the apparent antinomy with which we are at present

dealing, there exists a way of escape from the difficulty; for it is

not impossible that both of the contradictory statements may be true

in different relations. All sensuous phenomena may be contingent,

and consequently possess only an empirically conditioned existence,

and yet there may also exist a non-empirical condition of the whole

series, or, in other words, a necessary being. For this necessary

being, as an intelligible condition, would not form a member- not even

the highest member- of the series; the whole world of sense would be

left in its empirically determined existence uninterfered with and

uninfluenced. This would also form a ground of distinction between the

modes of solution employed for the third and fourth antinomies. For,

while in the consideration of freedom in the former antinomy, the

thing itself- the cause (substantia phaenomenon)- was regarded as

belonging to the series of conditions, and only its causality to the

intelligible world- we are obliged in the present case to cogitate

this necessary being as purely intelligible and as existing entirely

apart from the world of sense (as an ens extramundanum); for otherwise

it would be subject to the phenomenal law of contingency and

dependence.

  In relation to the present problem, therefore, the regulative

principle of reason is that everything in the sensuous world possesses

an empirically conditioned existence- that no property of the sensuous

world possesses unconditioned necessity- that we are bound to

expect, and, so far as is possible, to seek for the empirical

condition of every member in the series of conditions- and that

there is no sufficient reason to justify us in deducing any

existence from a condition which lies out of and beyond the

empirical series, or in regarding any existence as independent and

self-subsistent; although this should not prevent us from

recognizing the possibility of the whole series being based upon a

being which is intelligible, and for this reason free from all

empirical conditions.

  But it has been far from my intention, in these remarks, to prove

the existence of this unconditioned and necessary being, or even to

evidence the possibility of a purely intelligible condition of the

existence or all sensuous phenomena. As bounds were set to reason,

to prevent it from leaving the guiding thread of empirical

conditions and losing itself in transcendent theories which are

incapable of concrete presentation; so it was my purpose, on the other

band, to set bounds to the law of the purely empirical

understanding, and to protest against any attempts on its part at

deciding on the possibility of things, or declaring the existence of

the intelligible to be impossible, merely on the ground that it is not

available for the explanation and exposition of phenomena. It has been

shown, at the same time, that the contingency of all the phenomena

of nature and their empirical conditions is quite consistent with

the arbitrary hypothesis of a necessary, although purely

intelligible condition, that no real contradiction exists between them

and that, consequently, both may be true. The existence of such an

absolutely necessary being may be impossible; but this can never be

demonstrated from the universal contingency and dependence of sensuous

phenomena, nor from the principle which forbids us to discontinue

the series at some member of it, or to seek for its cause in some

sphere of existence beyond the world of nature. Reason goes its way in

the empirical world, and follows, too, its peculiar path in the sphere

of the transcendental.

  The sensuous world contains nothing but phenomena, which are mere

representations, and always sensuously conditioned; things in

themselves are not, and cannot be, objects to us. It is not to be

wondered at, therefore, that we are not justified in leaping from some

member of an empirical series beyond the world of sense, as if

empirical representations were things in themselves, existing apart

from their transcendental ground in the human mind, and the cause of

whose existence may be sought out of the empirical series. This

would certainly be the case with contingent things; but it cannot be

with mere representations of things, the contingency of which is

itself merely a phenomenon and can relate to no other regress than

that which determines phenomena, that is, the empirical. But to

cogitate an intelligible ground of phenomena, as free, moreover,

from the contingency of the latter, conflicts neither with the

unlimited nature of the empirical regress, nor with the complete

contingency of phenomena. And the demonstration of this was the only

thing necessary for the solution of this apparent antinomy. For if the

condition of every conditioned- as regards its existence- is sensuous,

and for this reason a part of the same series, it must be itself

conditioned, as was shown in the antithesis of the fourth antinomy.

The embarrassments into which a reason, which postulates the

unconditioned, necessarily falls, must, therefore, continue to

exist; or the unconditioned must be placed in the sphere of the

intelligible. In this way, its necessity does not require, nor does it

even permit, the presence of an empirical condition: and it is,

consequently, unconditionally necessary.

  The empirical employment of reason is not affected by the assumption

of a purely intelligible being; it continues its operations on the

principle of the contingency of all phenomena, proceeding from

empirical conditions to still higher and higher conditions, themselves

empirical. just as little does this regulative principle exclude the

assumption of an intelligible cause, when the question regards

merely the pure employment of reason- in relation to ends or aims.

For, in this case, an intelligible cause signifies merely the

transcendental and to us unknown ground of the possibility of sensuous

phenomena, and its existence, necessary and independent of all

sensuous conditions, is not inconsistent with the contingency of

phenomena, or with the unlimited possibility of regress which exists

in the series of empirical conditions.



       Concluding Remarks on the Antinomy of Pure Reason.



  So long as the object of our rational conceptions is the totality of

conditions in the world of phenomena, and the satisfaction, from

this source, of the requirements of reason, so long are our ideas

transcendental and cosmological. But when we set the unconditioned-

which is the aim of all our inquiries- in a sphere which lies out of

the world of sense and possible experience, our ideas become

transcendent. They are then not merely serviceable towards the

completion of the exercise of reason (which remains an idea, never

executed, but always to be pursued); they detach themselves completely

from experience and construct for themselves objects, the material

of which has not been presented by experience, and the objective

reality of which is not based upon the completion of the empirical

series, but upon pure a priori conceptions. The intelligible object of

these transcendent ideas may be conceded, as a transcendental

object. But we cannot cogitate it as a thing determinable by certain

distinct predicates relating to its internal nature, for it has no

connection with empirical conceptions; nor are we justified in

affirming the existence of any such object. It is, consequently, a

mere product of the mind alone. Of all the cosmological ideas,

however, it is that occasioning the fourth antinomy which compels us

to venture upon this step. For the existence of phenomena, always

conditioned and never self-subsistent, requires us to look for an

object different from phenomena- an intelligible object, with which

all contingency must cease. But, as we have allowed ourselves to

assume the existence of a self-subsistent reality out of the field

of experience, and are therefore obliged to regard phenomena as merely

a contingent mode of representing intelligible objects employed by

beings which are themselves intelligences- no other course remains for

us than to follow an alogy and employ the same mode in forming some

conception of intelligible things, of which we have not the least

knowledge, which nature taught us to use in the formation of empirical

conceptions. Experience made us acquainted with the contingent. But we

are at present engaged in the discussion of things which are not

objects of experience; and must, therefore, deduce our knowledge of

them from that which is necessary absolutely and in itself, that is,

from pure conceptions. Hence the first step which we take out of the

world of sense obliges us to begin our system of new cognition with

the investigation of a necessary being, and to deduce from our

conceptions of it all our conceptions of intelligible things. This

we propose to attempt in the following chapter.

           CHAPTER III. The Ideal of Pure Reason.



            SECTION I. Of the Ideal in General.



  We have seen that pure conceptions do not present objects to the

mind, except under sensuous conditions; because the conditions of

objective reality do not exist in these conceptions, which contain, in

fact, nothing but the mere form of thought. They may, however, when

applied to phenomena, be presented in concreto; for it is phenomena

that present to them the materials for the formation of empirical

conceptions, which are nothing more than concrete forms of the

conceptions of the understanding. But ideas are still further

removed from objective reality than categories; for no phenomenon

can ever present them to the human mind in concreto. They contain a

certain perfection, attainable by no possible empirical cognition; and

they give to reason a systematic unity, to which the unity of

experience attempts to approximate, but can never completely attain.

  But still further removed than the idea from objective reality is

the Ideal, by which term I understand the idea, not in concreto, but

in individuo- as an individual thing, determinable or determined by

the idea alone. The idea of humanity in its complete perfection

supposes not only the advancement of all the powers and faculties,

which constitute our conception of human nature, to a complete

attainment of their final aims, but also everything which is requisite

for the complete determination of the idea; for of all contradictory

predicates, only one can conform with the idea of the perfect man.

What I have termed an ideal was in Plato's philosophy an idea of the

divine mind- an individual object present to its pure intuition, the

most perfect of every kind of possible beings, and the archetype of

all phenomenal existences.

  Without rising to these speculative heights, we are bound to confess

that human reason contains not only ideas, but ideals, which

possess, not, like those of Plato, creative, but certainly practical

power- as regulative principles, and form the basis of the

perfectibility of certain actions. Moral conceptions are not perfectly

pure conceptions of reason, because an empirical element- of

pleasure or pain- lies at the foundation of them. In relation,

however, to the principle, whereby reason sets bounds to a freedom

which is in itself without law, and consequently when we attend merely

to their form, they may be considered as pure conceptions of reason.

Virtue and wisdom in their perfect purity are ideas. But the wise

man of the Stoics is an ideal, that is to say, a human being

existing only in thought and in complete conformity with the idea of

wisdom. As the idea provides a rule, so the ideal serves as an

archetype for the perfect and complete determination of the copy. Thus

the conduct of this wise and divine man serves us as a standard of

action, with which we may compare and judge ourselves, which may

help us to reform ourselves, although the perfection it demands can

never be attained by us. Although we cannot concede objective

reality to these ideals, they are not to be considered as chimeras; on

the contrary, they provide reason with a standard, which enables it to

estimate, by comparison, the degree of incompleteness in the objects

presented to it. But to aim at realizing the ideal in an example in

the world of experience- to describe, for instance, the character of

the perfectly wise man in a romance- is impracticable. Nay more, there

is something absurd in the attempt; and the result must be little

edifying, as the natural limitations, which are continually breaking

in upon the perfection and completeness of the idea, destroy the

illusion in the story and throw an air of suspicion even on what is

good in the idea, which hence appears fictitious and unreal.

  Such is the constitution of the ideal of reason, which is always

based upon determinate conceptions, and serves as a rule and a model

for limitation or of criticism. Very different is the nature of the

ideals of the imagination. Of these it is impossible to present an

intelligible conception; they are a kind of monogram, drawn

according to no determinate rule, and forming rather a vague

picture- the production of many diverse experiences- than a

determinate image. Such are the ideals which painters and

physiognomists profess to have in their minds, and which can serve

neither as a model for production nor as a standard for

appreciation. They may be termed, though improperly, sensuous

ideals, as they are declared to be models of certain possible

empirical intuitions. They cannot, however, furnish rules or standards

for explanation or examination with

  In its ideals, reason aims at complete and perfect determination

according to a priori rules; and hence it cogitates an object, which

must be completely determinable in conformity with principles,

although all empirical conditions are absent, and the conception of

the object is on this account transcendent.



       SECTION II. Of the Transcendental Ideal (Prototypon

                       Trancendentale).



  Every conception is, in relation to that which is not contained in

it, undetermined and subject to the principle of determinability. This

principle is that, of every two contradictorily opposed predicates,

only one can belong to a conception. It is a purely logical principle,

itself based upon the principle of contradiction; inasmuch as it makes

complete abstraction of the content and attends merely to the

logical form of the cognition.

  But again, everything, as regards its possibility, is also subject

to the principle of complete determination, according to which one

of all the possible contradictory predicates of things must belong

to it. This principle is not based merely upon that of

contradiction; for, in addition to the relation between two

contradictory predicates, it regards everything as standing in a

relation to the sum of possibilities, as the sum total of all

predicates of things, and, while presupposing this sum as an a

priori condition, presents to the mind everything as receiving the

possibility of its individual existence from the relation it bears to,

and the share it possesses in, the aforesaid sum of possibilities.*

The principle of complete determination relates the content and not to

the logical form. It is the principle of the synthesis of all the

predicates which are required to constitute the complete conception of

a thing, and not a mere principle analytical representation, which

enounces that one of two contradictory predicates must belong to a

conception. It contains, moreover, a transcendental presupposition-

that, namely, of the material for all possibility, which must

contain a priori the data for this or that particular possibility.



  *Thus this principle declares everything to possess a relation to

a common correlate- the sum-total of possibility, which, if discovered

to exist in the idea of one individual thing, would establish the

affinity of all possible things, from the identity of the ground of

their complete determination. The determinability of every

conception is subordinate to the universality (Allgemeinheit,

universalitas) of the principle of excluded middle; the

determination of a thing to the totality (Allheit, universitas) of all

possible predicates.



  The proposition, Everything which exists is completely determined,

means not only that one of every pair of given contradictory

attributes, but that one of all possible attributes, is always

predicable of the thing; in it the predicates are not merely

compared logically with each other, but the thing itself is

transcendentally compared with the sum-total of all possible

predicates. The proposition is equivalent to saying: "To attain to a

complete knowledge of a thing, it is necessary to possess a

knowledge of everything that is possible, and to determine it

thereby in a positive or negative manner." The conception of

complete determination is consequently a conception which cannot be

presented in its totality in concreto, and is therefore based upon

an idea, which has its seat in the reason- the faculty which

prescribes to the understanding the laws of its harmonious and perfect

exercise relates

  Now, although this idea of the sum-total of all possibility, in so

far as it forms the condition of the complete determination of

everything, is itself undetermined in relation to the predicates which

may constitute this sum-total, and we cogitate in it merely the

sum-total of all possible predicates- we nevertheless find, upon

closer examination, that this idea, as a primitive conception of the

mind, excludes a large number of predicates- those deduced and those

irreconcilable with others, and that it is evolved as a conception

completely determined a priori. Thus it becomes the conception of an

individual object, which is completely determined by and through the

mere idea, and must consequently be termed an ideal of pure reason.

  When we consider all possible predicates, not merely logically,

but transcendentally, that is to say, with reference to the content

which may be cogitated as existing in them a priori, we shall find

that some indicate a being, others merely a non-being. The logical

negation expressed in the word not does not properly belong to a

conception, but only to the relation of one conception to another in a

judgement, and is consequently quite insufficient to present to the

mind the content of a conception. The expression not mortal does not

indicate that a non-being is cogitated in the object; it does not

concern the content at all. A transcendental negation, on the

contrary, indicates non-being in itself, and is opposed to

transcendental affirmation, the conception of which of itself

expresses a being. Hence this affirmation indicates a reality, because

in and through it objects are considered to be something- to be

things; while the opposite negation, on the other band, indicates a

mere want, or privation, or absence, and, where such negations alone

are attached to a representation, the non-existence of anything

corresponding to the representation.

  Now a negation cannot be cogitated as determined, without cogitating

at the same time the opposite affirmation. The man born blind has

not the least notion of darkness, because he has none of light; the

vagabond knows nothing of poverty, because he has never known what

it is to be in comfort;* the ignorant man has no conception of his

ignorance, because he has no conception of knowledge. All

conceptions of negatives are accordingly derived or deduced

conceptions; and realities contain the data, and, so to speak, the

material or transcendental content of the possibility and complete

determination of all things.



  *The investigations and calculations of astronomers have taught us

much that is wonderful; but the most important lesson we have received

from them is the discovery of the abyss of our ignorance in relation

to the universe- an ignorance the magnitude of which reason, without

the information thus derived, could never have conceived. This

discovery of our deficiencies must produce a great change in the

determination of the aims of human reason.



  If, therefore, a transcendental substratum lies at the foundation of

the complete determination of things- a substratum which is to form

the fund from which all possible predicates of things are to be

supplied, this substratum cannot be anything else than the idea of a

sum-total of reality (omnitudo realitatis). In this view, negations

are nothing but limitations- a term which could not, with propriety,

be applied to them, if the unlimited (the all) did not form the true

basis of our conception.

  This conception of a sum-total of reality is the conception of a

thing in itself, regarded as completely determined; and the conception

of an ens realissimum is the conception of an individual being,

inasmuch as it is determined by that predicate of all possible

contradictory predicates, which indicates and belongs to being. It is,

therefore, a transcendental ideal which forms the basis of the

complete determination of everything that exists, and is the highest

material condition of its possibility- a condition on which must

rest the cogitation of all objects with respect to their content. Nay,

more, this ideal is the only proper ideal of which the human mind is

capable; because in this case alone a general conception of a thing is

completely determined by and through itself, and cognized as the

representation of an individuum.

  The logical determination of a conception is based upon a

disjunctive syllogism, the major of which contains the logical

division of the extent of a general conception, the minor limits

this extent to a certain part, while the conclusion determines the

conception by this part. The general conception of a reality cannot be

divided a priori, because, without the aid of experience, we cannot

know any determinate kinds of reality, standing under the former as

the genus. The transcendental principle of the complete

determination of all things is therefore merely the representation

of the sum-total of all reality; it is not a conception which is the

genus of all predicates under itself, but one which comprehends them

all within itself. The complete determination of a thing is

consequently based upon the limitation of this total of reality, so

much being predicated of the thing, while all that remains over is

excluded- a procedure which is in exact agreement with that of the

disjunctive syllogism and the determination of the objects in the

conclusion by one of the members of the division. It follows that

reason, in laying the transcendental ideal at the foundation of its

determination of all possible things, takes a course in exact

analogy with that which it pursues in disjunctive syllogisms- a

proposition which formed the basis of the systematic division of all

transcendental ideas, according to which they are produced in complete

parallelism with the three modes of syllogistic reasoning employed

by the human mind.

  It is self-evident that reason, in cogitating the necessary complete

determination of things, does not presuppose the existence of a

being corresponding to its ideal, but merely the idea of the ideal-

for the purpose of deducing from the unconditional totality of

complete determination, The ideal is therefore the prototype of all

things, which, as defective copies (ectypa), receive from it the

material of their possibility, and approximate to it more or less,

though it is impossible that they can ever attain to its perfection.

  The possibility of things must therefore be regarded as derived-

except that of the thing which contains in itself all reality, which

must be considered to be primitive and original. For all negations-

and they are the only predicates by means of which all other things

can be distinguished from the ens realissimum- are mere limitations of

a greater and a higher- nay, the highest reality; and they

consequently presuppose this reality, and are, as regards their

content, derived from it. The manifold nature of things is only an

infinitely various mode of limiting the conception of the highest

reality, which is their common substratum; just as all figures are

possible only as different modes of limiting infinite space. The

object of the ideal of reason- an object existing only in reason

itself- is also termed the primal being (ens originarium); as having

no existence superior to him, the supreme being (ens summum); and as

being the condition of all other beings, which rank under it, the

being of all beings (ens entium). But none of these terms indicate the

objective relation of an actually existing object to other things, but

merely that of an idea to conceptions; and all our investigations into

this subject still leave us in perfect uncertainty with regard to

the existence of this being.

  A primal being cannot be said to consist of many other beings with

an existence which is derivative, for the latter presuppose the

former, and therefore cannot be constitutive parts of it. It follows

that the ideal of the primal being must be cogitated as simple.

  The deduction of the possibility of all other things from this

primal being cannot, strictly speaking, be considered as a limitation,

or as a kind of division of its reality; for this would be regarding

the primal being as a mere aggregate- which has been shown to be

impossible, although it was so represented in our first rough

sketch. The highest reality must be regarded rather as the ground than

as the sum-total of the possibility of all things, and the manifold

nature of things be based, not upon the limitation of the primal being

itself, but upon the complete series of effects which flow from it.

And thus all our powers of sense, as well as all phenomenal reality,

phenomenal reality, may be with propriety regarded as belonging to

this series of effects, while they could not have formed parts of

the idea, considered as an aggregate. Pursuing this track, and

hypostatizing this idea, we shall find ourselves authorized to

determine our notion of the Supreme Being by means of the mere

conception of a highest reality, as one, simple, all-sufficient,

eternal, and so on- in one word, to determine it in its

unconditioned completeness by the aid of every possible predicate. The

conception of such a being is the conception of God in its

transcendental sense, and thus the ideal of pure reason is the

object-matter of a transcendental theology.

  But, by such an employment of the transcendental idea, we should

be over stepping the limits of its validity and purpose. For reason

placed it, as the conception of all reality, at the basis of the

complete determination of things, without requiring that this

conception be regarded as the conception of an objective existence.

Such an existence would be purely fictitious, and the hypostatizing of

the content of the idea into an ideal, as an individual being, is a

step perfectly unauthorized. Nay, more, we are not even called upon to

assume the possibility of such an hypothesis, as none of the

deductions drawn from such an ideal would affect the complete

determination of things in general- for the sake of which alone is the

idea necessary.

  It is not sufficient to circumscribe the procedure and the dialectic

of reason; we must also endeavour to discover the sources of this

dialectic, that we may have it in our power to give a rational

explanation of this illusion, as a phenomenon of the human mind. For

the ideal, of which we are at present speaking, is based, not upon

an arbitrary, but upon a natural, idea. The question hence arises: How

happens it that reason regards the possibility of all things as

deduced from a single possibility, that, to wit, of the highest

reality, and presupposes this as existing in an individual and

primal being?

  The answer is ready; it is at once presented by the procedure of

transcendental analytic. The possibility of sensuous objects is a

relation of these objects to thought, in which something (the

empirical form) may be cogitated a priori; while that which

constitutes the matter- the reality of the phenomenon (that element

which corresponds to sensation)- must be given from without, as

otherwise it could not even be cogitated by, nor could its possibility

be presentable to the mind. Now, a sensuous object is completely

determined, when it has been compared with all phenomenal

predicates, and represented by means of these either positively or

negatively. But, as that which constitutes the thing itself- the

real in a phenomenon, must be given, and that, in which the real of

all phenomena is given, is experience, one, sole, and all-embracing-

the material of the possibility of all sensuous objects must be

presupposed as given in a whole, and it is upon the limitation of this

whole that the possibility of all empirical objects, their distinction

from each other and their complete determination, are based. Now, no

other objects are presented to us besides sensuous objects, and

these can be given only in connection with a possible experience; it

follows that a thing is not an object to us, unless it presupposes the

whole or sum-total of empirical reality as the condition of its

possibility. Now, a natural illusion leads us to consider this

principle, which is valid only of sensuous objects, as valid with

regard to things in general. And thus we are induced to hold the

empirical principle of our conceptions of the possibility of things,

as phenomena, by leaving out this limitative condition, to be a

transcendental principle of the possibility of things in general.

  We proceed afterwards to hypostatize this idea of the sum-total of

all reality, by changing the distributive unity of the empirical

exercise of the understanding into the collective unity of an

empirical whole- a dialectical illusion, and by cogitating this

whole or sum of experience as an individual thing, containing in

itself all empirical reality. This individual thing or being is

then, by means of the above-mentioned transcendental subreption,

substituted for our notion of a thing which stands at the head of

the possibility of all things, the real conditions of whose complete

determination it presents.*



  *This ideal of the ens realissimum- although merely a mental

representation- is first objectivized, that is, has an objective

existence attributed to it, then hypostatized, and finally, by the

natural progress of reason to the completion of unity, personified, as

we shall show presently. For the regulative unity of experience is not

based upon phenomena themselves, but upon the connection of the

variety of phenomena by the understanding in a consciousness, and thus

the unity of the supreme reality and the complete determinability of

all things, seem to reside in a supreme understanding, and,

consequently, in a conscious intelligence.



   SECTION III. Of the Arguments employed by Speculative Reason in

            Proof of the Existence of a Supreme Being.



  Notwithstanding the pressing necessity which reason feels, to form

some presupposition that shall serve the understanding as a proper

basis for the complete determination of its conceptions, the

idealistic and factitious nature of such a presupposition is too

evident to allow reason for a moment to persuade itself into a

belief of the objective existence of a mere creation of its own

thought. But there are other considerations which compel reason to

seek out some resting place in the regress from the conditioned to the

unconditioned, which is not given as an actual existence from the mere

conception of it, although it alone can give completeness to the

series of conditions. And this is the natural course of every human

reason, even of the most uneducated, although the path at first

entered it does not always continue to follow. It does not begin

from conceptions, but from common experience, and requires a basis

in actual existence. But this basis is insecure, unless it rests

upon the immovable rock of the absolutely necessary. And this

foundation is itself unworthy of trust, if it leave under and above it

empty space, if it do not fill all, and leave no room for a why or a

wherefore, if it be not, in one word, infinite in its reality.

  If we admit the existence of some one thing, whatever it may be,

we must also admit that there is something which exists necessarily.

For what is contingent exists only under the condition of some other

thing, which is its cause; and from this we must go on to conclude the

existence of a cause which is not contingent, and which consequently

exists necessarily and unconditionally. Such is the argument by

which reason justifies its advances towards a primal being.

  Now reason looks round for the conception of a being that may be

admitted, without inconsistency, to be worthy of the attribute of

absolute necessity, not for the purpose of inferring a priori, from

the conception of such a being, its objective existence (for if reason

allowed itself to take this course, it would not require a basis in

given and actual existence, but merely the support of pure

conceptions), but for the purpose of discovering, among all our

conceptions of possible things, that conception which possesses no

element inconsistent with the idea of absolute necessity. For that

there must be some absolutely necessary existence, it regards as a

truth already established. Now, if it can remove every existence

incapable of supporting the attribute of absolute necessity, excepting

one- this must be the absolutely necessary being, whether its

necessity is comprehensible by us, that is, deducible from the

conception of it alone, or not.

  Now that, the conception of which contains a therefore to every

wherefore, which is not defective in any respect whatever, which is

all-sufficient as a condition, seems to be the being of which we can

justly predicate absolute necessity- for this reason, that, possessing

the conditions of all that is possible, it does not and cannot

itself require any condition. And thus it satisfies, in one respect at

least, the requirements of the conception of absolute necessity. In

this view, it is superior to all other conceptions, which, as

deficient and incomplete, do not possess the characteristic of

independence of all higher conditions. It is true that we cannot infer

from this that what does not contain in itself the supreme and

complete condition- the condition of all other things- must possess

only a conditioned existence; but as little can we assert the

contrary, for this supposed being does not possess the only

characteristic which can enable reason to cognize by means of an a

priori conception the unconditioned and necessary nature of its

existence.

  The conception of an ens realissimum is that which best agrees

with the conception of an unconditioned and necessary being. The

former conception does not satisfy all the requirements of the latter;

but we have no choice, we are obliged to adhere to it, for we find

that we cannot do without the existence of a necessary being; and even

although we admit it, we find it out of our power to discover in the

whole sphere of possibility any being that can advance wellgrounded

claims to such a distinction.

  The following is, therefore, the natural course of human reason.

It begins by persuading itself of the existence of some necessary

being. In this being it recognizes the characteristics of

unconditioned existence. It then seeks the conception of that which is

independent of all conditions, and finds it in that which is itself

the sufficient condition of all other things- in other words, in

that which contains all reality. But the unlimited all is an

absolute unity, and is conceived by the mind as a being one and

supreme; and thus reason concludes that the Supreme Being, as the

primal basis of all things, possesses an existence which is absolutely

necessary.

  This conception must be regarded as in some degree satisfactory,

if we admit the existence of a necessary being, and consider that

there exists a necessity for a definite and final answer to these

questions. In such a case, we cannot make a better choice, or rather

we have no choice at all, but feel ourselves obliged to declare in

favour of the absolute unity of complete reality, as the highest

source of the possibility of things. But if there exists no motive for

coming to a definite conclusion, and we may leave the question

unanswered till we have fully weighed both sides- in other words, when

we are merely called upon to decide how much we happen to know about

the question, and how much we merely flatter ourselves that we know-

the above conclusion does not appear to be so great advantage, but, on

the contrary, seems defective in the grounds upon which it is

supported.

  For, admitting the truth of all that has been said, that, namely,

the inference from a given existence (my own, for example) to the

existence of an unconditioned and necessary being is valid and

unassailable; that, in the second place, we must consider a being

which contains all reality, and consequently all the conditions of

other things, to be absolutely unconditioned; and admitting too,

that we have thus discovered the conception of a thing to which may be

attributed, without inconsistency, absolute necessity- it does not

follow from all this that the conception of a limited being, in

which the supreme reality does not reside, is therefore incompatible

with the idea of absolute necessity. For, although I do not discover

the element of the unconditioned in the conception of such a being- an

element which is manifestly existent in the sum-total of all

conditions- I am not entitled to conclude that its existence is

therefore conditioned; just as I am not entitled to affirm, in a

hypothetical syllogism, that where a certain condition does not

exist (in the present, completeness, as far as pure conceptions are

concerned), the conditioned does not exist either. On the contrary, we

are free to consider all limited beings as likewise unconditionally

necessary, although we are unable to infer this from the general

conception which we have of them. Thus conducted, this argument is

incapable of giving us the least notion of the properties of a

necessary being, and must be in every respect without result.

  This argument continues, however, to possess a weight and an

authority, which, in spite of its objective insufficiency, it has

never been divested of. For, granting that certain responsibilities

lie upon us, which, as based on the ideas of reason, deserve to be

respected and submitted to, although they are incapable of a real or

practical application to our nature, or, in other words, would be

responsibilities without motives, except upon the supposition of a

Supreme Being to give effect and influence to the practical laws: in

such a case we should be bound to obey our conceptions, which,

although objectively insufficient, do, according to the standard of

reason, preponderate over and are superior to any claims that may be

advanced from any other quarter. The equilibrium of doubt would in

this case be destroyed by a practical addition; indeed, Reason would

be compelled to condemn herself, if she refused to comply with the

demands of the judgement, no superior to which we know- however

defective her understanding of the grounds of these demands might be.

  This argument, although in fact transcendental, inasmuch as it rests

upon the intrinsic insufficiency of the contingent, is so simple and

natural, that the commonest understanding can appreciate its value. We

see things around us change, arise, and pass away; they, or their

condition, must therefore have a cause. The same demand must again

be made of the cause itself- as a datum of experience. Now it is

natural that we should place the highest causality just where we place

supreme causality, in that being, which contains the conditions of all

possible effects, and the conception of which is so simple as that

of an all-embracing reality. This highest cause, then, we regard as

absolutely necessary, because we find it absolutely necessary to

rise to it, and do not discover any reason for proceeding beyond it.

Thus, among all nations, through the darkest polytheism glimmer some

faint sparks of monotheism, to which these idolaters have been led,

not from reflection and profound thought, but by the study and natural

progress of the common understanding.

  There are only three modes of proving the existence of a Deity, on

the grounds of speculative reason.

  All the paths conducting to this end begin either from determinate

experience and the peculiar constitution of the world of sense, and

rise, according to the laws of causality, from it to the highest cause

existing apart from the world- or from a purely indeterminate

experience, that is, some empirical existence- or abstraction is

made of all experience, and the existence of a supreme cause is

concluded from a priori conceptions alone. The first is the

physicotheological argument, the second the cosmological, the third

the ontological. More there are not, and more there cannot be.

  I shall show it is as unsuccessful on the one path- the empirical-

as on the other- the transcendental- and that it stretches its wings

in vain, to soar beyond the world of sense by the mere might of

speculative thought. As regards the order in which we must discuss

those arguments, it will be exactly the reverse of that in which

reason, in the progress of its development, attains to them- the order

in which they are placed above. For it will be made manifest to the

reader that, although experience presents the occasion and the

starting-point, it is the transcendental idea of reason which guides

it in its pilgrimage and is the goal of all its struggles. I shall

therefore begin with an examination of the transcendental argument,

and afterwards inquire what additional strength has accrued to this

mode of proof from the addition of the empirical element.



  SECTION IV. Of the Impossibility of an Ontological Proof of

                    the Existence of God.



  It is evident from what has been said that the conception of an

absolutely necessary being is a mere idea, the objective reality of

which is far from being established by the mere fact that it is a need

of reason. On the contrary, this idea serves merely to indicate a

certain unattainable perfection, and rather limits the operations

than, by the presentation of new objects, extends the sphere of the

understanding. But a strange anomaly meets us at the very threshold;

for the inference from a given existence in general to an absolutely

necessary existence seems to be correct and unavoidable, while the

conditions of the understanding refuse to aid us in forming any

conception of such a being.

  Philosophers have always talked of an absolutely necessary being,

and have nevertheless declined to take the trouble of conceiving

whether- and how- a being of this nature is even cogitable, not to

mention that its existence is actually demonstrable. A verbal

definition of the conception is certainly easy enough: it is something

the non-existence of which is impossible. But does this definition

throw any light upon the conditions which render it impossible to

cogitate the non-existence of a thing- conditions which we wish to

ascertain, that we may discover whether we think anything in the

conception of such a being or not? For the mere fact that I throw

away, by means of the word unconditioned, all the conditions which the

understanding habitually requires in order to regard anything as

necessary, is very far from making clear whether by means of the

conception of the unconditionally necessary I think of something, or

really of nothing at all.

  Nay, more, this chance-conception, now become so current, many

have endeavoured to explain by examples which seemed to render any

inquiries regarding its intelligibility quite needless. Every

geometrical proposition- a triangle has three angles- it was said,

is absolutely necessary; and thus people talked of an object which lay

out of the sphere of our understanding as if it were perfectly plain

what the conception of such a being meant.

  All the examples adduced have been drawn, without exception, from

judgements, and not from things. But the unconditioned necessity of

a judgement does not form the absolute necessity of a thing. On the

contrary, the absolute necessity of a judgement is only a

conditioned necessity of a thing, or of the predicate in a

judgement. The proposition above-mentioned does not enounce that three

angles necessarily exist, but, upon condition that a triangle

exists, three angles must necessarily exist- in it. And thus this

logical necessity has been the source of the greatest delusions.

Having formed an a priori conception of a thing, the content of

which was made to embrace existence, we believed ourselves safe in

concluding that, because existence belongs necessarily to the object

of the conception (that is, under the condition of my positing this

thing as given), the existence of the thing is also posited

necessarily, and that it is therefore absolutely necessary- merely

because its existence has been cogitated in the conception.

  If, in an identical judgement, I annihilate the predicate in

thought, and retain the subject, a contradiction is the result; and

hence I say, the former belongs necessarily to the latter. But if I

suppress both subject and predicate in thought, no contradiction

arises; for there is nothing at all, and therefore no means of forming

a contradiction. To suppose the existence of a triangle and not that

of its three angles, is self-contradictory; but to suppose the

non-existence of both triangle and angles is perfectly admissible. And

so is it with the conception of an absolutely necessary being.

Annihilate its existence in thought, and you annihilate the thing

itself with all its predicates; how then can there be any room for

contradiction? Externally, there is nothing to give rise to a

contradiction, for a thing cannot be necessary externally; nor

internally, for, by the annihilation or suppression of the thing

itself, its internal properties are also annihilated. God is

omnipotent- that is a necessary judgement. His omnipotence cannot be

denied, if the existence of a Deity is posited- the existence, that

is, of an infinite being, the two conceptions being identical. But

when you say, God does not exist, neither omnipotence nor any other

predicate is affirmed; they must all disappear with the subject, and

in this judgement there cannot exist the least self-contradiction.

  You have thus seen that when the predicate of a judgement is

annihilated in thought along with the subject, no internal

contradiction can arise, be the predicate what it may. There is no

possibility of evading the conclusion- you find yourselves compelled

to declare: There are certain subjects which cannot be annihilated

in thought. But this is nothing more than saying: There exist subjects

which are absolutely necessary- the very hypothesis which you are

called upon to establish. For I find myself unable to form the

slightest conception of a thing which when annihilated in thought with

all its predicates, leaves behind a contradiction; and contradiction

is the only criterion of impossibility in the sphere of pure a

priori conceptions.

  Against these general considerations, the justice of which no one

can dispute, one argument is adduced, which is regarded as

furnishing a satisfactory demonstration from the fact. It is

affirmed that there is one and only one conception, in which the

non-being or annihilation of the object is self-contradictory, and

this is the conception of an ens realissimum. It possesses, you say,

all reality, and you feel yourselves justified in admitting the

possibility of such a being. (This I am willing to grant for the

present, although the existence of a conception which is not

self-contradictory is far from being sufficient to prove the

possibility of an object.)* Now the notion of all reality embraces

in it that of existence; the notion of existence lies, therefore, in

the conception of this possible thing. If this thing is annihilated in

thought, the internal possibility of the thing is also annihilated,

which is self-contradictory.



  *A conception is always possible, if it is not self-contradictory.

This is the logical criterion of possibility, distinguishing the

object of such a conception from the nihil negativum. But it may be,

notwithstanding, an empty conception, unless the objective reality

of this synthesis, but which it is generated, is demonstrated; and a

proof of this kind must be based upon principles of possible

experience, and not upon the principle of analysis or contradiction.

This remark may be serviceable as a warning against concluding, from

the possibility of a conception- which is logical- the possibility

of a thing- which is real.



  I answer: It is absurd to introduce- under whatever term

disguised- into the conception of a thing, which is to be cogitated

solely in reference to its possibility, the conception of its

existence. If this is admitted, you will have apparently gained the

day, but in reality have enounced nothing but a mere tautology. I ask,

is the proposition, this or that thing (which I am admitting to be

possible) exists, an analytical or a synthetical proposition? If the

former, there is no addition made to the subject of your thought by

the affirmation of its existence; but then the conception in your

minds is identical with the thing itself, or you have supposed the

existence of a thing to be possible, and then inferred its existence

from its internal possibility- which is but a miserable tautology. The

word reality in the conception of the thing, and the word existence in

the conception of the predicate, will not help you out of the

difficulty. For, supposing you were to term all positing of a thing

reality, you have thereby posited the thing with all its predicates in

the conception of the subject and assumed its actual existence, and

this you merely repeat in the predicate. But if you confess, as

every reasonable person must, that every existential proposition is

synthetical, how can it be maintained that the predicate of

existence cannot be denied without contradiction?- a property which is

the characteristic of analytical propositions, alone.

  I should have a reasonable hope of putting an end for ever to this

sophistical mode of argumentation, by a strict definition of the

conception of existence, did not my own experience teach me that the

illusion arising from our confounding a logical with a real

predicate (a predicate which aids in the determination of a thing)

resists almost all the endeavours of explanation and illustration. A

logical predicate may be what you please, even the subject may be

predicated of itself; for logic pays no regard to the content of a

judgement. But the determination of a conception is a predicate, which

adds to and enlarges the conception. It must not, therefore, be

contained in the conception.

  Being is evidently not a real predicate, that is, a conception of

something which is added to the conception of some other thing. It

is merely the positing of a thing, or of certain determinations in it.

Logically, it is merely the copula of a judgement. The proposition,

God is omnipotent, contains two conceptions, which have a certain

object or content; the word is, is no additional predicate- it

merely indicates the relation of the predicate to the subject. Now, if

I take the subject (God) with all its predicates (omnipotence being

one), and say: God is, or, There is a God, I add no new predicate to

the conception of God, I merely posit or affirm the existence of the

subject with all its predicates- I posit the object in relation to

my conception. The content of both is the same; and there is no

addition made to the conception, which expresses merely the

possibility of the object, by my cogitating the object- in the

expression, it is- as absolutely given or existing. Thus the real

contains no more than the possible. A hundred real dollars contain

no more than a hundred possible dollars. For, as the latter indicate

the conception, and the former the object, on the supposition that the

content of the former was greater than that of the latter, my

conception would not be an expression of the whole object, and would

consequently be an inadequate conception of it. But in reckoning my

wealth there may be said to be more in a hundred real dollars than

in a hundred possible dollars- that is, in the mere conception of

them. For the real object- the dollars- is not analytically

contained in my conception, but forms a synthetical addition to my

conception (which is merely a determination of my mental state),

although this objective reality- this existence- apart from my

conceptions, does not in the least degree increase the aforesaid

hundred dollars.

  By whatever and by whatever number of predicates- even to the

complete determination of it- I may cogitate a thing, I do not in

the least augment the object of my conception by the addition of the

statement: This thing exists. Otherwise, not exactly the same, but

something more than what was cogitated in my conception, would

exist, and I could not affirm that the exact object of my conception

had real existence. If I cogitate a thing as containing all modes of

reality except one, the mode of reality which is absent is not added

to the conception of the thing by the affirmation that the thing

exists; on the contrary, the thing exists- if it exist at all- with

the same defect as that cogitated in its conception; otherwise not

that which was cogitated, but something different, exists. Now, if I

cogitate a being as the highest reality, without defect or

imperfection, the question still remains- whether this being exists or

not? For, although no element is wanting in the possible real

content of my conception, there is a defect in its relation to my

mental state, that is, I am ignorant whether the cognition of the

object indicated by the conception is possible a posteriori. And

here the cause of the present difficulty becomes apparent. If the

question regarded an object of sense merely, it would be impossible

for me to confound the conception with the existence of a thing. For

the conception merely enables me to cogitate an object as according

with the general conditions of experience; while the existence of

the object permits me to cogitate it as contained in the sphere of

actual experience. At the same time, this connection with the world of

experience does not in the least augment the conception, although a

possible perception has been added to the experience of the mind.

But if we cogitate existence by the pure category alone, it is not

to be wondered at, that we should find ourselves unable to present any

criterion sufficient to distinguish it from mere possibility.

  Whatever be the content of our conception of an object, it is

necessary to go beyond it, if we wish to predicate existence of the

object. In the case of sensuous objects, this is attained by their

connection according to empirical laws with some one of my

perceptions; but there is no means of cognizing the existence of

objects of pure thought, because it must be cognized completely a

priori. But all our knowledge of existence (be it immediately by

perception, or by inferences connecting some object with a perception)

belongs entirely to the sphere of experience- which is in perfect

unity with itself; and although an existence out of this sphere cannot

be absolutely declared to be impossible, it is a hypothesis the

truth of which we have no means of ascertaining.

  The notion of a Supreme Being is in many respects a highly useful

idea; but for the very reason that it is an idea, it is incapable of

enlarging our cognition with regard to the existence of things. It

is not even sufficient to instruct us as to the possibility of a being

which we do not know to exist. The analytical criterion of

possibility, which consists in the absence of contradiction in

propositions, cannot be denied it. But the connection of real

properties in a thing is a synthesis of the possibility of which an

a priori judgement cannot be formed, because these realities are not

presented to us specifically; and even if this were to happen, a

judgement would still be impossible, because the criterion of the

possibility of synthetical cognitions must be sought for in the

world of experience, to which the object of an idea cannot belong. And

thus the celebrated Leibnitz has utterly failed in his attempt to

establish upon a priori grounds the possibility of this sublime

ideal being.

  The celebrated ontological or Cartesian argument for the existence

of a Supreme Being is therefore insufficient; and we may as well

hope to increase our stock of knowledge by the aid of mere ideas, as

the merchant to augment his wealth by the addition of noughts to his

cash account.



     SECTION V. Of the Impossibility of a Cosmological Proof

                  of the Existence of God.



  It was by no means a natural course of proceeding, but, on the

contrary, an invention entirely due to the subtlety of the schools, to

attempt to draw from a mere idea a proof of the existence of an object

corresponding to it. Such a course would never have been pursued, were

it not for that need of reason which requires it to suppose the

existence of a necessary being as a basis for the empirical regress,

and that, as this necessity must be unconditioned and a priori, reason

is bound to discover a conception which shall satisfy, if possible,

this requirement, and enable us to attain to the a priori cognition of

such a being. This conception was thought to be found in the idea of

an ens realissimum, and thus this idea was employed for the attainment

of a better defined knowledge of a necessary being, of the existence

of which we were convinced, or persuaded, on other grounds. Thus

reason was seduced from her natural courage; and, instead of

concluding with the conception of an ens realissimum, an attempt was

made to begin with it, for the purpose of inferring from it that

idea of a necessary existence which it was in fact called in to

complete. Thus arose that unfortunate ontological argument, which

neither satisfies the healthy common sense of humanity, nor sustains

the scientific examination of the philosopher.

  The cosmological proof, which we are about to examine, retains the

connection between absolute necessity and the highest reality; but,

instead of reasoning from this highest reality to a necessary

existence, like the preceding argument, it concludes from the given.

unconditioned necessity of some being its unlimited reality. The track

it pursues, whether rational or sophistical, is at least natural,

and not only goes far to persuade the common understanding, but

shows itself deserving of respect from the speculative intellect;

while it contains, at the same time, the outlines of all the arguments

employed in natural theology- arguments which always have been, and

still will be, in use and authority. These, however adorned, and hid

under whatever embellishments of rhetoric and sentiment, are at bottom

identical with the arguments we are at present to discuss. This proof,

termed by Leibnitz the argumentum a contingentia mundi, I shall now

lay before the reader, and subject to a strict examination.

  It is framed in the following manner: If something exists, an

absolutely necessary being must likewise exist. Now I, at least,

exist. Consequently, there exists an absolutely necessary being. The

minor contains an experience, the major reasons from a general

experience to the existence of a necessary being.* Thus this

argument really begins at experience, and is not completely a

priori, or ontological. The object of all possible experience being

the world, it is called the cosmological proof. It contains no

reference to any peculiar property of sensuous objects, by which

this world of sense might be distinguished from other possible worlds;

and in this respect it differs from the physico-theological proof,

which is based upon the consideration of the peculiar constitution

of our sensuous world.



  *This inference is too well known to require more detailed

discussion. It is based upon the spurious transcendental law of

causality, that everything which is contingent has a cause, which,

if itself contingent, must also have a cause; and so on, till the

series of subordinated causes must end with an absolutely necessary

cause, without which it would not possess completeness.



  The proof proceeds thus: A necessary being can be determined only in

one way, that is, it can be determined by only one of all possible

opposed predicates; consequently, it must be completely determined

in and by its conception. But there is only a single conception of a

thing possible, which completely determines the thing a priori: that

is, the conception of the ens realissimum. It follows that the

conception of the ens realissimum is the only conception by and in

which we can cogitate a necessary being. Consequently, a Supreme Being

necessarily exists.

  In this cosmological argument are assembled so many sophistical

propositions that speculative reason seems to have exerted in it all

her dialectical skill to produce a transcendental illusion of the most

extreme character. We shall postpone an investigation of this argument

for the present, and confine ourselves to exposing the stratagem by

which it imposes upon us an old argument in a new dress, and appeals

to the agreement of two witnesses, the one with the credentials of

pure reason, and the other with those of empiricism; while, in fact,

it is only the former who has changed his dress and voice, for the

purpose of passing himself off for an additional witness. That it

may possess a secure foundation, it bases its conclusions upon

experience, and thus appears to be completely distinct from the

ontological argument, which places its confidence entirely in pure a

priori conceptions. But this experience merely aids reason in making

one step- to the existence of a necessary being. What the properties

of this being are cannot be learned from experience; and therefore

reason abandons it altogether, and pursues its inquiries in the sphere

of pure conception, for the purpose of discovering what the properties

of an absolutely necessary being ought to be, that is, what among

all possible things contain the conditions (requisita) of absolute

necessity. Reason believes that it has discovered these requisites

in the conception of an ens realissimum- and in it alone, and hence

concludes: The ens realissimum is an absolutely necessary being. But

it is evident that reason has here presupposed that the conception

of an ens realissimum is perfectly adequate to the conception of a

being of absolute necessity, that is, that we may infer the

existence of the latter from that of the former- a proposition which

formed the basis of the ontological argument, and which is now

employed in the support of the cosmological argument, contrary to

the wish and professions of its inventors. For the existence of an

absolutely necessary being is given in conceptions alone. But if I

say: "The conception of the ens realissimum is a conception of this

kind, and in fact the only conception which is adequate to our idea of

a necessary being," I am obliged to admit, that the latter may be

inferred from the former. Thus it is properly the ontological argument

which figures in the cosmological, and constitutes the whole

strength of the latter; while the spurious basis of experience has

been of no further use than to conduct us to the conception of

absolute necessity, being utterly insufficient to demonstrate the

presence of this attribute in any determinate existence or thing.

For when we propose to ourselves an aim of this character, we must

abandon the sphere of experience, and rise to that of pure

conceptions, which we examine with the purpose of discovering

whether any one contains the conditions of the possibility of an

absolutely necessary being. But if the possibility of such a being

is thus demonstrated, its existence is also proved; for we may then

assert that, of all possible beings there is one which possesses the

attribute of necessity- in other words, this being possesses an

absolutely necessary existence.

  All illusions in an argument are more easily detected when they

are presented in the formal manner employed by the schools, which we

now proceed to do.

  If the proposition: "Every absolutely necessary being is likewise an

ens realissimum," is correct (and it is this which constitutes the

nervus probandi of the cosmological argument), it must, like all

affirmative judgements, be capable of conversion- the conversio per

accidens, at least. It follows, then, that some entia realissima are

absolutely necessary beings. But no ens realissimum is in any

respect different from another, and what is valid of some is valid

of all. In this present case, therefore, I may employ simple

conversion, and say: "Every ens realissimum is a necessary being." But

as this proposition is determined a priori by the conceptions

contained in it, the mere conception of an ens realissimum must

possess the additional attribute of absolute necessity. But this is

exactly what was maintained in the ontological argument, and not

recognized by the cosmological, although it formed the real ground

of its disguised and illusory reasoning.

  Thus the second mode employed by speculative reason of demonstrating

the existence of a Supreme Being, is not only, like the first,

illusory and inadequate, but possesses the additional blemish of an

ignoratio elenchi- professing to conduct us by a new road to the

desired goal, but bringing us back, after a short circuit, to the

old path which we had deserted at its call.

  I mentioned above that this cosmological argument contains a perfect

nest of dialectical assumptions, which transcendental criticism does

not find it difficult to expose and to dissipate. I shall merely

enumerate these, leaving it to the reader, who must by this time be

well practised in such matters, to investigate the fallacies

residing therein.

  The following fallacies, for example, are discoverable in this

mode of proof: 1. The transcendental principle: "Everything that is

contingent must have a cause"- a principle without significance,

except in the sensuous world. For the purely intellectual conception

of the contingent cannot produce any synthetical proposition, like

that of causality, which is itself without significance or

distinguishing characteristic except in the phenomenal world. But in

the present case it is employed to help us beyond the limits of its

sphere. 2. "From the impossibility of an infinite ascending series

of causes in the world of sense a first cause is inferred"; a

conclusion which the principles of the employment of reason do not

justify even in the sphere of experience, and still less when an

attempt is made to pass the limits of this sphere. 3. Reason allows

itself to be satisfied upon insufficient grounds, with regard to the

completion of this series. It removes all conditions (without which,

however, no conception of Necessity can take place); and, as after

this it is beyond our power to form any other conceptions, it

accepts this as a completion of the conception it wishes to form of

the series. 4. The logical possibility of a conception of the total of

reality (the criterion of this possibility being the absence of

contradiction) is confound. ed with the transcendental, which requires

a principle of the practicability of such a synthesis- a principle

which again refers us to the world of experience. And so on.

  The aim of the cosmological argument is to avoid the necessity of

proving the existence of a necessary being priori from mere

conceptions- a proof which must be ontological, and of which we feel

ourselves quite incapable. With this purpose, we reason from an actual

existence- an experience in general, to an absolutely necessary

condition of that existence. It is in this case unnecessary to

demonstrate its possibility. For after having proved that it exists,

the question regarding its possibility is superfluous. Now, when we

wish to define more strictly the nature of this necessary being, we do

not look out for some being the conception of which would enable us to

comprehend the necessity of its being- for if we could do this, an

empirical presupposition would be unnecessary; no, we try to

discover merely the negative condition (conditio sine qua non),

without which a being would not be absolutely necessary. Now this

would be perfectly admissible in every sort of reasoning, from a

consequence to its principle; but in the present case it unfortunately

happens that the condition of absolute necessity can be discovered

in but a single being, the conception of which must consequently

contain all that is requisite for demonstrating the presence of

absolute necessity, and thus entitle me to infer this absolute

necessity a priori. That is, it must be possible to reason conversely,

and say: The thing, to which the conception of the highest reality

belongs, is absolutely necessary. But if I cannot reason thus- and I

cannot, unless I believe in the sufficiency of the ontological

argument- I find insurmountable obstacles in my new path, and am

really no farther than the point from which I set out. The

conception of a Supreme Being satisfies all questions a priori

regarding the internal determinations of a thing, and is for this

reason an ideal without equal or parallel, the general conception of

it indicating it as at the same time an ens individuum among all

possible things. But the conception does not satisfy the question

regarding its existence- which was the purpose of all our inquiries;

and, although the existence of a necessary being were admitted, we

should find it impossible to answer the question: What of all things

in the world must be regarded as such?

  It is certainly allowable to admit the existence of an

all-sufficient being- a cause of all possible effects- for the purpose

of enabling reason to introduce unity into its mode and grounds of

explanation with regard to phenomena. But to assert that such a

being necessarily exists, is no longer the modest enunciation of an

admissible hypothesis, but the boldest declaration of an apodeictic

certainty; for the cognition of that which is absolutely necessary

must itself possess that character.

  The aim of the transcendental ideal formed by the mind is either

to discover a conception which shall harmonize with the idea of

absolute necessity, or a conception which shall contain that idea.

If the one is possible, so is the other; for reason recognizes that

alone as absolutely necessary which is necessary from its

conception. But both attempts are equally beyond our power- we find it

impossible to satisfy the understanding upon this point, and as

impossible to induce it to remain at rest in relation to this

incapacity.

  Unconditioned necessity, which, as the ultimate support and stay

of all existing things, is an indispensable requirement of the mind,

is an abyss on the verge of which human reason trembles in dismay.

Even the idea of eternity, terrible and sublime as it is, as

depicted by Haller, does not produce upon the mental vision such a

feeling of awe and terror; for, although it measures the duration of

things, it does not support them. We cannot bear, nor can we rid

ourselves of the thought that a being, which we regard as the greatest

of all possible existences, should say to himself: I am from

eternity to eternity; beside me there is nothing, except that which

exists by my will; whence then am I? Here all sinks away from under

us; and the greatest, as the smallest, perfection, hovers without stay

or footing in presence of the speculative reason, which finds it as

easy to part with the one as with the other.

  Many physical powers, which evidence their existence by their

effects, are perfectly inscrutable in their nature; they elude all our

powers of observation. The transcendental object which forms the basis

of phenomena, and, in connection with it, the reason why our

sensibility possesses this rather than that particular kind of

conditions, are and must ever remain hidden from our mental vision;

the fact is there, the reason of the fact we cannot see. But an

ideal of pure reason cannot be termed mysterious or inscrutable,

because the only credential of its reality is the need of it felt by

reason, for the purpose of giving completeness to the world of

synthetical unity. An ideal is not even given as a cogitable object,

and therefore cannot be inscrutable; on the contrary, it must, as a

mere idea, be based on the constitution of reason itself, and on

this account must be capable of explanation and solution. For the very

essence of reason consists in its ability to give an account, of all

our conceptions, opinions, and assertions- upon objective, or, when

they happen to be illusory and fallacious, upon subjective grounds.



     Detection and Explanation of the Dialectical Illusion in

       all Transcendental Arguments for the Existence of a

       Necessary Being.



  Both of the above arguments are transcendental; in other words, they

do not proceed upon empirical principles. For, although the

cosmological argument professed to lay a basis of experience for its

edifice of reasoning, it did not ground its procedure upon the

peculiar constitution of experience, but upon pure principles of

reason- in relation to an existence given by empirical

consciousness; utterly abandoning its guidance, however, for the

purpose of supporting its assertions entirely upon pure conceptions.

Now what is the cause, in these transcendental arguments, of the

dialectical, but natural, illusion, which connects the conceptions

of necessity and supreme reality, and hypostatizes that which cannot

be anything but an idea? What is the cause of this unavoidable step on

the part of reason, of admitting that some one among all existing

things must be necessary, while it falls back from the assertion of

the existence of such a being as from an abyss? And how does reason

proceed to explain this anomaly to itself, and from the wavering

condition of a timid and reluctant approbation- always again

withdrawn- arrive at a calm and settled insight into its cause?

  It is something very remarkable that, on the supposition that

something exists, I cannot avoid the inference that something exists

necessarily. Upon this perfectly natural- but not on that account

reliable- inference does the cosmological argument rest. But, let me

form any conception whatever of a thing, I find that I cannot cogitate

the existence of the thing as absolutely necessary, and that nothing

prevents me- be the thing or being what it may- from cogitating its

non-existence. I may thus be obliged to admit that all existing things

have a necessary basis, while I cannot cogitate any single or

individual thing as necessary. In other words, I can never complete

the regress through the conditions of existence, without admitting the

existence of a necessary being; but, on the other hand, I cannot

make a commencement from this being.

  If I must cogitate something as existing necessarily as the basis of

existing things, and yet am not permitted to cogitate any individual

thing as in itself necessary, the inevitable inference is that

necessity and contingency are not properties of things themselves-

otherwise an internal contradiction would result; that consequently

neither of these principles are objective, but merely subjective

principles of reason- the one requiring us to seek for a necessary

ground for everything that exists, that is, to be satisfied with no

other explanation than that which is complete a priori, the other

forbidding us ever to hope for the attainment of this completeness,

that is, to regard no member of the empirical world as

unconditioned. In this mode of viewing them, both principles, in their

purely heuristic and regulative character, and as concerning merely

the formal interest of reason, are quite consistent with each other.

The one says: "You must philosophize upon nature," as if there existed

a necessary primal basis of all existing things, solely for the

purpose of introducing systematic unity into your knowledge, by

pursuing an idea of this character- a foundation which is

arbitrarily admitted to be ultimate; while the other warns you to

consider no individual determination, concerning the existence of

things, as such an ultimate foundation, that is, as absolutely

necessary, but to keep the way always open for further progress in the

deduction, and to treat every determination as determined by some

other. But if all that we perceive must be regarded as conditionally

necessary, it is impossible that anything which is empirically given

should be absolutely necessary.

  It follows from this that you must accept the absolutely necessary

as out of and beyond the world, inasmuch as it is useful only as a

principle of the highest possible unity in experience, and you

cannot discover any such necessary existence in the would, the

second rule requiring you to regard all empirical causes of unity as

themselves deduced.

  The philosophers of antiquity regarded all the forms of nature as

contingent; while matter was considered by them, in accordance with

the judgement of the common reason of mankind, as primal and

necessary. But if they had regarded matter, not relatively- as the

substratum of phenomena, but absolutely and in itself- as an

independent existence, this idea of absolute necessity would have

immediately disappeared. For there is nothing absolutely connecting

reason with such an existence; on the contrary, it can annihilate it

in thought, always and without self-contradiction. But in thought

alone lay the idea of absolute necessity. A regulative principle must,

therefore, have been at the foundation of this opinion. In fact,

extension and impenetrability- which together constitute our

conception of matter- form the supreme empirical principle of the

unity of phenomena, and this principle, in so far as it is empirically

unconditioned, possesses the property of a regulative principle.

But, as every determination of matter which constitutes what is real

in it- and consequently impenetrability- is an effect, which must have

a cause, and is for this reason always derived, the notion of matter

cannot harmonize with the idea of a necessary being, in its

character of the principle of all derived unity. For every one of

its real properties, being derived, must be only conditionally

necessary, and can therefore be annihilated in thought; and thus the

whole existence of matter can be so annihilated or suppressed. If this

were not the case, we should have found in the world of phenomena

the highest ground or condition of unity- which is impossible,

according to the second regulative principle. It follows that

matter, and, in general, all that forms part of the world of sense,

cannot be a necessary primal being, nor even a principle of

empirical unity, but that this being or principle must have its

place assigned without the world. And, in this way, we can proceed

in perfect confidence to deduce the phenomena of the world and their

existence from other phenomena, just as if there existed no

necessary being; and we can at the same time, strive without ceasing

towards the attainment of completeness for our deduction, just as if

such a being- the supreme condition of all existences- were

presupposed by the mind.

  These remarks will have made it evident to the reader that the ideal

of the Supreme Being, far from being an enouncement of the existence

of a being in itself necessary, is nothing more than a regulative

principle of reason, requiring us to regard all connection existing

between phenomena as if it had its origin from an all-sufficient

necessary cause, and basing upon this the rule of a systematic and

necessary unity in the explanation of phenomena. We cannot, at the

same time, avoid regarding, by a transcendental subreptio, this formal

principle as constitutive, and hypostatizing this unity. Precisely

similar is the case with our notion of space. Space is the primal

condition of all forms, which are properly just so many different

limitations of it; and thus, although it is merely a principle of

sensibility, we cannot help regarding it as an absolutely necessary

and self-subsistent thing- as an object given a priori in itself. In

the same way, it is quite natural that, as the systematic unity of

nature cannot be established as a principle for the empirical

employment of reason, unless it is based upon the idea of an ens

realissimum, as the supreme cause, we should regard this idea as a

real object, and this object, in its character of supreme condition,

as absolutely necessary, and that in this way a regulative should be

transformed into a constitutive principle. This interchange becomes

evident when I regard this supreme being, which, relatively to the

world, was absolutely (unconditionally) necessary, as a thing per

se. In this case, I find it impossible to represent this necessity

in or by any conception, and it exists merely in my own mind, as the

formal condition of thought, but not as a material and hypostatic

condition of existence.



  SECTION VI. Of the Impossibility of a Physico-Theological Proof.



  If, then, neither a pure conception nor the general experience of an

existing being can provide a sufficient basis for the proof of the

existence of the Deity, we can make the attempt by the only other

mode- that of grounding our argument upon a determinate experience

of the phenomena of the present world, their constitution and

disposition, and discover whether we can thus attain to a sound

conviction of the existence of a Supreme Being. This argument we shall

term the physico-theological argument. If it is shown to be

insufficient, speculative reason cannot present us with any

satisfactory proof of the existence of a being corresponding to our

transcendental idea.

  It is evident from the remarks that have been made in the

preceding sections, that an answer to this question will be far from

being difficult or unconvincing. For how can any experience be

adequate with an idea? The very essence of an idea consists in the

fact that no experience can ever be discovered congruent or adequate

with it. The transcendental idea of a necessary and all-sufficient

being is so immeasurably great, so high above all that is empirical,

which is always conditioned, that we hope in vain to find materials in

the sphere of experience sufficiently ample for our conception, and in

vain seek the unconditioned among things that are conditioned, while

examples, nay, even guidance is denied us by the laws of empirical

synthesis.

  If the Supreme Being forms a link in the chain of empirical

conditions, it must be a member of the empirical series, and, like the

lower members which it precedes, have its origin in some higher member

of the series. If, on the other hand, we disengage it from the

chain, and cogitate it as an intelligible being, apart from the series

of natural causes- how shall reason bridge the abyss that separates

the latter from the former? All laws respecting the regress from

effects to causes, all synthetical additions to our knowledge relate

solely to possible experience and the objects of the sensuous world,

and, apart from them, are without significance.

  The world around us opens before our view so magnificent a spectacle

of order, variety, beauty, and conformity to ends, that whether we

pursue our observations into the infinity of space in the one

direction, or into its illimitable divisions in the other, whether

we regard the world in its greatest or its least manifestations-

even after we have attained to the highest summit of knowledge which

our weak minds can reach, we find that language in the presence of

wonders so inconceivable has lost its force, and number its power to

reckon, nay, even thought fails to conceive adequately, and our

conception of the whole dissolves into an astonishment without power

of expression- all the more eloquent that it is dumb. Everywhere

around us we observe a chain of causes and effects, of means and ends,

of death and birth; and, as nothing has entered of itself into the

condition in which we find it, we are constantly referred to some

other thing, which itself suggests the same inquiry regarding its

cause, and thus the universe must sink into the abyss of

nothingness, unless we admit that, besides this infinite chain of

contingencies, there exists something that is primal and

self-subsistent- something which, as the cause of this phenomenal

world, secures its continuance and preservation.

  This highest cause- what magnitude shall we attribute to it? Of

the content of the world we are ignorant; still less can we estimate

its magnitude by comparison with the sphere of the possible. But

this supreme cause being a necessity of the human mind, what is

there to prevent us from attributing to it such a degree of perfection

as to place it above the sphere of all that is possible? This we can

easily do, although only by the aid of the faint outline of an

abstract conception, by representing this being to ourselves as

containing in itself, as an individual substance, all possible

perfection- a conception which satisfies that requirement of reason

which demands parsimony in principles, which is free from

self-contradiction, which even contributes to the extension of the

employment of reason in experience, by means of the guidance

afforded by this idea to order and system, and which in no respect

conflicts with any law of experience.

  This argument always deserves to be mentioned with respect. It is

the oldest, the clearest, and that most in conformity with the

common reason of humanity. It animates the study of nature, as it

itself derives its existence and draws ever new strength from that

source. It introduces aims and ends into a sphere in which our

observation could not of itself have discovered them, and extends

our knowledge of nature, by directing our attention to a unity, the

principle of which lies beyond nature. This knowledge of nature

again reacts upon this idea- its cause; and thus our belief in a

divine author of the universe rises to the power of an irresistible

conviction.

  For these reasons it would be utterly hopeless to attempt to rob

this argument of the authority it has always enjoyed. The mind,

unceasingly elevated by these considerations, which, although

empirical, are so remarkably powerful, and continually adding to their

force, will not suffer itself to be depressed by the doubts

suggested by subtle speculation; it tears itself out of this state

of uncertainty, the moment it casts a look upon the wondrous forms

of nature and the majesty of the universe, and rises from height to

height, from condition to condition, till it has elevated itself to

the supreme and unconditioned author of all.

  But although we have nothing to object to the reasonableness and

utility of this procedure, but have rather to commend and encourage

it, we cannot approve of the claims which this argument advances to

demonstrative certainty and to a reception upon its own merits,

apart from favour or support by other arguments. Nor can it injure the

cause of morality to endeavour to lower the tone of the arrogant

sophist, and to teach him that modesty and moderation which are the

properties of a belief that brings calm and content into the mind,

without prescribing to it an unworthy subjection. I maintain, then,

that the physico-theological argument is insufficient of itself to

prove the existence of a Supreme Being, that it must entrust this to

the ontological argument- to which it serves merely as an

introduction, and that, consequently, this argument contains the

only possible ground of proof (possessed by speculative reason) for

the existence of this being.

  The chief momenta in the physico-theological argument are as follow:

1. We observe in the world manifest signs of an arrangement full of

purpose, executed with great wisdom, and argument in whole of a

content indescribably various, and of an extent without limits. 2.

This arrangement of means and ends is entirely foreign to the things

existing in the world- it belongs to them merely as a contingent

attribute; in other words, the nature of different things could not of

itself, whatever means were employed, harmoniously tend towards

certain purposes, were they not chosen and directed for these purposes

by a rational and disposing principle, in accordance with certain

fundamental ideas. 3. There exists, therefore, a sublime and wise

cause (or several), which is not merely a blind, all-powerful

nature, producing the beings and events which fill the world in

unconscious fecundity, but a free and intelligent cause of the

world. 4. The unity of this cause may be inferred from the unity of

the reciprocal relation existing between the parts of the world, as

portions of an artistic edifice- an inference which all our

observation favours, and all principles of analogy support.

  In the above argument, it is inferred from the analogy of certain

products of nature with those of human art, when it compels Nature

to bend herself to its purposes, as in the case of a house, a ship, or

a watch, that the same kind of causality- namely, understanding and

will- resides in nature. It is also declared that the internal

possibility of this freely-acting nature (which is the source of all

art, and perhaps also of human reason) is derivable from another and

superhuman art- a conclusion which would perhaps be found incapable of

standing the test of subtle transcendental criticism. But to neither

of these opinions shall we at present object. We shall only remark

that it must be confessed that, if we are to discuss the subject of

cause at all, we cannot proceed more securely than with the guidance

of the analogy subsisting between nature and such products of

design- these being the only products whose causes and modes of

organization are completely known to us. Reason would be unable to

satisfy her own requirements, if she passed from a causality which she

does know, to obscure and indemonstrable principles of explanation

which she does not know.

  According to the physico-theological argument, the connection and

harmony existing in the world evidence the contingency of the form

merely, but not of the matter, that is, of the substance of the world.

To establish the truth of the latter opinion, it would be necessary to

prove that all things would be in themselves incapable of this harmony

and order, unless they were, even as regards their substance, the

product of a supreme wisdom. But this would require very different

grounds of proof from those presented by the analogy with human art.

This proof can at most, therefore, demonstrate the existence of an

architect of the world, whose efforts are limited by the

capabilities of the material with which he works, but not of a creator

of the world, to whom all things are subject. Thus this argument is

utterly insufficient for the task before us- a demonstration of the

existence of an all-sufficient being. If we wish to prove the

contingency of matter, we must have recourse to a transcendental

argument, which the physicotheological was constructed expressly to

avoid.

  We infer, from the order and design visible in the universe, as a

disposition of a thoroughly contingent character, the existence of a

cause proportionate thereto. The conception of this cause must contain

certain determinate qualities, and it must therefore be regarded as

the conception of a being which possesses all power, wisdom, and so

on, in one word, all perfection- the conception, that is, of an

all-sufficient being. For the predicates of very great, astonishing,

or immeasurable power and excellence, give us no determinate

conception of the thing, nor do they inform us what the thing may be

in itself. They merely indicate the relation existing between the

magnitude of the object and the observer, who compares it with himself

and with his own power of comprehension, and are mere expressions of

praise and reverence, by which the object is either magnified, or

the observing subject depreciated in relation to the object. Where

we have to do with the magnitude (of the perfection) of a thing, we

can discover no determinate conception, except that which

comprehends all possible perfection or completeness, and it is only

the total (omnitudo) of reality which is completely determined in

and through its conception alone.

  Now it cannot be expected that any one will be bold enough to

declare that he has a perfect insight into the relation which the

magnitude of the world he contemplates bears (in its extent as well as

in its content) to omnipotence, into that of the order and design in

the world to the highest wisdom, and that of the unity of the world to

the absolute unity of a Supreme Being. Physico-theology is therefore

incapable of presenting a determinate conception of a supreme cause of

the world, and is therefore insufficient as a principle of theology- a

theology which is itself to be the basis of religion.

  The attainment of absolute totality is completely impossible on

the path of empiricism. And yet this is the path pursued in the

physicotheological argument. What means shall we employ to bridge

the abyss?

  After elevating ourselves to admiration of the magnitude of the

power, wisdom, and other attributes of the author of the world, and

finding we can advance no further, we leave the argument on

empirical grounds, and proceed to infer the contingency of the world

from the order and conformity to aims that are observable in it.

From this contingency we infer, by the help of transcendental

conceptions alone, the existence of something absolutely necessary;

and, still advancing, proceed from the conception of the absolute

necessity of the first cause to the completely determined or

determining conception thereof- the conception of an all-embracing

reality. Thus the physico-theological, failing in its undertaking,

recurs in its embarrassment to the cosmological argument; and, as this

is merely the ontological argument in disguise, it executes its design

solely by the aid of pure reason, although it at first professed to

have no connection with this faculty and to base its entire

procedure upon experience alone.

  The physico-theologians have therefore no reason to regard with such

contempt the transcendental mode of argument, and to look down upon

it, with the conceit of clear-sighted observers of nature, as the

brain-cobweb of obscure speculatists. For, if they reflect upon and

examine their own arguments, they will find that, after following

for some time the path of nature and experience, and discovering

themselves no nearer their object, they suddenly leave this path and

pass into the region of pure possibility, where they hope to reach

upon the wings of ideas what had eluded all their empirical

investigations. Gaining, as they think, a firm footing after this

immense leap, they extend their determinate conception- into the

possession of which they have come, they know not how- over the

whole sphere of creation, and explain their ideal, which is entirely a

product of pure reason, by illustrations drawn from experience- though

in a degree miserably unworthy of the grandeur of the object, while

they refuse to acknowledge that they have arrived at this cognition or

hypothesis by a very different road from that of experience.

  Thus the physico-theological is based upon the cosmological, and

this upon the ontological proof of the existence of a Supreme Being;

and as besides these three there is no other path open to

speculative reason, the ontological proof, on the ground of pure

conceptions of reason, is the only possible one, if any proof of a

proposition so far transcending the empirical exercise of the

understanding is possible at all.



    SECTION VII. Critique of all Theology based upon Speculative

                     Principles of Reason.



  If by the term theology I understand the cognition of a primal

being, that cognition is based either upon reason alone (theologia

rationalis) or upon revelation (theologia revelata). The former

cogitates its object either by means of pure transcendental

conceptions, as an ens originarium, realissimum, ens entium, and is

termed transcendental theology; or, by means of a conception derived

from the nature of our own mind, as a supreme intelligence, and must

then be entitled natural theology. The person who believes in a

transcendental theology alone, is termed a deist; he who

acknowledges the possibility of a natural theology also, a theist. The

former admits that we can cognize by pure reason alone the existence

of a Supreme Being, but at the same time maintains that our conception

of this being is purely transcendental, and that all we can say of

it is that it possesses all reality, without being able to define it

more closely. The second asserts that reason is capable of

presenting us, from the analogy with nature, with a more definite

conception of this being, and that its operations, as the cause of all

things, are the results of intelligence and free will. The former

regards the Supreme Being as the cause of the world- whether by the

necessity of his nature, or as a free agent, is left undetermined; the

latter considers this being as the author of the world.

  Transcendental theology aims either at inferring the existence of

a Supreme Being from a general experience, without any closer

reference to the world to which this experience belongs, and in this

case it is called cosmotheology; or it endeavours to cognize the

existence of such a being, through mere conceptions, without the aid

of experience, and is then termed ontotheology.

  Natural theology infers the attributes and the existence of an

author of the world, from the constitution of, the order and unity

observable in, the world, in which two modes of causality must be

admitted to exist- those of nature and freedom. Thus it rises from

this world to a supreme intelligence, either as the principle of all

natural, or of all moral order and perfection. In the former case it

is termed physico-theology, in the latter, ethical or moral-theology.*



  *Not theological ethics; for this science contains ethical laws,

which presuppose the existence of a Supreme Governor of the world;

while moral-theology, on the contrary, is the expression of a

conviction of the existence of a Supreme Being, founded upon ethical

laws.



  As we are wont to understand by the term God not merely an eternal

nature, the operations of which are insensate and blind, but a Supreme

Being, who is the free and intelligent author of all things, and as it

is this latter view alone that can be of interest to humanity, we

might, in strict rigour, deny to the deist any belief in God at all,

and regard him merely as a maintainer of the existence of a primal

being or thing- the supreme cause of all other things. But, as no

one ought to be blamed, merely because he does not feel himself

justified in maintaining a certain opinion, as if he altogether denied

its truth and asserted the opposite, it is more correct- as it is less

harsh- to say, the deist believes in a God, the theist in a living God

(summa intelligentia). We shall now proceed to investigate the sources

of all these attempts of reason to establish the existence of a

Supreme Being.

  It may be sufficient in this place to define theoretical knowledge

or cognition as knowledge of that which is, and practical knowledge as

knowledge of that which ought to be. In this view, the theoretical

employment of reason is that by which I cognize a priori (as

necessary) that something is, while the practical is that by which I

cognize a priori what ought to happen. Now, if it is an indubitably

certain, though at the same time an entirely conditioned truth, that

something is, or ought to happen, either a certain determinate

condition of this truth is absolutely necessary, or such a condition

may be arbitrarily presupposed. In the former case the condition is

postulated (per thesin), in the latter supposed (per hypothesin).

There are certain practical laws- those of morality- which are

absolutely necessary. Now, if these laws necessarily presuppose the

existence of some being, as the condition of the possibility of

their obligatory power, this being must be postulated, because the

conditioned, from which we reason to this determinate condition, is

itself cognized a priori as absolutely necessary. We shall at some

future time show that the moral laws not merely presuppose the

existence of a Supreme Being, but also, as themselves absolutely

necessary in a different relation, demand or postulate it- although

only from a practical point of view. The discussion of this argument

we postpone for the present.

  When the question relates merely to that which is, not to that which

ought to be, the conditioned which is presented in experience is

always cogitated as contingent. For this reason its condition cannot

be regarded as absolutely necessary, but merely as relatively

necessary, or rather as needful; the condition is in itself and a

priori a mere arbitrary presupposition in aid of the cognition, by

reason, of the conditioned. If, then, we are to possess a

theoretical cognition of the absolute necessity of a thing, we

cannot attain to this cognition otherwise than a priori by means of

conceptions; while it is impossible in this way to cognize the

existence of a cause which bears any relation to an existence given in

experience.

  Theoretical cognition is speculative when it relates to an object or

certain conceptions of an object which is not given and cannot be

discovered by means of experience. It is opposed to the cognition of

nature, which concerns only those objects or predicates which can be

presented in a possible experience.

  The principle that everything which happens (the empirically

contingent) must have a cause, is a principle of the cognition of

nature, but not of speculative cognition. For, if we change it into an

abstract principle, and deprive it of its reference to experience

and the empirical, we shall find that it cannot with justice be

regarded any longer as a synthetical proposition, and that it is

impossible to discover any mode of transition from that which exists

to something entirely different- termed cause. Nay, more, the

conception of a cause likewise that of the contingent- loses, in

this speculative mode of employing it, all significance, for its

objective reality and meaning are comprehensible from experience

alone.

  When from the existence of the universe and the things in it the

existence of a cause of the universe is inferred, reason is proceeding

not in the natural, but in the speculative method. For the principle

of the former enounces, not that things themselves or substances,

but only that which happens or their states- as empirically

contingent, have a cause: the assertion that the existence of

substance itself is contingent is not justified by experience, it is

the assertion of a reason employing its principles in a speculative

manner. If, again, I infer from the form of the universe, from the way

in which all things are connected and act and react upon each other,

the existence of a cause entirely distinct from the universe- this

would again be a judgement of purely speculative reason; because the

object in this case- the cause- can never be an object of possible

experience. In both these cases the principle of causality, which is

valid only in the field of experience- useless and even meaningless

beyond this region, would be diverted from its proper destination.

  Now I maintain that all attempts of reason to establish a theology

by the aid of speculation alone are fruitless, that the principles

of reason as applied to nature do not conduct us to any theological

truths, and, consequently, that a rational theology can have no

existence, unless it is founded upon the laws of morality. For all

synthetical principles of the understanding are valid only as immanent

in experience; while the cognition of a Supreme Being necessitates

their being employed transcendentally, and of this the understanding

is quite incapable. If the empirical law of causality is to conduct us

to a Supreme Being, this being must belong to the chain of empirical

objects- in which case it would be, like all phenomena, itself

conditioned. If the possibility of passing the limits of experience be

admitted, by means of the dynamical law of the relation of an effect

to its cause, what kind of conception shall we obtain by this

procedure? Certainly not the conception of a Supreme Being, because

experience never presents us with the greatest of all possible

effects, and it is only an effect of this character that could witness

to the existence of a corresponding cause. If, for the purpose of

fully satisfying the requirements of Reason, we recognize her right to

assert the existence of a perfect and absolutely necessary being, this

can be admitted only from favour, and cannot be regarded as the result

or irresistible demonstration. The physico-theological proof may add

weight to others- if other proofs there are- by connecting speculation

with experience; but in itself it rather prepares the mind for

theological cognition, and gives it a right and natural direction,

than establishes a sure foundation for theology.

  It is now perfectly evident that transcendental questions admit only

of transcendental answers- those presented a priori by pure

conceptions without the least empirical admixture. But the question in

the present case is evidently synthetical- it aims at the extension of

our cognition beyond the bounds of experience- it requires an

assurance respecting the existence of a being corresponding with the

idea in our minds, to which no experience can ever be adequate. Now it

has been abundantly proved that all a priori synthetical cognition

is possible only as the expression of the formal conditions of a

possible experience; and that the validity of all principles depends

upon their immanence in the field of experience, that is, their

relation to objects of empirical cognition or phenomena. Thus all

transcendental procedure in reference to speculative theology is

without result.

  If any one prefers doubting the conclusiveness of the proofs of

our analytic to losing the persuasion of the validity of these old and

time honoured arguments, he at least cannot decline answering the

question- how he can pass the limits of all possible experience by the

help of mere ideas. If he talks of new arguments, or of improvements

upon old arguments, I request him to spare me. There is certainly no

great choice in this sphere of discussion, as all speculative

arguments must at last look for support to the ontological, and I

have, therefore, very little to fear from the argumentative

fecundity of the dogmatical defenders of a non-sensuous reason.

Without looking upon myself as a remarkably combative person, I

shall not decline the challenge to detect the fallacy and destroy

the pretensions of every attempt of speculative theology. And yet

the hope of better fortune never deserts those who are accustomed to

the dogmatical mode of procedure. I shall, therefore, restrict

myself to the simple and equitable demand that such reasoners will

demonstrate, from the nature of the human mind as well as from that of

the other sources of knowledge, how we are to proceed to extend our

cognition completely a priori, and to carry it to that point where

experience abandons us, and no means exist of guaranteeing the

objective reality of our conceptions. In whatever way the

understanding may have attained to a conception, the existence of

the object of the conception cannot be discovered in it by analysis,

because the cognition of the existence of the object depends upon

the object's being posited and given in itself apart from the

conception. But it is utterly impossible to go beyond our

conception, without the aid of experience- which presents to the

mind nothing but phenomena, or to attain by the help of mere

conceptions to a conviction of the existence of new kinds of objects

or supernatural beings.

  But although pure speculative reason is far from sufficient to

demonstrate the existence of a Supreme Being, it is of the highest

utility in correcting our conception of this being- on the supposition

that we can attain to the cognition of it by some other means- in

making it consistent with itself and with all other conceptions of

intelligible objects, clearing it from all that is incompatible with

the conception of an ens summun, and eliminating from it all

limitations or admixtures of empirical elements.

  Transcendental theology is still therefore, notwithstanding its

objective insufficiency, of importance in a negative respect; it is

useful as a test of the procedure of reason when engaged with pure

ideas, no other than a transcendental standard being in this case

admissible. For if, from a practical point of view, the hypothesis

of a Supreme and All-sufficient Being is to maintain its validity

without opposition, it must be of the highest importance to define

this conception in a correct and rigorous manner- as the

transcendental conception of a necessary being, to eliminate all

phenomenal elements (anthropomorphism in its most extended

signification), and at the same time to overflow all contradictory

assertions- be they atheistic, deistic, or anthropomorphic. This is of

course very easy; as the same arguments which demonstrated the

inability of human reason to affirm the existence of a Supreme Being

must be alike sufficient to prove the invalidity of its denial. For it

is impossible to gain from the pure speculation of reason

demonstration that there exists no Supreme Being, as the ground of all

that exists, or that this being possesses none of those properties

which we regard as analogical with the dynamical qualities of a

thinking being, or that, as the anthropomorphists would have us

believe, it is subject to all the limitations which sensibility

imposes upon those intelligences which exist in the world of

experience.

  A Supreme Being is, therefore, for the speculative reason, a mere

ideal, though a faultless one- a conception which perfects and

crowns the system of human cognition, but the objective reality of

which can neither be proved nor disproved by pure reason. If this

defect is ever supplied by a moral theology, the problematic

transcendental theology which has preceded, will have been at least

serviceable as demonstrating the mental necessity existing for the

conception, by the complete determination of it which it has

furnished, and the ceaseless testing of the conclusions of a reason

often deceived by sense, and not always in harmony with its own ideas.

The attributes of necessity, infinitude, unity, existence apart from

the world (and not as a world soul), eternity (free from conditions of

time), omnipresence (free from conditions of space), omnipotence,

and others, are pure transcendental predicates; and thus the

accurate conception of a Supreme Being, which every theology requires,

is furnished by transcendental theology alone.

APPENDIX

                        APPENDIX.



        Of the Regulative Employment of the Ideas of

                      Pure Reason.



  The result of all the dialectical attempts of pure reason not only

confirms the truth of what we have already proved in our

Transcendental Analytic, namely, that all inferences which would

lead us beyond the limits of experience are fallacious and groundless,

but it at the same time teaches us this important lesson, that human

reason has a natural inclination to overstep these limits, and that

transcendental ideas are as much the natural property of the reason as

categories are of the understanding. There exists this difference,

however, that while the categories never mislead us, outward objects

being always in perfect harmony therewith, ideas are the parents of

irresistible illusions, the severest and most subtle criticism being

required to save us from the fallacies which they induce.

  Whatever is grounded in the nature of our powers will be found to be

in harmony with the final purpose and proper employment of these

powers, when once we have discovered their true direction and aim.

We are entitled to suppose, therefore, that there exists a mode of

employing transcendental ideas which is proper and immanent; although,

when we mistake their meaning, and regard them as conceptions of

actual things, their mode of application is transcendent and delusive.

For it is not the idea itself, but only the employment of the idea

in relation to possible experience, that is transcendent or

immanent. An idea is employed transcendently, when it is applied to an

object falsely believed to be adequate with and to correspond to it;

imminently, when it is applied solely to the employment of the

understanding in the sphere of experience. Thus all errors of

subreptio- of misapplication, are to be ascribed to defects of

judgement, and not to understanding or reason.

  Reason never has an immediate relation to an object; it relates

immediately to the understanding alone. It is only through the

understanding that it can be employed in the field of experience. It

does not form conceptions of objects, it merely arranges them and

gives to them that unity which they are capable of possessing when the

sphere of their application has been extended as widely as possible.

Reason avails itself of the conception of the understanding for the

sole purpose of producing totality in the different series. This

totality the understanding does not concern itself with; its only

occupation is the connection of experiences, by which series of

conditions in accordance with conceptions are established. The

object of reason is, therefore, the understanding and its proper

destination. As the latter brings unity into the diversity of

objects by means of its conceptions, so the former brings unity into

the diversity of conceptions by means of ideas; as it sets the final

aim of a collective unity to the operations of the understanding,

which without this occupies itself with a distributive unity alone.

  I accordingly maintain that transcendental ideas can never be

employed as constitutive ideas, that they cannot be conceptions of

objects, and that, when thus considered, they assume a fallacious

and dialectical character. But, on the other hand, they are capable of

an admirable and indispensably necessary application to objects- as

regulative ideas, directing the understanding to a certain aim, the

guiding lines towards which all its laws follow, and in which they all

meet in one point. This point- though a mere idea (focus imaginarius),

that is, not a point from which the conceptions of the understanding

do really proceed, for it lies beyond the sphere of possible

experience- serves, notwithstanding, to give to these conceptions

the greatest possible unity combined with the greatest possible

extension. Hence arises the natural illusion which induces us to

believe that these lines proceed from an object which lies out of

the sphere of empirical cognition, just as objects reflected in a

mirror appear to be behind it. But this illusion- which we may

hinder from imposing upon us- is necessary and unavoidable, if we

desire to see, not only those objects which lie before us, but those

which are at a great distance behind us; that is to say, when, in

the present case, we direct the aims of the understanding, beyond

every given experience, towards an extension as great as can

possibly be attained.

  If we review our cognitions in their entire extent, we shall find

that the peculiar business of reason is to arrange them into a system,

that is to say, to give them connection according to a principle. This

unity presupposes an idea- the idea of the form of a whole (of

cognition), preceding the determinate cognition of the parts, and

containing the conditions which determine a priori to every part its

place and relation to the other parts of the whole system. This

idea, accordingly, demands complete unity in the cognition of the

understanding- not the unity of a contingent aggregate, but that of

a system connected according to necessary laws. It cannot be

affirmed with propriety that this idea is a conception of an object;

it is merely a conception of the complete unity of the conceptions

of objects, in so far as this unity is available to the

understanding as a rule. Such conceptions of reason are not derived

from nature; on the contrary, we employ them for the interrogation and

investigation of nature, and regard our cognition as defective so long

as it is not adequate to them. We admit that such a thing as pure

earth, pure water, or pure air, is not to be discovered. And yet we

require these conceptions (which have their origin in the reason, so

far as regards their absolute purity and completeness) for the purpose

of determining the share which each of these natural causes has in

every phenomenon. Thus the different kinds of matter are all ref erred

to earths, as mere weight; to salts and inflammable bodies, as pure

force; and finally, to water and air, as the vehicula of the former,

or the machines employed by them in their operations- for the

purpose of explaining the chemical action and reaction of bodies in

accordance with the idea of a mechanism. For, although not actually so

expressed, the influence of such ideas of reason is very observable in

the procedure of natural philosophers.

  If reason is the faculty of deducing the particular from the

general, and if the general be certain in se and given, it is only

necessary that the judgement should subsume the particular under the

general, the particular being thus necessarily determined. I shall

term this the demonstrative or apodeictic employment of reason. If,

however, the general is admitted as problematical only, and is a

mere idea, the particular case is certain, but the universality of the

rule which applies to this particular case remains a problem.

Several particular cases, the certainty of which is beyond doubt,

are then taken and examined, for the purpose of discovering whether

the rule is applicable to them; and if it appears that all the

particular cases which can be collected follow from the rule, its

universality is inferred, and at the same time, all the causes which

have not, or cannot be presented to our observation, are concluded

to be of the same character with those which we have observed. This

I shall term the hypothetical employment of the reason.

  The hypothetical exercise of reason by the aid of ideas employed

as problematical conceptions is properly not constitutive. That is

to say, if we consider the subject strictly, the truth of the rule,

which has been employed as an hypothesis, does not follow from the use

that is made of it by reason. For how can we know all the possible

cases that may arise? some of which may, however, prove exceptions

to the universality of the rule. This employment of reason is merely

regulative, and its sole aim is the introduction of unity into the

aggregate of our particular cognitions, and thereby the

approximating of the rule to universality.

  The object of the hypothetical employment of reason is therefore the

systematic unity of cognitions; and this unity is the criterion of the

truth of a rule. On the other hand, this systematic unity- as a mere

idea- is in fact merely a unity projected, not to be regarded as

given, but only in the light of a problem- a problem which serves,

however, as a principle for the various and particular exercise of the

understanding in experience, directs it with regard to those cases

which are not presented to our observation, and introduces harmony and

consistency into all its operations.

  All that we can be certain of from the above considerations is

that this systematic unity is a logical principle, whose aim is to

assist the understanding, where it cannot of itself attain to rules,

by means of ideas, to bring all these various rules under one

principle, and thus to ensure the most complete consistency and

connection that can be attained. But the assertion that objects and

the understanding by which they are cognized are so constituted as

to be determined to systematic unity, that this may be postulated a

priori, without any reference to the interest of reason, and that we

are justified in declaring all possible cognitions- empirical and

others- to possess systematic unity, and to be subject to general

principles from which, notwithstanding their various character, they

are all derivable such an assertion can be founded only upon a

transcendental principle of reason, which would render this systematic

unity not subjectively and logically- in its character of a method,

but objectively necessary.

  We shall illustrate this by an example. The conceptions of the

understanding make us acquainted, among many other kinds of unity,

with that of the causality of a substance, which is termed power.

The different phenomenal manifestations of the same substance appear

at first view to be so very dissimilar that we are inclined to

assume the existence of just as many different powers as there are

different effects- as, in the case of the human mind, we have feeling,

consciousness, imagination, memory, wit, analysis, pleasure, desire

and so on. Now we are required by a logical maxim to reduce these

differences to as small a number as possible, by comparing them and

discovering the hidden identity which exists. We must inquire, for

example, whether or not imagination (connected with consciousness),

memory, wit, and analysis are not merely different forms of

understanding and reason. The idea of a fundamental power, the

existence of which no effort of logic can assure us of, is the problem

to be solved, for the systematic representation of the existing

variety of powers. The logical principle of reason requires us to

produce as great a unity as is possible in the system of our

cognitions; and the more the phenomena of this and the other power are

found to be identical, the more probable does it become, that they are

nothing but different manifestations of one and the same power,

which may be called, relatively speaking, a fundamental power. And

so with other cases.

  These relatively fundamental powers must again be compared with each

other, to discover, if possible, the one radical and absolutely

fundamental power of which they are but the manifestations. But this

unity is purely hypothetical. It is not maintained, that this unity

does really exist, but that we must, in the interest of reason, that

is, for the establishment of principles for the various rules

presented by experience, try to discover and introduce it, so far as

is practicable, into the sphere of our cognitions.

  But the transcendental employment of the understanding would lead us

to believe that this idea of a fundamental power is not problematical,

but that it possesses objective reality, and thus the systematic unity

of the various powers or forces in a substance is demanded by the

understanding and erected into an apodeictic or necessary principle.

For, without having attempted to discover the unity of the various

powers existing in nature, nay, even after all our attempts have

failed, we notwithstanding presuppose that it does exist, and may

be, sooner or later, discovered. And this reason does, not only, as in

the case above adduced, with regard to the unity of substance, but

where many substances, although all to a certain extent homogeneous,

are discoverable, as in the case of matter in general. Here also

does reason presuppose the existence of the systematic unity of

various powers- inasmuch as particular laws of nature are

subordinate to general laws; and parsimony in principles is not merely

an economical principle of reason, but an essential law of nature.

  We cannot understand, in fact, how a logical principle of unity

can of right exist, unless we presuppose a transcendental principle,

by which such a systematic unit- as a property of objects

themselves- is regarded as necessary a priori. For with what right can

reason, in its logical exercise, require us to regard the variety of

forces which nature displays, as in effect a disguised unity, and to

deduce them from one fundamental force or power, when she is free to

admit that it is just as possible that all forces should be

different in kind, and that a systematic unity is not conformable to

the design of nature? In this view of the case, reason would be

proceeding in direct opposition to her own destination, by setting

as an aim an idea which entirely conflicts with the procedure and

arrangement of nature. Neither can we assert that reason has

previously inferred this unity from the contingent nature of

phenomena. For the law of reason which requires us to seek for this

unity is a necessary law, inasmuch as without it we should not possess

a faculty of reason, nor without reason a consistent and

self-accordant mode of employing the understanding, nor, in the

absence of this, any proper and sufficient criterion of empirical

truth. In relation to this criterion, therefore, we must suppose the

idea of the systematic unity of nature to possess objective validity

and necessity.

  We find this transcendental presupposition lurking in different

forms in the principles of philosophers, although they have neither

recognized it nor confessed to themselves its presence. That the

diversities of individual things do not exclude identity of species,

that the various species must be considered as merely different

determinations of a few genera, and these again as divisions of

still higher races, and so on- that, accordingly, a certain systematic

unity of all possible empirical conceptions, in so far as they can

be deduced from higher and more general conceptions, must be sought

for, is a scholastic maxim or logical principle, without which

reason could not be employed by us. For we can infer the particular

from the general, only in so far as general properties of things

constitute the foundation upon which the particular rest.

  That the same unity exists in nature is presupposed by

philosophers in the well-known scholastic maxim, which forbids us

unnecessarily to augment the number of entities or principles (entia

praeter necessitatem non esse multiplicanda). This maxim asserts

that nature herself assists in the establishment of this unity of

reason, and that the seemingly infinite diversity of phenomena

should not deter us from the expectation of discovering beneath this

diversity a unity of fundamental properties, of which the aforesaid

variety is but a more or less determined form. This unity, although

a mere idea, thinkers have found it necessary rather to moderate the

desire than to encourage it. It was considered a great step when

chemists were able to reduce all salts to two main genera- acids and

alkalis; and they regard this difference as itself a mere variety,

or different manifestation of one and the same fundamental material.

The different kinds of earths (stones and even metals) chemists have

endeavoured to reduce to three, and afterwards to two; but still,

not content with this advance, they cannot but think that behind these

diversities there lurks but one genus- nay, that even salts and earths

have a common principle. It might be conjectured that this is merely

an economical plan of reason, for the purpose of sparing itself

trouble, and an attempt of a purely hypothetical character, which,

when successful, gives an appearance of probability to the principle

of explanation employed by the reason. But a selfish purpose of this

kind is easily to be distinguished from the idea, according to which

every one presupposes that this unity is in accordance with the laws

of nature, and that reason does not in this case request, but

requires, although we are quite unable to determine the proper

limits of this unity.

  If the diversity existing in phenomena- a diversity not of form (for

in this they may be similar) but of content- were so great that the

subtlest human reason could never by comparison discover in them the

least similarity (which is not impossible), in this case the logical

law of genera would be without foundation, the conception of a

genus, nay, all general conceptions would be impossible, and the

faculty of the understanding, the exercise of which is restricted to

the world of conceptions, could not exist. The logical principle of

genera, accordingly, if it is to be applied to nature (by which I mean

objects presented to our senses), presupposes a transcendental

principle. In accordance with this principle, homogeneity is

necessarily presupposed in the variety of phenomena (although we are

unable to determine a priori the degree of this homogeneity),

because without it no empirical conceptions, and consequently no

experience, would be possible.

  The logical principle of genera, which demands identity in

phenomena, is balanced by another principle- that of species, which

requires variety and diversity in things, notwithstanding their

accordance in the same genus, and directs the understanding to

attend to the one no less than to the other. This principle (of the

faculty of distinction) acts as a check upon the reason and reason

exhibits in this respect a double and conflicting interest- on the one

hand, the interest in the extent (the interest of generality) in

relation to genera; on the other, that of the content (the interest of

individuality) in relation to the variety of species. In the former

case, the understanding cogitates more under its conceptions, in the

latter it cogitates more in them. This distinction manifests itself

likewise in the habits of thought peculiar to natural philosophers,

some of whom- the remarkably speculative heads- may be said to be

hostile to heterogeneity in phenomena, and have their eyes always

fixed on the unity of genera, while others- with a strong empirical

tendency- aim unceasingly at the analysis of phenomena, and almost

destroy in us the hope of ever being able to estimate the character of

these according to general principles.

  The latter mode of thought is evidently based upon a logical

principle, the aim of which is the systematic completeness of all

cognitions. This principle authorizes me, beginning at the genus, to

descend to the various and diverse contained under it; and in this way

extension, as in the former case unity, is assured to the system.

For if we merely examine the sphere of the conception which

indicates a genus, we cannot discover how far it is possible to

proceed in the division of that sphere; just as it is impossible, from

the consideration of the space occupied by matter, to determine how

far we can proceed in the division of it. Hence every genus must

contain different species, and these again different subspecies; and

as each of the latter must itself contain a sphere (must be of a

certain extent, as a conceptus communis), reason demands that no

species or sub-species is to be considered as the lowest possible. For

a species or sub-species, being always a conception, which contains

only what is common to a number of different things, does not

completely determine any individual thing, or relate immediately to

it, and must consequently contain other conceptions, that is, other

sub-species under it. This law of specification may be thus expressed:

entium varietates non temere sunt minuendae.

  But it is easy to see that this logical law would likewise be

without sense or application, were it not based upon a

transcendental law of specification, which certainly does not

require that the differences existing phenomena should be infinite

in number, for the logical principle, which merely maintains the

indeterminateness of the logical sphere of a conception, in relation

to its possible division, does not authorize this statement; while

it does impose upon the understanding the duty of searching for

subspecies to every species, and minor differences in every

difference. For, were there no lower conceptions, neither could

there be any higher. Now the understanding cognizes only by means of

conceptions; consequently, how far soever it may proceed in

division, never by mere intuition, but always by lower and lower

conceptions. The cognition of phenomena in their complete

determination (which is possible only by means of the understanding)

requires an unceasingly continued specification of conceptions, and

a progression to ever smaller differences, of which abstraction bad

been made in the conception of the species, and still more in that

of the genus.

  This law of specification cannot be deduced from experience; it

can never present us with a principle of so universal an

application. Empirical specification very soon stops in its

distinction of diversities, and requires the guidance of the

transcendental law, as a principle of the reason- a law which

imposes on us the necessity of never ceasing in our search for

differences, even although these may not present themselves to the

senses. That absorbent earths are of different kinds could only be

discovered by obeying the anticipatory law of reason, which imposes

upon the understanding the task of discovering the differences

existing between these earths, and supposes that nature is richer in

substances than our senses would indicate. The faculty of the

understanding belongs to us just as much under the presupposition of

differences in the objects of nature, as under the condition that

these objects are homogeneous, because we could not possess

conceptions, nor make any use of our understanding, were not the

phenomena included under these conceptions in some respects

dissimilar, as well as similar, in their character.

  Reason thus prepares the sphere of the understanding for the

operations of this faculty: 1. By the principle of the homogeneity

of the diverse in higher genera; 2. By the principle of the variety of

the homogeneous in lower species; and, to complete the systematic

unity, it adds, 3. A law of the affinity of all conceptions which

prescribes a continuous transition from one species to every other

by the gradual increase of diversity. We may term these the principles

of the homogeneity, the specification, and the continuity of forms.

The latter results from the union of the two former, inasmuch as we

regard the systematic connection as complete in thought, in the ascent

to higher genera, as well as in the descent to lower species. For

all diversities must be related to each other, as they all spring from

one highest genus, descending through the different gradations of a

more and more extended determination.

  We may illustrate the systematic unity produced by the three logical

principles in the following manner. Every conception may be regarded

as a point, which, as the standpoint of a spectator, has a certain

horizon, which may be said to enclose a number of things that may be

viewed, so to speak, from that centre. Within this horizon there

must be an infinite number of other points, each of which has its

own horizon, smaller and more circumscribed; in other words, every

species contains sub-species, according to the principle of

specification, and the logical horizon consists of smaller horizons

(subspecies), but not of points (individuals), which possess no

extent. But different horizons or genera, which include under them

so many conceptions, may have one common horizon, from which, as

from a mid-point, they may be surveyed; and we may proceed thus,

till we arrive at the highest genus, or universal and true horizon,

which is determined by the highest conception, and which contains

under itself all differences and varieties, as genera, species, and

subspecies.

  To this highest standpoint I am conducted by the law of homogeneity,

as to all lower and more variously-determined conceptions by the law

of specification. Now as in this way there exists no void in the whole

extent of all possible conceptions, and as out of the sphere of

these the mind can discover nothing, there arises from the

presupposition of the universal horizon above mentioned, and its

complete division, the principle: Non datur vacuum formarum. This

principle asserts that there are not different primitive and highest

genera, which stand isolated, so to speak, from each other, but all

the various genera are mere divisions and limitations of one highest

and universal genus; and hence follows immediately the principle:

Datur continuum formarum. This principle indicates that all

differences of species limit each other, and do not admit of

transition from one to another by a saltus, but only through smaller

degrees of the difference between the one species and the other. In

one word, there are no species or sub-species which (in the view of

reason) are the nearest possible to each other; intermediate species

or sub-species being always possible, the difference of which from

each of the former is always smaller than the difference existing

between these.

  The first law, therefore, directs us to avoid the notion that

there exist different primal genera, and enounces the fact of

perfect homogeneity; the second imposes a check upon this tendency

to unity and prescribes the distinction of sub-species, before

proceeding to apply our general conceptions to individuals. The

third unites both the former, by enouncing the fact of homogeneity

as existing even in the most various diversity, by means of the

gradual transition from one species to another. Thus it indicates a

relationship between the different branches or species, in so far as

they all spring from the same stem.

  But this logical law of the continuum specierum (formarum logicarum)

presupposes a transcendental principle (lex continui in natura),

without which the understanding might be led into error, by

following the guidance of the former, and thus perhaps pursuing a path

contrary to that prescribed by nature. This law must, consequently, be

based upon pure transcendental, and not upon empirical,

considerations. For, in the latter case, it would come later than

the system; whereas it is really itself the parent of all that is

systematic in our cognition of nature. These principles are not mere

hypotheses employed for the purpose of experimenting upon nature;

although when any such connection is discovered, it forms a solid

ground for regarding the hypothetical unity as valid in the sphere

of nature- and thus they are in this respect not without their use.

But we go farther, and maintain that it is manifest that these

principles of parsimony in fundamental causes, variety in effects, and

affinity in phenomena, are in accordance both with reason and

nature, and that they are not mere methods or plans devised for the

purpose of assisting us in our observation of the external world.

  But it is plain that this continuity of forms is a mere idea, to

which no adequate object can be discovered in experience. And this for

two reasons. First, because the species in nature are really

divided, and hence form quanta discreta; and, if the gradual

progression through their affinity were continuous, the intermediate

members lying between two given species must be infinite in number,

which is impossible. Secondly, because we cannot make any

determinate empirical use of this law, inasmuch as it does not present

us with any criterion of affinity which could aid us in determining

how far we ought to pursue the graduation of differences: it merely

contains a general indication that it is our duty to seek for and,

if possible, to discover them.

  When we arrange these principles of systematic unity in the order

conformable to their employment in experience, they will stand thus:

Variety, Affinity, Unity, each of them, as ideas, being taken in the

highest degree of their completeness. Reason presupposes the existence

of cognitions of the understanding, which have a direct relation to

experience, and aims at the ideal unity of these cognitions- a unity

which far transcends all experience or empirical notions. The affinity

of the diverse, notwithstanding the differences existing between its

parts, has a relation to things, but a still closer one to the mere

properties and powers of things. For example, imperfect experience may

represent the orbits of the planets as circular. But we discover

variations from this course, and we proceed to suppose that the

planets revolve in a path which, if not a circle, is of a character

very similar to it. That is to say, the movements of those planets

which do not form a circle will approximate more or less to the

properties of a circle, and probably form an ellipse. The paths of

comets exhibit still greater variations, for, so far as our

observation extends, they do not return upon their own course in a

circle or ellipse. But we proceed to the conjecture that comets

describe a parabola, a figure which is closely allied to the

ellipse. In fact, a parabola is merely an ellipse, with its longer

axis produced to an indefinite extent. Thus these principles conduct

us to a unity in the genera of the forms of these orbits, and,

proceeding farther, to a unity as regards the cause of the motions

of the heavenly bodies- that is, gravitation. But we go on extending

our conquests over nature, and endeavour to explain all seeming

deviations from these rules, and even make additions to our system

which no experience can ever substantiate- for example, the theory, in

affinity with that of ellipses, of hyperbolic paths of comets,

pursuing which, these bodies leave our solar system and, passing

from sun to sun, unite the most distant parts of the infinite

universe, which is held together by the same moving power.

  The most remarkable circumstance connected with these principles

is that they seem to be transcendental, and, although only

containing ideas for the guidance of the empirical exercise of reason,

and although this empirical employment stands to these ideas in an

asymptotic relation alone (to use a mathematical term), that is,

continually approximate, without ever being able to attain to them,

they possess, notwithstanding, as a priori synthetical propositions,

objective though undetermined validity, and are available as rules for

possible experience. In the elaboration of our experience, they may

also be employed with great advantage, as heuristic* principles. A

transcendental deduction of them cannot be made; such a deduction

being always impossible in the case of ideas, as has been already

shown.



  *From the Greek, eurhioko.



  We distinguished, in the Transcendental Analytic, the dynamical

principles of the understanding, which are regulative principles of

intuition, from the mathematical, which are constitutive principles of

intuition. These dynamical laws are, however, constitutive in relation

to experience, inasmuch as they render the conceptions without which

experience could not exist possible a priori. But the principles of

pure reason cannot be constitutive even in regard to empirical

conceptions, because no sensuous schema corresponding to them can be

discovered, and they cannot therefore have an object in concreto. Now,

if I grant that they cannot be employed in the sphere of experience,

as constitutive principles, how shall I secure for them employment and

objective validity as regulative principles, and in what way can

they be so employed?

  The understanding is the object of reason, as sensibility is the

object of the understanding. The production of systematic unity in all

the empirical operations of the understanding is the proper occupation

of reason; just as it is the business of the understanding to

connect the various content of phenomena by means of conceptions,

and subject them to empirical laws. But the operations of the

understanding are, without the schemata of sensibility,

undetermined; and, in the same manner, the unity of reason is

perfectly undetermined as regards the conditions under which, and

the extent to which, the understanding ought to carry the systematic

connection of its conceptions. But, although it is impossible to

discover in intuition a schema for the complete systematic unity of

all the conceptions of the understanding, there must be some

analogon of this schema. This analogon is the idea of the maximum of

the division and the connection of our cognition in one principle. For

we may have a determinate notion of a maximum and an absolutely

perfect, all the restrictive conditions which are connected with an

indeterminate and various content having been abstracted. Thus the

idea of reason is analogous with a sensuous schema, with this

difference, that the application of the categories to the schema of

reason does not present a cognition of any object (as is the case with

the application of the categories to sensuous schemata), but merely

provides us with a rule or principle for the systematic unity of the

exercise of the understanding. Now, as every principle which imposes

upon the exercise of the understanding a priori compliance with the

rule of systematic unity also relates, although only in an indirect

manner, to an object of experience, the principles of pure reason will

also possess objective reality and validity in relation to experience.

But they will not aim at determining our knowledge in regard to any

empirical object; they will merely indicate the procedure, following

which the empirical and determinate exercise of the understanding

may be in complete harmony and connection with itself- a result

which is produced by its being brought into harmony with the principle

of systematic unity, so far as that is possible, and deduced from it.

  I term all subjective principles, which are not derived from

observation of the constitution of an object, but from the interest

which Reason has in producing a certain completeness in her

cognition of that object, maxims of reason. Thus there are maxims of

speculative reason, which are based solely upon its speculative

interest, although they appear to be objective principles.

  When principles which are really regulative are regarded as

constitutive, and employed as objective principles, contradictions

must arise; but if they are considered as mere maxims, there is no

room for contradictions of any kind, as they then merely indicate

the different interests of reason, which occasion differences in the

mode of thought. In effect, Reason has only one single interest, and

the seeming contradiction existing between her maxims merely indicates

a difference in, and a reciprocal limitation of, the methods by

which this interest is satisfied.

  This reasoner has at heart the interest of diversity- in

accordance with the principle of specification; another, the

interest of unity- in accordance with the principle of aggregation.

Each believes that his judgement rests upon a thorough insight into

the subject he is examining, and yet it has been influenced solely

by a greater or less degree of adherence to some one of the two

principles, neither of which are objective, but originate solely

from the interest of reason, and on this account to be termed maxims

rather than principles. When I observe intelligent men disputing about

the distinctive characteristics of men, animals, or plants, and even

of minerals, those on the one side assuming the existence of certain

national characteristics, certain well-defined and hereditary

distinctions of family, race, and so on, while the other side maintain

that nature has endowed all races of men with the same faculties and

dispositions, and that all differences are but the result of

external and accidental circumstances- I have only to consider for a

moment the real nature of the subject of discussion, to arrive at

the conclusion that it is a subject far too deep for us to judge of,

and that there is little probability of either party being able to

speak from a perfect insight into and understanding of the nature of

the subject itself. Both have, in reality, been struggling for the

twofold interest of reason; the one maintaining the one interest,

the other the other. But this difference between the maxims of

diversity and unity may easily be reconciled and adjusted; although,

so long as they are regarded as objective principles, they must

occasion not only contradictions and polemic, but place hinderances in

the way of the advancement of truth, until some means is discovered of

reconciling these conflicting interests, and bringing reason into

union and harmony with itself.

  The same is the case with the so-called law discovered by

Leibnitz, and supported with remarkable ability by Bonnet- the law

of the continuous gradation of created beings, which is nothing more

than an inference from the principle of affinity; for observation

and study of the order of nature could never present it to the mind as

an objective truth. The steps of this ladder, as they appear in

experience, are too far apart from each other, and the so-called petty

differences between different kinds of animals are in nature

commonly so wide separations that no confidence can be placed in

such views (particularly when we reflect on the great variety of

things, and the ease with which we can discover resemblances), and

no faith in the laws which are said to express the aims and purposes

of nature. On the other hand, the method of investigating the order of

nature in the light of this principle, and the maxim which requires us

to regard this order- it being still undetermined how far it

extends- as really existing in nature, is beyond doubt a legitimate

and excellent principle of reason- a principle which extends farther

than any experience or observation of ours and which, without giving

us any positive knowledge of anything in the region of experience,

guides us to the goal of systematic unity.



  Of the Ultimate End of the Natural Dialectic of Human Reason.



  The ideas of pure reason cannot be, of themselves and in their own

nature, dialectical; it is from their misemployment alone that

fallacies and illusions arise. For they originate in the nature of

reason itself, and it is impossible that this supreme tribunal for all

the rights and claims of speculation should be itself undeserving of

confidence and promotive of error. It is to be expected, therefore,

that these ideas have a genuine and legitimate aim. It is true, the

mob of sophists raise against reason the cry of inconsistency and

contradiction, and affect to despise the government of that faculty,

because they cannot understand its constitution, while it is to its

beneficial influences alone that they owe the position and the

intelligence which enable them to criticize and to blame its

procedure.

  We cannot employ an a priori conception with certainty, until we

have made a transcendental deduction therefore. The ideas of pure

reason do not admit of the same kind of deduction as the categories.

But if they are to possess the least objective validity, and to

represent anything but mere creations of thought (entia rationis

ratiocinantis), a deduction of them must be possible. This deduction

will complete the critical task imposed upon pure reason; and it is to

this part Of our labours that we now proceed.

  There is a great difference between a thing's being presented to the

mind as an object in an absolute sense, or merely as an ideal

object. In the former case I employ my conceptions to determine the

object; in the latter case nothing is present to the mind but a mere

schema, which does not relate directly to an object, not even in a

hypothetical sense, but which is useful only for the purpose of

representing other objects to the mind, in a mediate and indirect

manner, by means of their relation to the idea in the intellect.

Thus I say the conception of a supreme intelligence is a mere idea;

that is to say, its objective reality does not consist in the fact

that it has an immediate relation to an object (for in this sense we

have no means of establishing its objective validity), it is merely

a schema constructed according to the necessary conditions of the

unity of reason- the schema of a thing in general, which is useful

towards the production of the highest degree of systematic unity in

the empirical exercise of reason, in which we deduce this or that

object of experience from the imaginary object of this idea, as the

ground or cause of the said object of experience. In this way, the

idea is properly a heuristic, and not an ostensive, conception; it

does not give us any information respecting the constitution of an

object, it merely indicates how, under the guidance of the idea, we

ought to investigate the constitution and the relations of objects

in the world of experience. Now, if it can be shown that the three

kinds of transcendental ideas (psychological, cosmological, and

theological), although not relating directly to any object nor

determining it, do nevertheless, on the supposition of the existence

of an ideal object, produce systematic unity in the laws of the

empirical employment of the reason, and extend our empirical

cognition, without ever being inconsistent or in opposition with it-

it must be a necessary maxim of reason to regulate its procedure

according to these ideas. And this forms the transcendental

deduction of all speculative ideas, not as constitutive principles

of the extension of our cognition beyond the limits of our experience,

but as regulative principles of the systematic unity of empirical

cognition, which is by the aid of these ideas arranged and emended

within its own proper limits, to an extent unattainable by the

operation of the principles of the understanding alone.

  I shall make this plainer. Guided by the principles involved in

these ideas, we must, in the first place, so connect all the

phenomena, actions, and feelings of the mind, as if it were a simple

substance, which, endowed with personal identity, possesses a

permanent existence (in this life at least), while its states, among

which those of the body are to be included as external conditions, are

in continual change. Secondly, in cosmology, we must investigate the

conditions of all natural phenomena, internal as well as external,

as if they belonged to a chain infinite and without any prime or

supreme member, while we do not, on this account, deny the existence

of intelligible grounds of these phenomena, although we never employ

them to explain phenomena, for the simple reason that they are not

objects of our cognition. Thirdly, in the sphere of theology, we

must regard the whole system of possible experience as forming an

absolute, but dependent and sensuously-conditioned unity, and at the

same time as based upon a sole, supreme, and all-sufficient ground

existing apart from the world itself- a ground which is a

self-subsistent, primeval and creative reason, in relation to which we

so employ our reason in the field of experience, as if all objects

drew their origin from that archetype of all reason. In other words,

we ought not to deduce the internal phenomena of the mind from a

simple thinking substance, but deduce them from each other under the

guidance of the regulative idea of a simple being; we ought not to

deduce the phenomena, order, and unity of the universe from a

supreme intelligence, but merely draw from this idea of a supremely

wise cause the rules which must guide reason in its connection of

causes and effects.

  Now there is nothing to hinder us from admitting these ideas to

possess an objective and hyperbolic existence, except the cosmological

ideas, which lead reason into an antinomy: the psychological and

theological ideas are not antinomial. They contain no contradiction;

and how, then, can any one dispute their objective reality, since he

who denies it knows as little about their possibility as we who

affirm? And yet, when we wish to admit the existence of a thing, it is

not sufficient to convince ourselves that there is no positive

obstacle in the way; for it cannot be allowable to regard mere

creations of thought, which transcend, though they do not

contradict, all our conceptions, as real and determinate objects,

solely upon the authority of a speculative reason striving to

compass its own aims. They cannot, therefore, be admitted to be real

in themselves; they can only possess a comparative reality- that of

a schema of the regulative principle of the systematic unity of all

cognition. They are to be regarded not as actual things, but as in

some measure analogous to them. We abstract from the object of the

idea all the conditions which limit the exercise of our understanding,

but which, on the other hand, are the sole conditions of our

possessing a determinate conception of any given thing. And thus we

cogitate a something, of the real nature of which we have not the

least conception, but which we represent to ourselves as standing in a

relation to the whole system of phenomena, analogous to that in

which phenomena stand to each other.

  By admitting these ideal beings, we do not really extend our

cognitions beyond the objects of possible experience; we extend merely

the empirical unity of our experience, by the aid of systematic unity,

the schema of which is furnished by the idea, which is therefore

valid- not as a constitutive, but as a regulative principle. For

although we posit a thing corresponding to the idea- a something, an

actual existence- we do not on that account aim at the extension of

our cognition by means of transcendent conceptions. This existence

is purely ideal, and not objective; it is the mere expression of the

systematic unity which is to be the guide of reason in the field of

experience. There are no attempts made at deciding what the ground

of this unity may be, or what the real nature of this imaginary being.

  Thus the transcendental and only determinate conception of God,

which is presented to us by speculative reason, is in the strictest

sense deistic. In other words, reason does not assure us of the

objective validity of the conception; it merely gives us the idea of

something, on which the supreme and necessary unity of all

experience is based. This something we cannot, following the analogy

of a real substance, cogitate otherwise than as the cause of all

things operating in accordance with rational laws, if we regard it

as an individual object; although we should rest contented with the

idea alone as a regulative principle of reason, and make no attempt at

completing the sum of the conditions imposed by thought. This

attempt is, indeed, inconsistent with the grand aim of complete

systematic unity in the sphere of cognition- a unity to which no

bounds are set by reason.

  Hence it happens that, admitting a divine being, I can have no

conception of the internal possibility of its perfection, or of the

necessity of its existence. The only advantage of this admission is

that it enables me to answer all other questions relating to the

contingent, and to give reason the most complete satisfaction as

regards the unity which it aims at attaining in the world of

experience. But I cannot satisfy reason with regard to this hypothesis

itself; and this proves that it is not its intelligence and insight

into the subject, but its speculative interest alone which induces

it to proceed from a point lying far beyond the sphere of our

cognition, for the purpose of being able to consider all objects as

parts of a systematic whole.

  Here a distinction presents itself, in regard to the way in which we

may cogitate a presupposition- a distinction which is somewhat subtle,

but of great importance in transcendental philosophy. I may have

sufficient grounds to admit something, or the existence of

something, in a relative point of view (suppositio relativa),

without being justified in admitting it in an absolute sense

(suppositio absoluta). This distinction is undoubtedly requisite, in

the case of a regulative principle, the necessity of which we

recognize, though we are ignorant of the source and cause of that

necessity, and which we assume to be based upon some ultimate

ground, for the purpose of being able to cogitate the universality

of the principle in a more determinate way. For example, I cogitate

the existence of a being corresponding to a pure transcendental

idea. But I cannot admit that this being exists absolutely and in

itself, because all of the conceptions by which I can cogitate an

object in a determinate manner fall short of assuring me of its

existence; nay, the conditions of the objective validity of my

conceptions are excluded by the idea- by the very fact of its being an

idea. The conceptions of reality, substance, causality, nay, even that

of necessity in existence, have no significance out of the sphere of

empirical cognition, and cannot, beyond that sphere, determine any

object. They may, accordingly, be employed to explain the

possibility of things in the world of sense, but they are utterly

inadequate to explain the possibility of the universe itself

considered as a whole; because in this case the ground of

explanation must lie out of and beyond the world, and cannot,

therefore, be an object of possible experience. Now, I may admit the

existence of an incomprehensible being of this nature- the object of a

mere idea, relatively to the world of sense; although I have no ground

to admit its existence absolutely and in itself. For if an idea

(that of a systematic and complete unity, of which I shall presently

speak more particularly) lies at the foundation of the most extended

empirical employment of reason, and if this idea cannot be

adequately represented in concreto, although it is indispensably

necessary for the approximation of empirical unity to the highest

possible degree- I am not only authorized, but compelled, to realize

this idea, that is, to posit a real object corresponding thereto.

But I cannot profess to know this object; it is to me merely a

something, to which, as the ground of systematic unity in cognition, I

attribute such properties as are analogous to the conceptions employed

by the understanding in the sphere of experience. Following the

analogy of the notions of reality, substance, causality, and

necessity, I cogitate a being, which possesses all these attributes in

the highest degree; and, as this idea is the offspring of my reason

alone, I cogitate this being as self-subsistent reason, and as the

cause of the universe operating by means of ideas of the greatest

possible harmony and unity. Thus I abstract all conditions that

would limit my idea, solely for the purpose of rendering systematic

unity possible in the world of empirical diversity, and thus

securing the widest possible extension for the exercise of reason in

that sphere. This I am enabled to do, by regarding all connections and

relations in the world of sense, as if they were the dispositions of a

supreme reason, of which our reason is but a faint image. I then

proceed to cogitate this Supreme Being by conceptions which have,

properly, no meaning or application, except in the world of sense. But

as I am authorized to employ the transcendental hypothesis of such a

being in a relative respect alone, that is, as the substratum of the

greatest possible unity in experience- I may attribute to a being

which I regard as distinct from the world, such properties as belong

solely to the sphere of sense and experience. For I do not desire, and

am not justified in desiring, to cognize this object of my idea, as it

exists in itself; for I possess no conceptions sufficient for or task,

those of reality, substance, causality, nay, even that of necessity in

existence, losing all significance, and becoming merely the signs of

conceptions, without content and without applicability, when I attempt

to carry them beyond the limits of the world of sense. I cogitate

merely the relation of a perfectly unknown being to the greatest

possible systematic unity of experience, solely for the purpose of

employing it as the schema of the regulative principle which directs

reason in its empirical exercise.

  It is evident, at the first view, that we cannot presuppose the

reality of this transcendental object, by means of the conceptions

of reality, substance, causality, and so on, because these conceptions

cannot be applied to anything that is distinct from the world of

sense. Thus the supposition of a Supreme Being or cause is purely

relative; it is cogitated only in behalf of the systematic unity of

experience; such a being is but a something, of whose existence in

itself we have not the least conception. Thus, too, it becomes

sufficiently manifest why we required the idea of a necessary being in

relation to objects given by sense, although we can never have the

least conception of this being, or of its absolute necessity.

  And now we can clearly perceive the result of our transcendental

dialectic, and the proper aim of the ideas of pure reason- which

become dialectical solely from misunderstanding and inconsiderateness.

Pure reason is, in fact, occupied with itself, and not with any

object. Objects are not presented to it to be embraced in the unity of

an empirical conception; it is only the cognitions of the

understanding that are presented to it, for the purpose of receiving

the unity of a rational conception, that is, of being connected

according to a principle. The unity of reason is the unity of

system; and this systematic unity is not an objective principle,

extending its dominion over objects, but a subjective maxim, extending

its authority over the empirical cognition of objects. The

systematic connection which reason gives to the empirical employment

of the understanding not only advances the extension of that

employment, but ensures its correctness, and thus the principle of a

systematic unity of this nature is also objective, although only in an

indefinite respect (principium vagum). It is not, however, a

constitutive principle, determining an object to which it directly

relates; it is merely a regulative principle or maxim, advancing and

strengthening the empirical exercise of reason, by the opening up of

new paths of which the understanding is ignorant, while it never

conflicts with the laws of its exercise in the sphere of experience.

  But reason cannot cogitate this systematic unity, without at the

same time cogitating an object of the idea- an object that cannot be

presented in any experience, which contains no concrete example of a

complete systematic unity. This being (ens rationis ratiocinatae) is

therefore a mere idea and is not assumed to be a thing which is real

absolutely and in itself. On the contrary, it forms merely the

problematical foundation of the connection which the mind introduces

among the phenomena of the sensuous world. We look upon this

connection, in the light of the above-mentioned idea, as if it drew

its origin from the supposed being which corresponds to the idea.

And yet all we aim at is the possession of this idea as a secure

foundation for the systematic unity of experience- a unity

indispensable to reason, advantageous to the understanding, and

promotive of the interests of empirical cognition.

  We mistake the true meaning of this idea when we regard it as an

enouncement, or even as a hypothetical declaration of the existence of

a real thing, which we are to regard as the origin or ground of a

systematic constitution of the universe. On the contrary, it is left

completely undetermined what the nature or properties of this

so-called ground may be. The idea is merely to be adopted as a point

of view, from which this unity, so essential to reason and so

beneficial to the understanding, may be regarded as radiating. In

one word, this transcendental thing is merely the schema of a

regulative principle, by means of which Reason, so far as in her lies,

extends the dominion of systematic unity over the whole sphere of

experience.

  The first object of an idea of this kind is the ego, considered

merely as a thinking nature or soul. If I wish to investigate the

properties of a thinking being, I must interrogate experience. But I

find that I can apply none of the categories to this object, the

schema of these categories, which is the condition of their

application, being given only in sensuous intuition. But I cannot thus

attain to the cognition of a systematic unity of all the phenomena

of the internal sense. Instead, therefore, of an empirical

conception of what the soul really is, reason takes the conception

of the empirical unity of all thought, and, by cogitating this unity

as unconditioned and primitive, constructs the rational conception

or idea of a simple substance which is in itself unchangeable,

possessing personal identity, and in connection with other real things

external to it; in one word, it constructs the idea of a simple

self-subsistent intelligence. But the real aim of reason in this

procedure is the attainment of principles of systematic unity for

the explanation of the phenomena of the soul. That is, reason

desires to be able to represent all the determinations of the internal

sense as existing in one subject, all powers as deduced from one

fundamental power, all changes as mere varieties in the condition of a

being which is permanent and always the same, and all phenomena in

space as entirely different in their nature from the procedure of

thought. Essential simplicity (with the other attributes predicated of

the ego) is regarded as the mere schema of this regulative

principle; it is not assumed that it is the actual ground of the

properties of the soul. For these properties may rest upon quite

different grounds, of which we are completely ignorant; just as the

above predicates could not give us any knowledge of the soul as it

is in itself, even if we regarded them as valid in respect of it,

inasmuch as they constitute a mere idea, which cannot be represented

in concreto. Nothing but good can result from a psychological idea

of this kind, if we only take proper care not to consider it as more

than an idea; that is, if we regard it as valid merely in relation

to the employment of reason, in the sphere of the phenomena of the

soul. Under the guidance of this idea, or principle, no empirical laws

of corporeal phenomena are called in to explain that which is a

phenomenon of the internal sense alone; no windy hypotheses of the

generation, annihilation, and palingenesis of souls are admitted. Thus

the consideration of this object of the internal sense is kept pure,

and unmixed with heterogeneous elements; while the investigation of

reason aims at reducing all the grounds of explanation employed in

this sphere of knowledge to a single principle. All this is best

effected, nay, cannot be effected otherwise than by means of such a

schema, which requires us to regard this ideal thing as an actual

existence. The psychological idea is, therefore, meaningless and

inapplicable, except as the schema of a regulative conception. For, if

I ask whether the soul is not really of a spiritual nature- it is a

question which has no meaning. From such a conception has been

abstracted, not merely all corporeal nature, but all nature, that

is, all the predicates of a possible experience; and consequently, all

the conditions which enable us to cogitate an object to this

conception have disappeared. But, if these conditions are absent, it

is evident that the conception is meaningless.

  The second regulative idea of speculative reason is the conception

of the universe. For nature is properly the only object presented to

us, in regard to which reason requires regulative principles. Nature

is twofold- thinking and corporeal nature. To cogitate the latter in

regard to its internal possibility, that is, to determine the

application of the categories to it, no idea is required- no

representation which transcends experience. In this sphere, therefore,

an idea is impossible, sensuous intuition being our only guide; while,

in the sphere of psychology, we require the fundamental idea (I),

which contains a priori a certain form of thought namely, the unity of

the ego. Pure reason has, therefore, nothing left but nature in

general, and the completeness of conditions in nature in accordance

with some principle. The absolute totality of the series of these

conditions is an idea, which can never be fully realized in the

empirical exercise of reason, while it is serviceable as a rule for

the procedure of reason in relation to that totality. It requires

us, in the explanation of given phenomena (in the regress or ascent in

the series), to proceed as if the series were infinite in itself, that

is, were prolonged in indefinitum,; while on the other hand, where

reason is regarded as itself the determining cause (in the region of

freedom), we are required to proceed as if we had not before us an

object of sense, but of the pure understanding. In this latter case,

the conditions do not exist in the series of phenomena, but may be

placed quite out of and beyond it, and the series of conditions may be

regarded as if it had an absolute beginning from an intelligible

cause. All this proves that the cosmological ideas are nothing but

regulative principles, and not constitutive; and that their aim is not

to realize an actual totality in such series. The full discussion of

this subject will be found in its proper place in the chapter on the

antinomy of pure reason.

  The third idea of pure reason, containing the hypothesis of a

being which is valid merely as a relative hypothesis, is that of the

one and all-sufficient cause of all cosmological series, in other

words, the idea of God. We have not the slightest ground absolutely to

admit the existence of an object corresponding to this idea; for

what can empower or authorize us to affirm the existence of a being of

the highest perfection- a being whose existence is absolutely

necessary- merely because we possess the conception of such a being?

The answer is: It is the existence of the world which renders this

hypothesis necessary. But this answer makes it perfectly evident

that the idea of this being, like all other speculative ideas, is

essentially nothing more than a demand upon reason that it shall

regulate the connection which it and its subordinate faculties

introduce into the phenomena of the world by principles of

systematic unity and, consequently, that it shall regard all phenomena

as originating from one all-embracing being, as the supreme and

all-sufficient cause. From this it is plain that the only aim of

reason in this procedure is the establishment of its own formal rule

for the extension of its dominion in the world of experience; that

it does not aim at an extension of its cognition beyond the limits

of experience; and that, consequently, this idea does not contain

any constitutive principle.

  The highest formal unity, which is based upon ideas alone, is the

unity of all things- a unity in accordance with an aim or purpose; and

the speculative interest of reason renders it necessary to regard

all order in the world as if it originated from the intention and

design of a supreme reason. This principle unfolds to the view of

reason in the sphere of experience new and enlarged prospects, and

invites it to connect the phenomena of the world according to

teleological laws, and in this way to attain to the highest possible

degree of systematic unity. The hypothesis of a supreme

intelligence, as the sole cause of the universe- an intelligence which

has for us no more than an ideal existence- is accordingly always of

the greatest service to reason. Thus, if we presuppose, in relation to

the figure of the earth (which is round, but somewhat flattened at the

poles),* or that of mountains or seas, wise designs on the part of

an author of the universe, we cannot fail to make, by the light of

this supposition, a great number of interesting discoveries. If we

keep to this hypothesis, as a principle which is purely regulative,

even error cannot be very detrimental. For, in this case, error can

have no more serious consequences than that, where we expected to

discover a teleological connection (nexus finalis), only a

mechanical or physical connection appears. In such a case, we merely

fail to find the additional form of unity we expected, but we do not

lose the rational unity which the mind requires in its procedure in

experience. But even a miscarriage of this sort cannot affect the

law in its general and teleological relations. For although we may

convict an anatomist of an error, when he connects the limb of some

animal with a certain purpose, it is quite impossible to prove in a

single case that any arrangement of nature, be it what it may, is

entirely without aim or design. And thus medical physiology, by the

aid of a principle presented to it by pure reason, extends its very

limited empirical knowledge of the purposes of the different parts

of an organized body so far that it may be asserted with the utmost

confidence, and with the approbation of all reflecting men, that every

organ or bodily part of an animal has its use and answers a certain

design. Now, this is a supposition which, if regarded as of a

constitutive character, goes much farther than any experience or

observation of ours can justify. Hence it is evident that it is

nothing more than a regulative principle of reason, which aims at

the highest degree of systematic unity, by the aid of the idea of a

causality according to design in a supreme cause- a cause which it

regards as the highest intelligence.



  *The advantages which a circular form, in the case of the earth, has

over every other, are well known. But few are aware that the slight

flattening at the poles, which gives it the figure of a spheroid, is

the only cause which prevents the elevations of continents or even

of mountains, perhaps thrown up by some internal convulsion, from

continually altering the position of the axis of the earth- and that

to some considerable degree in a short time. The great protuberance of

the earth under the Equator serves to overbalance the impetus of all

other masses of earth, and thus to preserve the axis of the earth,

so far as we can observe, in its present position. And yet this wise

arrangement has been unthinkingly explained from the equilibrium of

the formerly fluid mass.



  If, however, we neglect this restriction of the idea to a purely

regulative influence, reason is betrayed into numerous errors. For

it has then left the ground of experience, in which alone are to be

found the criteria of truth, and has ventured into the region of the

incomprehensible and unsearchable, on the heights of which it loses

its power and collectedness, because it has completely severed its

connection with experience.

  The first error which arises from our employing the idea of a

Supreme Being as a constitutive (in repugnance to the very nature of

an idea), and not as a regulative principle, is the error of

inactive reason (ignava ratio).* We may so term every principle

which requires us to regard our investigations of nature as absolutely

complete, and allows reason to cease its inquiries, as if it had fully

executed its task. Thus the psychological idea of the ego, when

employed as a constitutive principle for the explanation of the

phenomena of the soul, and for the extension of our knowledge

regarding this subject beyond the limits of experience- even to the

condition of the soul after death- is convenient enough for the

purposes of pure reason, but detrimental and even ruinous to its

interests in the sphere of nature and experience. The dogmatizing

spiritualist explains the unchanging unity of our personality

through all changes of condition from the unity of a thinking

substance, the interest which we take in things and events that can

happen only after our death, from a consciousness of the immaterial

nature of our thinking subject, and so on. Thus he dispenses with

all empirical investigations into the cause of these internal

phenomena, and with all possible explanations of them upon purely

natural grounds; while, at the dictation of a transcendent reason,

he passes by the immanent sources of cognition in experience,

greatly to his own ease and convenience, but to the sacrifice of

all, genuine insight and intelligence. These prejudicial

consequences become still more evident, in the case of the

dogmatical treatment of our idea of a Supreme Intelligence, and the

theological system of nature (physico-theology) which is falsely based

upon it. For, in this case, the aims which we observe in nature, and

often those which we merely fancy to exist, make the investigation

of causes a very easy task, by directing us to refer such and such

phenomena immediately to the unsearchable will and counsel of the

Supreme Wisdom, while we ought to investigate their causes in the

general laws of the mechanism of matter. We are thus recommended to

consider the labour of reason as ended, when we have merely

dispensed with its employment, which is guided surely and safely

only by the order of nature and the series of changes in the world-

which are arranged according to immanent and general laws. This

error may be avoided, if we do not merely consider from the view-point

of final aims certain parts of nature, such as the division and

structure of a continent, the constitution and direction of certain

mountain-chains, or even the organization existing in the vegetable

and animal kingdoms, but look upon this systematic unity of nature

in a perfectly general way, in relation to the idea of a Supreme

Intelligence. If we pursue this advice, we lay as a foundation for all

investigation the conformity to aims of all phenomena of nature in

accordance with universal laws, for which no particular arrangement of

nature is exempt, but only cognized by us with more or less

difficulty; and we possess a regulative principle of the systematic

unity of a teleological connection, which we do not attempt to

anticipate or predetermine. All that we do, and ought to do, is to

follow out the physico-mechanical connection in nature according to

general laws, with the hope of discovering, sooner or later, the

teleological connection also. Thus, and thus only, can the principle

of final unity aid in the extension of the employment of reason in the

sphere of experience, without being in any case detrimental to its

interests.



  *This was the term applied by the old dialecticians to a sophistical

argument, which ran thus: If it is your fate to die of this disease,

you will die, whether you employ a physician or not. Cicero says

that this mode of reasoning has received this appellation, because, if

followed, it puts an end to the employment of reason in the affairs of

life. For a similar reason, I have applied this designation to the

sophistical argument of pure reason.



  The second error which arises from the misconception of the

principle of systematic unity is that of perverted reason (perversa

ratio, usteron roteron rationis). The idea of systematic unity is

available as a regulative principle in the connection of phenomena

according to general natural laws; and, how far soever we have to

travel upon the path of experience to discover some fact or event,

this idea requires us to believe that we have approached all the

more nearly to the completion of its use in the sphere of nature,

although that completion can never be attained. But this error

reverses the procedure of reason. We begin by hypostatizing the

principle of systematic unity, and by giving an anthropomorphic

determination to the conception of a Supreme Intelligence, and then

proceed forcibly to impose aims upon nature. Thus not only does

teleology, which ought to aid in the completion of unity in accordance

with general laws, operate to the destruction of its influence, but it

hinders reason from attaining its proper aim, that is, the proof, upon

natural grounds, of the existence of a supreme intelligent cause. For,

if we cannot presuppose supreme finality in nature a priori, that

is, as essentially belonging to nature, how can we be directed to

endeavour to discover this unity and, rising gradually through its

different degrees, to approach the supreme perfection of an author

of all- a perfection which is absolutely necessary, and therefore

cognizable a priori? The regulative principle directs us to presuppose

systematic unity absolutely and, consequently, as following from the

essential nature of things- but only as a unity of nature, not

merely cognized empirically, but presupposed a priori, although only

in an indeterminate manner. But if I insist on basing nature upon

the foundation of a supreme ordaining Being, the unity of nature is in

effect lost. For, in this case, it is quite foreign and unessential to

the nature of things, and cannot be cognized from the general laws

of nature. And thus arises a vicious circular argument, what ought

to have been proved having been presupposed.

  To take the regulative principle of systematic unity in nature for a

constitutive principle, and to hypostatize and make a cause out of

that which is properly the ideal ground of the consistent and

harmonious exercise of reason, involves reason in inextricable

embarrassments. The investigation of nature pursues its own path under

the guidance of the chain of natural causes, in accordance with the

general laws of nature, and ever follows the light of the idea of an

author of the universe- not for the purpose of deducing the

finality, which it constantly pursues, from this Supreme Being, but to

attain to the cognition of his existence from the finality which it

seeks in the existence of the phenomena of nature, and, if possible,

in that of all things to cognize this being, consequently, as

absolutely necessary. Whether this latter purpose succeed or not,

the idea is and must always be a true one, and its employment, when

merely regulative, must always be accompanied by truthful and

beneficial results.

  Complete unity, in conformity with aims, constitutes absolute

perfection. But if we do not find this unity in the nature of the

things which go to constitute the world of experience, that is, of

objective cognition, consequently in the universal and necessary

laws of nature, how can we infer from this unity the idea of the

supreme and absolutely necessary perfection of a primal being, which

is the origin of all causality? The greatest systematic unity, and

consequently teleological unity, constitutes the very foundation of

the possibility of the most extended employment of human reason. The

idea of unity is therefore essentially and indissolubly connected with

the nature of our reason. This idea is a legislative one; and hence it

is very natural that we should assume the existence of a legislative

reason corresponding to it, from which the systematic unity of nature-

the object of the operations of reason- must be derived.

  In the course of our discussion of the antinomies, we stated that it

is always possible to answer all the questions which pure reason may

raise; and that the plea of the limited nature of our cognition, which

is unavoidable and proper in many questions regarding natural

phenomena, cannot in this case be admitted, because the questions

raised do not relate to the nature of things, but are necessarily

originated by the nature of reason itself, and relate to its own

internal constitution. We can now establish this assertion, which at

first sight appeared so rash, in relation to the two questions in

which reason takes the greatest interest, and thus complete our

discussion of the dialectic of pure reason.

  If, then, the question is asked, in relation to transcendental

theology,* first, whether there is anything distinct from the world,

which contains the ground of cosmical order and connection according

to general laws? The answer is: Certainly. For the world is a sum of

phenomena; there must, therefore, be some transcendental basis of

these phenomena, that is, a basis cogitable by the pure

understanding alone. If, secondly, the question is asked whether

this being is substance, whether it is of the greatest reality,

whether it is necessary, and so forth? I answer that this question

is utterly without meaning. For all the categories which aid me in

forming a conception of an object cannot be employed except in the

world of sense, and are without meaning when not applied to objects of

actual or possible experience. Out of this sphere, they are not

properly conceptions, but the mere marks or indices of conceptions,

which we may admit, although they cannot, without the help of

experience, help us to understand any subject or thing. If, thirdly,

the question is whether we may not cogitate this being, which is

distinct from the world, in analogy with the objects of experience?

The answer is: Undoubtedly, but only as an ideal, and not as a real

object. That is, we must cogitate it only as an unknown substratum

of the systematic unity, order, and finality of the world- a unity

which reason must employ as the regulative principle of its

investigation of nature. Nay, more, we may admit into the idea certain

anthropomorphic elements, which are promotive of the interests of this

regulative principle. For it is no more than an idea, which does not

relate directly to a being distinct from the world, but to the

regulative principle of the systematic unity of the world, by means,

however, of a schema of this unity- the schema of a Supreme

Intelligence, who is the wisely-designing author of the universe. What

this basis of cosmical unity may be in itself, we know not- we

cannot discover from the idea; we merely know how we ought to employ

the idea of this unity, in relation to the systematic operation of

reason in the sphere of experience.



  *After what has been said of the psychological idea of the ego and

its proper employment as a regulative principle of the operations of

reason, I need not enter into details regarding the transcendental

illusion by which the systematic unity of all the various phenomena of

the internal sense is hypostatized. The procedure is in this case very

similar to that which has been discussed in our remarks on the

theological ideal.



  But, it will be asked again, can we on these grounds, admit the

existence of a wise and omnipotent author of the world? Without doubt;

and not only so, but we must assume the existence of such a being. But

do we thus extend the limits of our knowledge beyond the field of

possible experience? By no means. For we have merely presupposed a

something, of which we have no conception, which we do not know as

it is in itself; but, in relation to the systematic disposition of the

universe, which we must presuppose in all our observation of nature,

we have cogitated this unknown being in analogy with an intelligent

existence (an empirical conception), that is to say, we have endowed

it with those attributes, which, judging from the nature of our own

reason, may contain the ground of such a systematic unity. This idea

is therefore valid only relatively to the employment in experience

of our reason. But if we attribute to it absolute and objective

validity, we overlook the fact that it is merely an ideal being that

we cogitate; and, by setting out from a basis which is not

determinable by considerations drawn from experience, we place

ourselves in a position which incapacitates us from applying this

principle to the empirical employment of reason.

  But, it will be asked further, can I make any use of this conception

and hypothesis in my investigations into the world and nature? Yes,

for this very purpose was the idea established by reason as a

fundamental basis. But may I regard certain arrangements, which seemed

to have been made in conformity with some fixed aim, as the

arrangements of design, and look upon them as proceeding from the

divine will, with the intervention, however, of certain other

particular arrangements disposed to that end? Yes, you may do so;

but at the same time you must regard it as indifferent, whether it

is asserted that divine wisdom has disposed all things in conformity

with his highest aims, or that the idea of supreme wisdom is a

regulative principle in the investigation of nature, and at the same

time a principle of the systematic unity of nature according to

general laws, even in those cases where we are unable to discover that

unity. In other words, it must be perfectly indifferent to you whether

you say, when you have discovered this unity: God has wisely willed it

so; or: Nature has wisely arranged this. For it was nothing but the

systematic unity, which reason requires as a basis for the

investigation of nature, that justified you in accepting the idea of a

supreme intelligence as a schema for a regulative principle; and,

the farther you advance in the discovery of design and finality, the

more certain the validity of your idea. But, as the whole aim of

this regulative principle was the discovery of a necessary and

systematic unity in nature, we have, in so far as we attain this, to

attribute our success to the idea of a Supreme Being; while, at the

same time, we cannot, without involving ourselves in contradictions,

overlook the general laws of nature, as it was in reference to them

alone that this idea was employed. We cannot, I say, overlook the

general laws of nature, and regard this conformity to aims

observable in nature as contingent or hyperphysical in its origin;

inasmuch as there is no ground which can justify us in the admission

of a being with such properties distinct from and above nature. All

that we are authorized to assert is that this idea may be employed

as a principle, and that the properties of the being which is

assumed to correspond to it may be regarded as systematically

connected in analogy with the causal determination of phenomena.

  For the same reasons we are justified in introducing into the idea

of the supreme cause other anthropomorphic elements (for without these

we could not predicate anything of it); we may regard it as

allowable to cogitate this cause as a being with understanding, the

feelings of pleasure and displeasure, and faculties of desire and will

corresponding to these. At the same time, we may attribute to this

being infinite perfection- a perfection which necessarily transcends

that which our knowledge of the order and design in the world

authorize us to predicate of it. For the regulative law of

systematic unity requires us to study nature on the supposition that

systematic and final unity in infinitum is everywhere discoverable,

even in the highest diversity. For, although we may discover little of

this cosmical perfection, it belongs to the legislative prerogative of

reason to require us always to seek for and to expect it; while it

must always be beneficial to institute all inquiries into nature in

accordance with this principle. But it is evident that, by this idea

of a supreme author of all, which I place as the foundation of all

inquiries into nature, I do not mean to assert the existence of such a

being, or that I have any knowledge of its existence; and,

consequently, I do not really deduce anything from the existence of

this being, but merely from its idea, that is to say, from the

nature of things in this world, in accordance with this idea. A

certain dim consciousness of the true use of this idea seems to have

dictated to the philosophers of all times the moderate language used

by them regarding the cause of the world. We find them employing the

expressions wisdom and care of nature, and divine wisdom, as

synonymous- nay, in purely speculative discussions, preferring the

former, because it does not carry the appearance of greater

pretensions than such as we are entitled to make, and at the same time

directs reason to its proper field of action- nature and her

phenomena.

  Thus, pure reason, which at first seemed to promise us nothing

less than the extension of our cognition beyond the limits of

experience, is found, when thoroughly examined, to contain nothing but

regulative principles, the virtue and function of which is to

introduce into our cognition a higher degree of unity than the

understanding could of itself. These principles, by placing the goal

of all our struggles at so great a distance, realize for us the most

thorough connection between the different parts of our cognition,

and the highest degree of systematic unity. But, on the other hand, if

misunderstood and employed as constitutive principles of

transcendent cognition, they become the parents of illusions and

contradictions, while pretending to introduce us to new regions of

knowledge.



  Thus all human cognition begins with intuitions, proceeds from

thence to conceptions, and ends with ideas. Although it possesses,

in relation to all three elements, a priori sources of cognition,

which seemed to transcend the limits of all experience, a

thoroughgoing criticism demonstrates that speculative reason can

never, by the aid of these elements, pass the bounds of possible

experience, and that the proper destination of this highest faculty of

cognition is to employ all methods, and all the principles of these

methods, for the purpose of penetrating into the innermost secrets

of nature, by the aid of the principles of unity (among all kinds of

which teleological unity is the highest), while it ought not to

attempt to soar above the sphere of experience, beyond which there

lies nought for us but the void inane. The critical examination, in

our Transcendental Analytic, of all the propositions which professed

to extend cognition beyond the sphere of experience, completely

demonstrated that they can only conduct us to a possible experience.

If we were not distrustful even of the clearest abstract theorems,

if we were not allured by specious and inviting prospects to escape

from the constraining power of their evidence, we might spare

ourselves the laborious examination of all the dialectical arguments

which a transcendent reason adduces in support of its pretensions; for

we should know with the most complete certainty that, however honest

such professions might be, they are null and valueless, because they

relate to a kind of knowledge to which no man can by any possibility

attain. But, as there is no end to discussion, if we cannot discover

the true cause of the illusions by which even the wisest are deceived,

and as the analysis of all our transcendent cognition into its

elements is of itself of no slight value as a psychological study,

while it is a duty incumbent on every philosopher- it was found

necessary to investigate the dialectical procedure of reason in its

primary sources. And as the inferences of which this dialectic is

the parent are not only deceitful, but naturally possess a profound

interest for humanity, it was advisable at the same time, to give a

full account of the momenta of this dialectical procedure, and to

deposit it in the archives of human reason, as a warning to all future

metaphysicians to avoid these causes of speculative error.

METHOD

                           II.



             TRANSCENDENTAL DOCTRINE OF METHOD.



  If we regard the sum of the cognition of pure speculative reason

as an edifice, the idea of which, at least, exists in the human

mind, it may be said that we have in the Transcendental Doctrine of

Elements examined the materials and determined to what edifice these

belong, and what its height and stability. We have found, indeed,

that, although we had purposed to build for ourselves a tower which

should reach to Heaven, the supply of materials sufficed merely for

a habitation, which was spacious enough for all terrestrial

purposes, and high enough to enable us to survey the level plain of

experience, but that the bold undertaking designed necessarily

failed for want of materials- not to mention the confusion of tongues,

which gave rise to endless disputes among the labourers on the plan of

the edifice, and at last scattered them over all the world, each to

erect a separate building for himself, according to his own plans

and his own inclinations. Our present task relates not to the

materials, but to the plan of an edifice; and, as we have had

sufficient warning not to venture blindly upon a design which may be

found to transcend our natural powers, while, at the same time, we

cannot give up the intention of erecting a secure abode for the

mind, we must proportion our design to the material which is presented

to us, and which is, at the same time, sufficient for all our wants.

  I understand, then, by the transcendental doctrine of method, the

determination of the formal conditions of a complete system of pure

reason. We shall accordingly have to treat of the discipline, the

canon, the architectonic, and, finally, the history of pure reason.

This part of our Critique will accomplish, from the transcendental

point of view, what has been usually attempted, but miserably

executed, under the name of practical logic. It has been badly

executed, I say, because general logic, not being limited to any

particular kind of cognition (not even to the pure cognition of the

understanding) nor to any particular objects, it cannot, without

borrowing from other sciences, do more than present merely the

titles or signs of possible methods and the technical expressions,

which are employed in the systematic parts of all sciences; and thus

the pupil is made acquainted with names, the meaning and application

of which he is to learn only at some future time.

            CHAPTER I. The Discipline of Pure Reason.



  Negative judgements- those which are so not merely as regards

their logical form, but in respect of their content- are not

commonly held in especial respect. They are, on the contrary, regarded

as jealous enemies of our insatiable desire for knowledge; and it

almost requires an apology to induce us to tolerate, much less to

prize and to respect them.

  All propositions, indeed, may be logically expressed in a negative

form; but, in relation to the content of our cognition, the peculiar

province of negative judgements is solely to prevent error. For this

reason, too, negative propositions, which are framed for the purpose

of correcting false cognitions where error is absolutely impossible,

are undoubtedly true, but inane and senseless; that is, they are in

reality purposeless and, for this reason, often very ridiculous.

Such is the proposition of the schoolman that Alexander could not have

subdued any countries without an army.

  But where the limits of our possible cognition are very much

contracted, the attraction to new fields of knowledge great, the

illusions to which the mind is subject of the most deceptive

character, and the evil consequences of error of no inconsiderable

magnitude- the negative element in knowledge, which is useful only

to guard us against error, is of far more importance than much of that

positive instruction which makes additions to the sum of our

knowledge. The restraint which is employed to repress, and finally

to extirpate the constant inclination to depart from certain rules, is

termed discipline. It is distinguished from culture, which aims at the

formation of a certain degree of skill, without attempting to

repress or to destroy any other mental power, already existing. In the

cultivation of a talent, which has given evidence of an impulse

towards self-development, discipline takes a negative,* culture and

doctrine a positive, part.



  *I am well aware that, in the language of the schools, the term

discipline is usually employed as synonymous with instruction. But

there are so many cases in which it is necessary to distinguish the

notion of the former, as a course of corrective training, from that of

the latter, as the communication of knowledge, and the nature of

things itself demands the appropriation of the most suitable

expressions for this distinction, that it is my desire that the former

terms should never be employed in any other than a negative

signification.



  That natural dispositions and talents (such as imagination and with,

which ask a free and unlimited development, require in many respects

the corrective influence of discipline, every one will readily

grant. But it may well appear strange that reason, whose proper duty

it is to prescribe rules of discipline to all the other powers of

the mind, should itself require this corrective. It has, in fact,

hitherto escaped this humiliation, only because, in presence of its

magnificent pretensions and high position, no one could readily

suspect it to be capable of substituting fancies for conceptions,

and words for things.

  Reason, when employed in the field of experience, does not stand

in need of criticism, because its principles are subjected to the

continual test of empirical observations. Nor is criticism requisite

in the sphere of mathematics, where the conceptions of reason must

always be presented in concreto in pure intuition, and baseless or

arbitrary assertions are discovered without difficulty. But where

reason is not held in a plain track by the influence of empirical or

of pure intuition, that is, when it is employed in the

transcendental sphere of pure conceptions, it stands in great need

of discipline, to restrain its propensity to overstep the limits of

possible experience and to keep it from wandering into error. In fact,

the utility of the philosophy of pure reason is entirely of this

negative character. Particular errors may be corrected by particular

animadversions, and the causes of these errors may be eradicated by

criticism. But where we find, as in the case of pure reason, a

complete system of illusions and fallacies, closely connected with

each other and depending upon grand general principles, there seems to

be required a peculiar and negative code of mental legislation, which,

under the denomination of a discipline, and founded upon the nature of

reason and the objects of its exercise, shall constitute a system of

thorough examination and testing, which no fallacy will be able to

withstand or escape from, under whatever disguise or concealment it

may lurk.

  But the reader must remark that, in this the second division of

our transcendental Critique the discipline of pure reason is not

directed to the content, but to the method of the cognition of pure

reason. The former task has been completed in the doctrine of

elements. But there is so much similarity in the mode of employing the

faculty of reason, whatever be the object to which it is applied,

while, at the same time, its employment in the transcendental sphere

is so essentially different in kind from every other, that, without

the warning negative influence of a discipline specially directed to

that end, the errors are unavoidable which spring from the

unskillful employment of the methods which are originated by reason

but which are out of place in this sphere.



     SECTION I. The Discipline of Pure Reason in the Sphere

                       of Dogmatism.



  The science of mathematics presents the most brilliant example of

the extension of the sphere of pure reason without the aid of

experience. Examples are always contagious; and they exert an especial

influence on the same faculty, which naturally flatters itself that it

will have the same good fortune in other case as fell to its lot in

one fortunate instance. Hence pure reason hopes to be able to extend

its empire in the transcendental sphere with equal success and

security, especially when it applies the same method which was

attended with such brilliant results in the science of mathematics. It

is, therefore, of the highest importance for us to know whether the

method of arriving at demonstrative certainty, which is termed

mathematical, be identical with that by which we endeavour to attain

the same degree of certainty in philosophy, and which is termed in

that science dogmatical.

  Philosophical cognition is the cognition of reason by means of

conceptions; mathematical cognition is cognition by means of the

construction of conceptions. The construction of a conception is the

presentation a priori of the intuition which corresponds to the

conception. For this purpose a non-empirical intuition is requisite,

which, as an intuition, is an individual object; while, as the

construction of a conception (a general representation), it must be

seen to be universally valid for all the possible intuitions which

rank under that conception. Thus I construct a triangle, by the

presentation of the object which corresponds to this conception,

either by mere imagination, in pure intuition, or upon paper, in

empirical intuition, in both cases completely a priori, without

borrowing the type of that figure from any experience. The

individual figure drawn upon paper is empirical; but it serves,

notwithstanding, to indicate the conception, even in its universality,

because in this empirical intuition we keep our eye merely on the

act of the construction of the conception, and pay no attention to the

various modes of determining it, for example, its size, the length

of its sides, the size of its angles, these not in the least affecting

the essential character of the conception.

  Philosophical cognition, accordingly, regards the particular only in

the general; mathematical the general in the particular, nay, in the

individual. This is done, however, entirely a priori and by means of

pure reason, so that, as this individual figure is determined under

certain universal conditions of construction, the object of the

conception, to which this individual figure corresponds as its schema,

must be cogitated as universally determined.

  The essential difference of these two modes of cognition consists,

therefore, in this formal quality; it does not regard the difference

of the matter or objects of both. Those thinkers who aim at

distinguishing philosophy from mathematics by asserting that the

former has to do with quality merely, and the latter with quantity,

have mistaken the effect for the cause. The reason why mathematical

cognition can relate only to quantity is to be found in its form

alone. For it is the conception of quantities only that is capable

of being constructed, that is, presented a priori in intuition;

while qualities cannot be given in any other than an empirical

intuition. Hence the cognition of qualities by reason is possible only

through conceptions. No one can find an intuition which shall

correspond to the conception of reality, except in experience; it

cannot be presented to the mind a priori and antecedently to the

empirical consciousness of a reality. We can form an intuition, by

means of the mere conception of it, of a cone, without the aid of

experience; but the colour of the cone we cannot know except from

experience. I cannot present an intuition of a cause, except in an

example which experience offers to me. Besides, philosophy, as well as

mathematics, treats of quantities; as, for example, of totality,

infinity, and so on. Mathematics, too, treats of the difference of

lines and surfaces- as spaces of different quality, of the

continuity of extension- as a quality thereof. But, although in such

cases they have a common object, the mode in which reason considers

that object is very different in philosophy from what it is in

mathematics. The former confines itself to the general conceptions;

the latter can do nothing with a mere conception, it hastens to

intuition. In this intuition it regards the conception in concreto,

not empirically, but in an a priori intuition, which it has

constructed; and in which, all the results which follow from the

general conditions of the construction of the conception are in all

cases valid for the object of the constructed conception.

  Suppose that the conception of a triangle is given to a

philosopher and that he is required to discover, by the

philosophical method, what relation the sum of its angles bears to a

right angle. He has nothing before him but the conception of a

figure enclosed within three right lines, and, consequently, with

the same number of angles. He may analyse the conception of a right

line, of an angle, or of the number three as long as he pleases, but

he will not discover any properties not contained in these

conceptions. But, if this question is proposed to a geometrician, he

at once begins by constructing a triangle. He knows that two right

angles are equal to the sum of all the contiguous angles which proceed

from one point in a straight line; and he goes on to produce one

side of his triangle, thus forming two adjacent angles which are

together equal to two right angles. He then divides the exterior of

these angles, by drawing a line parallel with the opposite side of the

triangle, and immediately perceives that be has thus got an exterior

adjacent angle which is equal to the interior. Proceeding in this way,

through a chain of inferences, and always on the ground of

intuition, he arrives at a clear and universally valid solution of the

question.

  But mathematics does not confine itself to the construction of

quantities (quanta), as in the case of geometry; it occupies itself

with pure quantity also (quantitas), as in the case of algebra,

where complete abstraction is made of the properties of the object

indicated by the conception of quantity. In algebra, a certain

method of notation by signs is adopted, and these indicate the

different possible constructions of quantities, the extraction of

roots, and so on. After having thus denoted the general conception

of quantities, according to their different relations, the different

operations by which quantity or number is increased or diminished

are presented in intuition in accordance with general rules. Thus,

when one quantity is to be divided by another, the signs which

denote both are placed in the form peculiar to the operation of

division; and thus algebra, by means of a symbolical construction of

quantity, just as geometry, with its ostensive or geometrical

construction (a construction of the objects themselves), arrives at

results which discursive cognition cannot hope to reach by the aid

of mere conceptions.

  Now, what is the cause of this difference in the fortune of the

philosopher and the mathematician, the former of whom follows the path

of conceptions, while the latter pursues that of intuitions, which

he represents, a priori, in correspondence with his conceptions? The

cause is evident from what has been already demonstrated in the

introduction to this Critique. We do not, in the present case, want to

discover analytical propositions, which may be produced merely by

analysing our conceptions- for in this the philosopher would have

the advantage over his rival; we aim at the discovery of synthetical

propositions- such synthetical propositions, moreover, as can be

cognized a priori. I must not confine myself to that which I

actually cogitate in my conception of a triangle, for this is

nothing more than the mere definition; I must try to go beyond that,

and to arrive at properties which are not contained in, although

they belong to, the conception. Now, this is impossible, unless I

determine the object present to my mind according to the conditions,

either of empirical, or of pure, intuition. In the former case, I

should have an empirical proposition (arrived at by actual measurement

of the angles of the triangle), which would possess neither

universality nor necessity; but that would be of no value. In the

latter, I proceed by geometrical construction, by means of which I

collect, in a pure intuition, just as I would in an empirical

intuition, all the various properties which belong to the schema of

a triangle in general, and consequently to its conception, and thus

construct synthetical propositions which possess the attribute of

universality.

  It would be vain to philosophize upon the triangle, that is, to

reflect on it discursively; I should get no further than the

definition with which I had been obliged to set out. There are

certainly transcendental synthetical propositions which are framed

by means of pure conceptions, and which form the peculiar

distinction of philosophy; but these do not relate to any particular

thing, but to a thing in general, and enounce the conditions under

which the perception of it may become a part of possible experience.

But the science of mathematics has nothing to do with such

questions, nor with the question of existence in any fashion; it is

concerned merely with the properties of objects in themselves, only in

so far as these are connected with the conception of the objects.

  In the above example, we merely attempted to show the great

difference which exists between the discursive employment of reason in

the sphere of conceptions, and its intuitive exercise by means of

the construction of conceptions. The question naturally arises: What

is the cause which necessitates this twofold exercise of reason, and

how are we to discover whether it is the philosophical or the

mathematical method which reason is pursuing in an argument?

  All our knowledge relates, finally, to possible intuitions, for it

is these alone that present objects to the mind. An a priori or

non-empirical conception contains either a pure intuition- and in this

case it can be constructed; or it contains nothing but the synthesis

of possible intuitions, which are not given a priori. In this latter

case, it may help us to form synthetical a priori judgements, but only

in the discursive method, by conceptions, not in the intuitive, by

means of the construction of conceptions.

  The only a priori intuition is that of the pure form of phenomena-

space and time. A conception of space and time as quanta may be

presented a priori in intuition, that is, constructed, either alone

with their quality (figure), or as pure quantity (the mere synthesis

of the homogeneous), by means of number. But the matter of

phenomena, by which things are given in space and time, can be

presented only in perception, a posteriori. The only conception

which represents a priori this empirical content of phenomena is the

conception of a thing in general; and the a priori synthetical

cognition of this conception can give us nothing more than the rule

for the synthesis of that which may be contained in the

corresponding a posteriori perception; it is utterly inadequate to

present an a priori intuition of the real object, which must

necessarily be empirical.

  Synthetical propositions, which relate to things in general, an a

priori intuition of which is impossible, are transcendental. For

this reason transcendental propositions cannot be framed by means of

the construction of conceptions; they are a priori, and based entirely

on conceptions themselves. They contain merely the rule, by which we

are to seek in the world of perception or experience the synthetical

unity of that which cannot be intuited a priori. But they are

incompetent to present any of the conceptions which appear in them

in an a priori intuition; these can be given only a posteriori, in

experience, which, however, is itself possible only through these

synthetical principles.

  If we are to form a synthetical judgement regarding a conception, we

must go beyond it, to the intuition in which it is given. If we keep

to what is contained in the conception, the judgement is merely

analytical- it is merely an explanation of what we have cogitated in

the conception. But I can pass from the conception to the pure or

empirical intuition which corresponds to it. I can proceed to

examine my conception in concreto, and to cognize, either a priori

or a posterio, what I find in the object of the conception. The

former- a priori cognition- is rational-mathematical cognition by

means of the construction of the conception; the latter- a

posteriori cognition- is purely empirical cognition, which does not

possess the attributes of necessity and universality. Thus I may

analyse the conception I have of gold; but I gain no new information

from this analysis, I merely enumerate the different properties

which I had connected with the notion indicated by the word. My

knowledge has gained in logical clearness and arrangement, but no

addition has been made to it. But if I take the matter which is

indicated by this name, and submit it to the examination of my senses,

I am enabled to form several synthetical- although still empirical-

propositions. The mathematical conception of a triangle I should

construct, that is, present a priori in intuition, and in this way

attain to rational-synthetical cognition. But when the

transcendental conception of reality, or substance, or power is

presented to my mind, I find that it does not relate to or indicate

either an empirical or pure intuition, but that it indicates merely

the synthesis of empirical intuitions, which cannot of course be given

a priori. The synthesis in such a conception cannot proceed a

priori- without the aid of experience- to the intuition which

corresponds to the conception; and, for this reason, none of these

conceptions can produce a determinative synthetical proposition,

they can never present more than a principle of the synthesis* of

possible empirical intuitions. A transcendental proposition is,

therefore, a synthetical cognition of reason by means of pure

conceptions and the discursive method, and it renders possible all

synthetical unity in empirical cognition, though it cannot present

us with any intuition a priori.



  *In the case of the conception of cause, I do really go beyond the

empirical conception of an event- but not to the intuition which

presents this conception in concreto, but only to the time-conditions,

which may be found in experience to correspond to the conception. My

procedure is, therefore, strictly according to conceptions; I cannot

in a case of this kind employ the construction of conceptions, because

the conception is merely a rule for the synthesis of perceptions,

which are not pure intuitions, and which, therefore, cannot be given a

priori.



  There is thus a twofold exercise of reason. Both modes have the

properties of universality and an a priori origin in common, but

are, in their procedure, of widely different character. The reason

of this is that in the world of phenomena, in which alone objects

are presented to our minds, there are two main elements- the form of

intuition (space and time), which can be cognized and determined

completely a priori, and the matter or content- that which is

presented in space and time, and which, consequently, contains a

something- an existence corresponding to our powers of sensation. As

regards the latter, which can never be given in a determinate mode

except by experience, there are no a priori notions which relate to

it, except the undetermined conceptions of the synthesis of possible

sensations, in so far as these belong (in a possible experience) to

the unity of consciousness. As regards the former, we can determine

our conceptions a priori in intuition, inasmuch as we are ourselves

the creators of the objects of the conceptions in space and time-

these objects being regarded simply as quanta. In the one case, reason

proceeds according to conceptions and can do nothing more than subject

phenomena to these- which can only be determined empirically, that is,

a posteriori- in conformity, however, with those conceptions as the

rules of all empirical synthesis. In the other case, reason proceeds

by the construction of conceptions; and, as these conceptions relate

to an a priori intuition, they may be given and determined in pure

intuition a priori, and without the aid of empirical data. The

examination and consideration of everything that exists in space or

time- whether it is a quantum or not, in how far the particular

something (which fills space or time) is a primary substratum, or a

mere determination of some other existence, whether it relates to

anything else- either as cause or effect, whether its existence is

isolated or in reciprocal connection with and dependence upon

others, the possibility of this existence, its reality and necessity

or opposites- all these form part of the cognition of reason on the

ground of conceptions, and this cognition is termed philosophical. But

to determine a priori an intuition in space (its figure), to divide

time into periods, or merely to cognize the quantity of an intuition

in space and time, and to determine it by number- all this is an

operation of reason by means of the construction of conceptions, and

is called mathematical.

  The success which attends the efforts of reason in the sphere of

mathematics naturally fosters the expectation that the same good

fortune will be its lot, if it applies the mathematical method in

other regions of mental endeavour besides that of quantities. Its

success is thus great, because it can support all its conceptions by a

priori intuitions and, in this way, make itself a master, as it

were, over nature; while pure philosophy, with its a priori discursive

conceptions, bungles about in the world of nature, and cannot accredit

or show any a priori evidence of the reality of these conceptions.

Masters in the science of mathematics are confident of the success

of this method; indeed, it is a common persuasion that it is capable

of being applied to any subject of human thought. They have hardly

ever reflected or philosophized on their favourite science- a task

of great difficulty; and the specific difference between the two modes

of employing the faculty of reason has never entered their thoughts.

Rules current in the field of common experience, and which common

sense stamps everywhere with its approval, are regarded by them as

axiomatic. From what source the conceptions of space and time, with

which (as the only primitive quanta) they have to deal, enter their

minds, is a question which they do not trouble themselves to answer;

and they think it just as unnecessary to examine into the origin of

the pure conceptions of the understanding and the extent of their

validity. All they have to do with them is to employ them. In all this

they are perfectly right, if they do not overstep the limits of the

sphere of nature. But they pass, unconsciously, from the world of

sense to the insecure ground of pure transcendental conceptions

(instabilis tellus, innabilis unda), where they can neither stand

nor swim, and where the tracks of their footsteps are obliterated by

time; while the march of mathematics is pursued on a broad and

magnificent highway, which the latest posterity shall frequent without

fear of danger or impediment.

  As we have taken upon us the task of determining, clearly and

certainly, the limits of pure reason in the sphere of

transcendentalism, and as the efforts of reason in this direction

are persisted in, even after the plainest and most expressive

warnings, hope still beckoning us past the limits of experience into

the splendours of the intellectual world- it becomes necessary to

cut away the last anchor of this fallacious and fantastic hope. We

shall, accordingly, show that the mathematical method is unattended in

the sphere of philosophy by the least advantage- except, perhaps, that

it more plainly exhibits its own inadequacy- that geometry and

philosophy are two quite different things, although they go band in

hand in hand in the field of natural science, and, consequently,

that the procedure of the one can never be imitated by the other.

  The evidence of mathematics rests upon definitions, axioms, and

demonstrations. I shall be satisfied with showing that none of these

forms can be employed or imitated in philosophy in the sense in

which they are understood by mathematicians; and that the

geometrician, if he employs his method in philosophy, will succeed

only in building card-castles, while the employment of the

philosophical method in mathematics can result in nothing but mere

verbiage. The essential business of philosophy, indeed, is to mark out

the limits of the science; and even the mathematician, unless his

talent is naturally circumscribed and limited to this particular

department of knowledge, cannot turn a deaf ear to the warnings of

philosophy, or set himself above its direction.

  I. Of Definitions. A definition is, as the term itself indicates,

the representation, upon primary grounds, of the complete conception

of a thing within its own limits.* Accordingly, an empirical

conception cannot be defined, it can only be explained. For, as

there are in such a conception only a certain number of marks or

signs, which denote a certain class of sensuous objects, we can

never be sure that we do not cogitate under the word which indicates

the same object, at one time a greater, at another a smaller number of

signs. Thus, one person may cogitate in his conception of gold, in

addition to its properties of weight, colour, malleability, that of

resisting rust, while another person may be ignorant of this

quality. We employ certain signs only so long as we require them for

the sake of distinction; new observations abstract some and add new

ones, so that an empirical conception never remains within permanent

limits. It is, in fact, useless to define a conception of this kind.

If, for example, we are speaking of water and its properties, we do

not stop at what we actually think by the word water, but proceed to

observation and experiment; and the word, with the few signs

attached to it, is more properly a designation than a conception of

the thing. A definition in this case would evidently be nothing more

than a determination of the word. In the second place, no a priori

conception, such as those of substance, cause, right, fitness, and

so on, can be defined. For I can never be sure, that the clear

representation of a given conception (which is given in a confused

state) has been fully developed, until I know that the

representation is adequate with its object. But, inasmuch as the

conception, as it is presented to the mind, may contain a number of

obscure representations, which we do not observe in our analysis,

although we employ them in our application of the conception, I can

never be sure that my analysis is complete, while examples may make

this probable, although they can never demonstrate the fact. instead

of the word definition, I should rather employ the term exposition-

a more modest expression, which the critic may accept without

surrendering his doubts as to the completeness of the analysis of

any such conception. As, therefore, neither empirical nor a priori

conceptions are capable of definition, we have to see whether the only

other kind of conceptions- arbitrary conceptions- can be subjected

to this mental operation. Such a conception can always be defined; for

I must know thoroughly what I wished to cogitate in it, as it was I

who created it, and it was not given to my mind either by the nature

of my understanding or by experience. At the same time, I cannot say

that, by such a definition, I have defined a real object. If the

conception is based upon empirical conditions, if, for example, I have

a conception of a clock for a ship, this arbitrary conception does not

assure me of the existence or even of the possibility of the object.

My definition of such a conception would with more propriety be termed

a declaration of a project than a definition of an object. There

are no other conceptions which can bear definition, except those which

contain an arbitrary synthesis, which can be constructed a priori.

Consequently, the science of mathematics alone possesses

definitions. For the object here thought is presented a priori in

intuition; and thus it can never contain more or less than the

conception, because the conception of the object has been given by the

definition- and primarily, that is, without deriving the definition

from any other source. Philosophical definitions are, therefore,

merely expositions of given conceptions, while mathematical

definitions are constructions of conceptions originally formed by

the mind itself; the former are produced by analysis, the completeness

of which is never demonstratively certain, the latter by a

synthesis. In a mathematical definition the conception is formed, in a

philosophical definition it is only explained. From this it follows:



  *The definition must describe the conception completely that is,

omit none of the marks or signs of which it composed; within its own

limits, that is, it must be precise, and enumerate no more signs

than belong to the conception; and on primary grounds, that is to say,

the limitations of the bounds of the conception must not be deduced

from other conceptions, as in this case a proof would be necessary,

and the so-called definition would be incapable of taking its place at

the bead of all the judgements we have to form regarding an object.



  (a) That we must not imitate, in philosophy, the mathematical

usage of commencing with definitions- except by way of hypothesis or

experiment. For, as all so-called philosophical definitions are merely

analyses of given conceptions, these conceptions, although only in a

confused form, must precede the analysis; and the incomplete

exposition must precede the complete, so that we may be able to draw

certain inferences from the characteristics which an incomplete

analysis has enabled us to discover, before we attain to the

complete exposition or definition of the conception. In one word, a

full and clear definition ought, in philosophy, rather to form the

conclusion than the commencement of our labours.* In mathematics, on

the contrary, we cannot have a conception prior to the definition;

it is the definition which gives us the conception, and it must for

this reason form the commencement of every chain of mathematical

reasoning.



  *Philosophy abounds in faulty definitions, especially such as

contain some of the elements requisite to form a complete

definition. If a conception could not be employed in reasoning

before it had been defined, it would fare ill with all philosophical

thought. But, as incompletely defined conceptions may always be

employed without detriment to truth, so far as our analysis of the

elements contained in them proceeds, imperfect definitions, that is,

propositions which are properly not definitions, but merely

approximations thereto, may be used with great advantage. In

mathematics, definition belongs ad esse, in philosophy ad melius esse.

It is a difficult task to construct a proper definition. Jurists are

still without a complete definition of the idea of right.



  (b) Mathematical definitions cannot be erroneous. For the conception

is given only in and through the definition, and thus it contains only

what has been cogitated in the definition. But although a definition

cannot be incorrect, as regards its content, an error may sometimes,

although seldom, creep into the form. This error consists in a want of

precision. Thus the common definition of a circle- that it is a curved

line, every point in which is equally distant from another point

called the centre- is faulty, from the fact that the determination

indicated by the word curved is superfluous. For there ought to be a

particular theorem, which may be easily proved from the definition, to

the effect that every line, which has all its points at equal

distances from another point, must be a curved line- that is, that not

even the smallest part of it can be straight. Analytical

definitions, on the other hand, may be erroneous in many respects,

either by the introduction of signs which do not actually exist in the

conception, or by wanting in that completeness which forms the

essential of a definition. In the latter case, the definition is

necessarily defective, because we can never be fully certain of the

completeness of our analysis. For these reasons, the method of

definition employed in mathematics cannot be imitated in philosophy.

  2. Of Axioms. These, in so far as they are immediately certain,

are a priori synthetical principles. Now, one conception cannot be

connected synthetically and yet immediately with another; because,

if we wish to proceed out of and beyond a conception, a third

mediating cognition is necessary. And, as philosophy is a cognition of

reason by the aid of conceptions alone, there is to be found in it

no principle which deserves to be called an axiom. Mathematics, on the

other hand, may possess axioms, because it can always connect the

predicates of an object a priori, and without any mediating term, by

means of the construction of conceptions in intuition. Such is the

case with the proposition: Three points can always lie in a plane.

On the other hand, no synthetical principle which is based upon

conceptions, can ever be immediately certain (for example, the

proposition: Everything that happens has a cause), because I require a

mediating term to connect the two conceptions of event and cause-

namely, the condition of time-determination in an experience, and I

cannot cognize any such principle immediately and from conceptions

alone. Discursive principles are, accordingly, very different from

intuitive principles or axioms. The former always require deduction,

which in the case of the latter may be altogether dispensed with.

Axioms are, for this reason, always self-evident, while

philosophical principles, whatever may be the degree of certainty they

possess, cannot lay any claim to such a distinction. No synthetical

proposition of pure transcendental reason can be so evident, as is

often rashly enough declared, as the statement, twice two are four. It

is true that in the Analytic I introduced into the list of

principles of the pure understanding, certain axioms of intuition; but

the principle there discussed was not itself an axiom, but served

merely to present the principle of the possibility of axioms in

general, while it was really nothing more than a principle based

upon conceptions. For it is one part of the duty of transcendental

philosophy to establish the possibility of mathematics itself.

Philosophy possesses, then, no axioms, and has no right to impose

its a priori principles upon thought, until it has established their

authority and validity by a thoroughgoing deduction.

  3. Of Demonstrations. Only an apodeictic proof, based upon

intuition, can be termed a demonstration. Experience teaches us what

is, but it cannot convince us that it might not have been otherwise.

Hence a proof upon empirical grounds cannot be apodeictic. A priori

conceptions, in discursive cognition, can never produce intuitive

certainty or evidence, however certain the judgement they present

may be. Mathematics alone, therefore, contains demonstrations, because

it does not deduce its cognition from conceptions, but from the

construction of conceptions, that is, from intuition, which can be

given a priori in accordance with conceptions. The method of

algebra, in equations, from which the correct answer is deduced by

reduction, is a kind of construction- not geometrical, but by symbols-

in which all conceptions, especially those of the relations of

quantities, are represented in intuition by signs; and thus the

conclusions in that science are secured from errors by the fact that

every proof is submitted to ocular evidence. Philosophical cognition

does not possess this advantage, it being required to consider the

general always in abstracto (by means of conceptions), while

mathematics can always consider it in concreto (in an individual

intuition), and at the same time by means of a priori

representation, whereby all errors are rendered manifest to the

senses. The former- discursive proofs- ought to be termed acroamatic

proofs, rather than demonstrations, as only words are employed in

them, while demonstrations proper, as the term itself indicates,

always require a reference to the intuition of the object.

  It follows from all these considerations that it is not consonant

with the nature of philosophy, especially in the sphere of pure

reason, to employ the dogmatical method, and to adorn itself with

the titles and insignia of mathematical science. It does not belong to

that order, and can only hope for a fraternal union with that science.

Its attempts at mathematical evidence are vain pretensions, which

can only keep it back from its true aim, which is to detect the

illusory procedure of reason when transgressing its proper limits, and

by fully explaining and analysing our conceptions, to conduct us

from the dim regions of speculation to the clear region of modest

self-knowledge. Reason must not, therefore, in its transcendental

endeavours, look forward with such confidence, as if the path it is

pursuing led straight to its aim, nor reckon with such security upon

its premisses, as to consider it unnecessary to take a step back, or

to keep a strict watch for errors, which, overlooked in the

principles, may be detected in the arguments themselves- in which case

it may be requisite either to determine these principles with

greater strictness, or to change them entirely.

  I divide all apodeictic propositions, whether demonstrable or

immediately certain, into dogmata and mathemata. A direct

synthetical proposition, based on conceptions, is a dogma; a

proposition of the same kind, based on the construction of

conceptions, is a mathema. Analytical judgements do not teach us any

more about an object than what was contained in the conception we

had of it; because they do not extend our cognition beyond our

conception of an object, they merely elucidate the conception. They

cannot therefore be with propriety termed dogmas. Of the two kinds

of a priori synthetical propositions above mentioned, only those which

are employed in philosophy can, according to the general mode of

speech, bear this name; those of arithmetic or geometry would not be

rightly so denominated. Thus the customary mode of speaking confirms

the explanation given above, and the conclusion arrived at, that

only those judgements which are based upon conceptions, not on the

construction of conceptions, can be termed dogmatical.

  Thus, pure reason, in the sphere of speculation, does not contain

a single direct synthetical judgement based upon conceptions. By means

of ideas, it is, as we have shown, incapable of producing

synthetical judgements, which are objectively valid; by means of the

conceptions of the understanding, it establishes certain indubitable

principles, not, however, directly on the basis of conceptions, but

only indirectly by means of the relation of these conceptions to

something of a purely contingent nature, namely, possible

experience. When experience is presupposed, these principles are

apodeictically certain, but in themselves, and directly, they cannot

even be cognized a priori. Thus the given conceptions of cause and

event will not be sufficient for the demonstration of the proposition:

Every event has a cause. For this reason, it is not a dogma;

although from another point of view, that of experience, it is capable

of being proved to demonstration. The proper term for such a

proposition is principle, and not theorem (although it does require to

be proved), because it possesses the remarkable peculiarity of being

the condition of the possibility of its own ground of proof, that

is, experience, and of forming a necessary presupposition in all

empirical observation.

  If then, in the speculative sphere of pure reason, no dogmata are to

be found; all dogmatical methods, whether borrowed from mathematics,

or invented by philosophical thinkers, are alike inappropriate and

inefficient. They only serve to conceal errors and fallacies, and to

deceive philosophy, whose duty it is to see that reason pursues a safe

and straight path. A philosophical method may, however, be

systematical. For our reason is, subjectively considered, itself a

system, and, in the sphere of mere conceptions, a system of

investigation according to principles of unity, the material being

supplied by experience alone. But this is not the proper place for

discussing the peculiar method of transcendental philosophy, as our

present task is simply to examine whether our faculties are capable of

erecting an edifice on the basis of pure reason, and how far they

may proceed with the materials at their command.



     SECTION II. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Polemics.



  Reason must be subject, in all its operations, to criticism, which

must always be permitted to exercise its functions without

restraint; otherwise its interests are imperilled and its influence

obnoxious to suspicion. There is nothing, however useful, however

sacred it may be, that can claim exemption from the searching

examination of this supreme tribunal, which has no respect of persons.

The very existence of reason depends upon this freedom; for the

voice of reason is not that of a dictatorial and despotic power, it is

rather like the vote of the citizens of a free state, every member

of which must have the privilege of giving free expression to his

doubts, and possess even the right of veto.

  But while reason can never decline to submit itself to the

tribunal of criticism, it has not always cause to dread the

judgement of this court. Pure reason, however, when engaged in the

sphere of dogmatism, is not so thoroughly conscious of a strict

observance of its highest laws, as to appear before a higher

judicial reason with perfect confidence. On the contrary, it must

renounce its magnificent dogmatical pretensions in philosophy.

  Very different is the case when it has to defend itself, not

before a judge, but against an equal. If dogmatical assertions are

advanced on the negative side, in opposition to those made by reason

on the positive side, its justification kat authrhopon is complete,

although the proof of its propositions is kat aletheian

unsatisfactory.

  By the polemic of pure reason I mean the defence of its propositions

made by reason, in opposition to the dogmatical counter-propositions

advanced by other parties. The question here is not whether its own

statements may not also be false; it merely regards the fact that

reason proves that the opposite cannot be established with

demonstrative certainty, nor even asserted with a higher degree of

probability. Reason does not hold her possessions upon sufferance;

for, although she cannot show a perfectly satisfactory title to

them, no one can prove that she is not the rightful possessor.

  It is a melancholy reflection that reason, in its highest

exercise, falls into an antithetic; and that the supreme tribunal

for the settlement of differences should not be at union with

itself. It is true that we had to discuss the question of an

apparent antithetic, but we found that it was based upon a

misconception. In conformity with the common prejudice, phenomena were

regarded as things in themselves, and thus an absolute completeness in

their synthesis was required in the one mode or in the other (it was

shown to be impossible in both); a demand entirely out of place in

regard to phenomena. There was, then, no real self-contradiction of

reason in the propositions: The series of phenomena given in

themselves has an absolutely first beginning; and: This series is

absolutely and in itself without beginning. The two propositions are

perfectly consistent with each other, because phenomena as phenomena

are in themselves nothing, and consequently the hypothesis that they

are things in themselves must lead to self-contradictory inferences.

  But there are cases in which a similar misunderstanding cannot be

provided against, and the dispute must remain unsettled. Take, for

example, the theistic proposition: There is a Supreme Being; and on

the other hand, the atheistic counter-statement: There exists no

Supreme Being; or, in psychology: Everything that thinks possesses the

attribute of absolute and permanent unity, which is utterly

different from the transitory unity of material phenomena; and the

counter-proposition: The soul is not an immaterial unity, and its

nature is transitory, like that of phenomena. The objects of these

questions contain no heterogeneous or contradictory elements, for they

relate to things in themselves, and not to phenomena. There would

arise, indeed, a real contradiction, if reason came forward with a

statement on the negative side of these questions alone. As regards

the criticism to which the grounds of proof on the affirmative side

must be subjected, it may be freely admitted, without necessitating

the surrender of the affirmative propositions, which have, at least,

the interest of reason in their favour- an advantage which the

opposite party cannot lay claim to.

  I cannot agree with the opinion of several admirable thinkers-

Sulzer among the rest- that, in spite of the weakness of the arguments

hitherto in use, we may hope, one day, to see sufficient

demonstrations of the two cardinal propositions of pure reason- the

existence of a Supreme Being, and the immortality of the soul. I am

certain, on the contrary, that this will never be the case. For on

what ground can reason base such synthetical propositions, which do

not relate to the objects of experience and their internal

possibility? But it is also demonstratively certain that no one will

ever be able to maintain the contrary with the least show of

probability. For, as he can attempt such a proof solely upon the basis

of pure reason, he is bound to prove that a Supreme Being, and a

thinking subject in the character of a pure intelligence, are

impossible. But where will he find the knowledge which can enable

him to enounce synthetical judgements in regard to things which

transcend the region of experience? We may, therefore, rest assured

that the opposite never will be demonstrated. We need not, then,

have recourse to scholastic arguments; we may always admit the truth

of those propositions which are consistent with the speculative

interests of reason in the sphere of experience, and form, moreover,

the only means of uniting the speculative with the practical interest.

Our opponent, who must not be considered here as a critic solely, we

can be ready to meet with a non liquet which cannot fail to disconcert

him; while we cannot deny his right to a similar retort, as we have on

our side the advantage of the support of the subjective maxim of

reason, and can therefore look upon all his sophistical arguments with

calm indifference.

  From this point of view, there is properly no antithetic of pure

reason. For the only arena for such a struggle would be upon the field

of pure theology and psychology; but on this ground there can appear

no combatant whom we need to fear. Ridicule and boasting can be his

only weapons; and these may be laughed at, as mere child's play.

This consideration restores to Reason her courage; for what source

of confidence could be found, if she, whose vocation it is to

destroy error, were at variance with herself and without any

reasonable hope of ever reaching a state of permanent repose?

  Everything in nature is good for some purpose. Even poisons are

serviceable; they destroy the evil effects of other poisons

generated in our system, and must always find a place in every

complete pharmacopoeia. The objections raised against the fallacies

and sophistries of speculative reason, are objections given by the

nature of this reason itself, and must therefore have a destination

and purpose which can only be for the good of humanity. For what

purpose has Providence raised many objects, in which we have the

deepest interest, so far above us, that we vainly try to cognize

them with certainty, and our powers of mental vision are rather

excited than satisfied by the glimpses we may chance to seize? It is

very doubtful whether it is for our benefit to advance bold

affirmations regarding subjects involved in such obscurity; perhaps it

would even be detrimental to our best interests. But it is undoubtedly

always beneficial to leave the investigating, as well as the

critical reason, in perfect freedom, and permit it to take charge of

its own interests, which are advanced as much by its limitation, as by

its extension of its views, and which always suffer by the

interference of foreign powers forcing it, against its natural

tendencies, to bend to certain preconceived designs.

  Allow your opponent to say what he thinks reasonable, and combat him

only with the weapons of reason. Have no anxiety for the practical

interests of humanity- these are never imperilled in a purely

speculative dispute. Such a dispute serves merely to disclose the

antinomy of reason, which, as it has its source in the nature of

reason, ought to be thoroughly investigated. Reason is benefited by

the examination of a subject on both sides, and its judgements are

corrected by being limited. It is not the matter that may give

occasion to dispute, but the manner. For it is perfectly permissible

to employ, in the presence of reason, the language of a firmly

rooted faith, even after we have been obliged to renounce all

pretensions to knowledge.

  If we were to ask the dispassionate David Hume- a philosopher

endowed, in a degree that few are, with a well-balanced judgement:

What motive induced you to spend so much labour and thought in

undermining the consoling and beneficial persuasion that reason is

capable of assuring us of the existence, and presenting us with a

determinate conception of a Supreme Being?- his answer would be:

Nothing but the desire of teaching reason to know its own powers

better, and, at the same time, a dislike of the procedure by which

that faculty was compelled to support foregone conclusions, and

prevented from confessing the internal weaknesses which it cannot

but feel when it enters upon a rigid self-examination. If, on the

other hand, we were to ask Priestley- a philosopher who had no taste

for transcendental speculation, but was entirely devoted to the

principles of empiricism- what his motives were for overturning

those two main pillars of religion- the doctrines of the freedom of

the will and the immortality of the soul (in his view the hope of a

future life is but the expectation of the miracle of resurrection)-

this philosopher, himself a zealous and pious teacher of religion,

could give no other answer than this: I acted in the interest of

reason, which always suffers, when certain objects are explained and

judged by a reference to other supposed laws than those of material

nature- the only laws which we know in a determinate manner. It

would be unfair to decry the latter philosopher, who endeavoured to

harmonize his paradoxical opinions with the interests of religion, and

to undervalue an honest and reflecting man, because he finds himself

at a loss the moment he has left the field of natural science. The

same grace must be accorded to Hume, a man not less well-disposed, and

quite as blameless in his moral character, and who pushed his abstract

speculations to an extreme length, because, as he rightly believed,

the object of them lies entirely beyond the bounds of natural science,

and within the sphere of pure ideas.

  What is to be done to provide against the danger which seems in

the present case to menace the best interests of humanity? The

course to be pursued in reference to this subject is a perfectly plain

and natural one. Let each thinker pursue his own path; if he shows

talent, if be gives evidence of profound thought, in one word, if he

shows that he possesses the power of reasoning- reason is always the

gainer. If you have recourse to other means, if you attempt to

coerce reason, if you raise the cry of treason to humanity, if you

excite the feelings of the crowd, which can neither understand nor

sympathize with such subtle speculations- you will only make

yourselves ridiculous. For the question does not concern the advantage

or disadvantage which we are expected to reap from such inquiries; the

question is merely how far reason can advance in the field of

speculation, apart from all kinds of interest, and whether we may

depend upon the exertions of speculative reason, or must renounce

all reliance on it. Instead of joining the combatants, it is your part

to be a tranquil spectator of the struggle- a laborious struggle for

the parties engaged, but attended, in its progress as well as in its

result, with the most advantageous consequences for the interests of

thought and knowledge. It is absurd to expect to be enlightened by

Reason, and at the same time to prescribe to her what side of the

question she must adopt. Moreover, reason is sufficiently held in

check by its own power, the limits imposed on it by its own nature are

sufficient; it is unnecessary for you to place over it additional

guards, as if its power were dangerous to the constitution of the

intellectual state. In the dialectic of reason there is no victory

gained which need in the least disturb your tranquility.

  The strife of dialectic is a necessity of reason, and we cannot

but wish that it had been conducted long ere this with that perfect

freedom which ought to be its essential condition. In this case, we

should have had at an earlier period a matured and profound criticism,

which must have put an end to all dialectical disputes, by exposing

the illusions and prejudices in which they originated.

  There is in human nature an unworthy propensity- a propensity which,

like everything that springs from nature, must in its final purpose be

conducive to the good of humanity- to conceal our real sentiments, and

to give expression only to certain received opinions, which are

regarded as at once safe and promotive of the common good. It is true,

this tendency, not only to conceal our real sentiments, but to profess

those which may gain us favour in the eyes of society, has not only

civilized, but, in a certain measure, moralized us; as no one can

break through the outward covering of respectability, honour, and

morality, and thus the seemingly-good examples which we which we see

around us form an excellent school for moral improvement, so long as

our belief in their genuineness remains unshaken. But this disposition

to represent ourselves as better than we are, and to utter opinions

which are not our own, can be nothing more than a kind of provisionary

arrangement of nature to lead us from the rudeness of an uncivilized

state, and to teach us how to assume at least the appearance and

manner of the good we see. But when true principles have been

developed, and have obtained a sure foundation in our habit of

thought, this conventionalism must be attacked with earnest vigour,

otherwise it corrupts the heart, and checks the growth of good

dispositions with the mischievous weed of air appearances.

  I am sorry to remark the same tendency to misrepresentation and

hypocrisy in the sphere of speculative discussion, where there is less

temptation to restrain the free expression of thought. For what can be

more prejudicial to the interests of intelligence than to falsify

our real sentiments, to conceal the doubts which we feel in regard

to our statements, or to maintain the validity of grounds of proof

which we well know to be insufficient? So long as mere personal vanity

is the source of these unworthy artifices- and this is generally the

case in speculative discussions, which are mostly destitute of

practical interest, and are incapable of complete demonstration- the

vanity of the opposite party exaggerates as much on the other side;

and thus the result is the same, although it is not brought about so

soon as if the dispute had been conducted in a sincere and upright

spirit. But where the mass entertains the notion that the aim of

certain subtle speculators is nothing less than to shake the very

foundations of public welfare and morality- it seems not only prudent,

but even praise worthy, to maintain the good cause by illusory

arguments, rather than to give to our supposed opponents the advantage

of lowering our declarations to the moderate tone of a merely

practical conviction, and of compelling us to confess our inability to

attain to apodeictic certainty in speculative subjects. But we ought

to reflect that there is nothing, in the world more fatal to the

maintenance of a good cause than deceit, misrepresentation, and

falsehood. That the strictest laws of honesty should be observed in

the discussion of a purely speculative subject is the least

requirement that can be made. If we could reckon with security even

upon so little, the conflict of speculative reason regarding the

important questions of God, immortality, and freedom, would have

been either decided long ago, or would very soon be brought to a

conclusion. But, in general, the uprightness of the defence stands

in an inverse ratio to the goodness of the cause; and perhaps more

honesty and fairness are shown by those who deny than by those who

uphold these doctrines.

  I shall persuade myself, then, that I have readers who do not wish

to see a righteous cause defended by unfair arguments. Such will now

recognize the fact that, according to the principles of this Critique,

if we consider not what is, but what ought to be the case, there can

be really no polemic of pure reason. For how can two persons dispute

about a thing, the reality of which neither can present in actual or

even in possible experience? Each adopts the plan of meditating on his

idea for the purpose of drawing from the idea, if he can, what is more

than the idea, that is, the reality of the object which it

indicates. How shall they settle the dispute, since neither is able to

make his assertions directly comprehensible and certain, but must

restrict himself to attacking and confuting those of his opponent? All

statements enounced by pure reason transcend the conditions of

possible experience, beyond the sphere of which we can discover no

criterion of truth, while they are at the same time framed in

accordance with the laws of the understanding, which are applicable

only to experience; and thus it is the fate of all such speculative

discussions that while the one party attacks the weaker side of his

opponent, he infallibly lays open his own weaknesses.

  The critique of pure reason may be regarded as the highest

tribunal for all speculative disputes; for it is not involved in these

disputes, which have an immediate relation to certain objects and

not to the laws of the mind, but is instituted for the purpose of

determining the rights and limits of reason.

  Without the control of criticism, reason is, as it were, in a

state of nature, and can only establish its claims and assertions by

war. Criticism, on the contrary, deciding all questions according to

the fundamental laws of its own institution, secures to us the peace

of law and order, and enables us to discuss all differences in the

more tranquil manner of a legal process. In the former case,

disputes are ended by victory, which both sides may claim and which is

followed by a hollow armistice; in the latter, by a sentence, which,

as it strikes at the root of all speculative differences, ensures to

all concerned a lasting peace. The endless disputes of a dogmatizing

reason compel us to look for some mode of arriving at a settled

decision by a critical investigation of reason itself; just as

Hobbes maintains that the state of nature is a state of injustice

and violence, and that we must leave it and submit ourselves to the

constraint of law, which indeed limits individual freedom, but only

that it may consist with the freedom of others and with the common

good of all.

  This freedom will, among other things, permit of our openly

stating the difficulties and doubts which we are ourselves unable to

solve, without being decried on that account as turbulent and

dangerous citizens. This privilege forms part of the native rights

of human reason, which recognizes no other judge than the universal

reason of humanity; and as this reason is the source of all progress

and improvement, such a privilege is to be held sacred and inviolable.

It is unwise, moreover, to denounce as dangerous any bold assertions

against, or rash attacks upon, an opinion which is held by the largest

and most moral class of the community; for that would be giving them

an importance which they do not deserve. When I hear that the

freedom of the will, the hope of a future life, and the existence of

God have been overthrown by the arguments of some able writer, I

feel a strong desire to read his book; for I expect that he will add

to my knowledge and impart greater clearness and distinctness to my

views by the argumentative power shown in his writings. But I am

perfectly certain, even before I have opened the book, that he has not

succeeded in a single point, not because I believe I am in

possession of irrefutable demonstrations of these important

propositions, but because this transcendental critique, which has

disclosed to me the power and the limits of pure reason, has fully

convinced me that, as it is insufficient to establish the affirmative,

it is as powerless, and even more so, to assure us of the truth of the

negative answer to these questions. From what source does this

free-thinker derive his knowledge that there is, for example, no

Supreme Being? This proposition lies out of the field of possible

experience, and, therefore, beyond the limits of human cognition.

But I would not read at, all the answer which the dogmatical

maintainer of the good cause makes to his opponent, because I know

well beforehand, that he will merely attack the fallacious grounds

of his adversary, without being able to establish his own

assertions. Besides, a new illusory argument, in the construction of

which talent and acuteness are shown, is suggestive of new ideas and

new trains of reasoning, and in this respect the old and everyday

sophistries are quite useless. Again, the dogmatical opponent of

religion gives employment to criticism, and enables us to test and

correct its principles, while there is no occasion for anxiety in

regard to the influence and results of his reasoning.

  But, it will be said, must we not warn the youth entrusted to

academical care against such writings, must we not preserve them

from the knowledge of these dangerous assertions, until their

judgement is ripened, or rather until the doctrines which we wish to

inculcate are so firmly rooted in their minds as to withstand all

attempts at instilling the contrary dogmas, from whatever quarter they

may come?

  If we are to confine ourselves to the dogmatical procedure in the

sphere of pure reason, and find ourselves unable to settle such

disputes otherwise than by becoming a party in them, and setting

counter-assertions against the statements advanced by our opponents,

there is certainly no plan more advisable for the moment, but, at

the same time, none more absurd and inefficient for the future, than

this retaining of the youthful mind under guardianship for a time, and

thus preserving it- for so long at least- from seduction into error.

But when, at a later period, either curiosity, or the prevalent

fashion of thought places such writings in their hands, will the

so-called convictions of their youth stand firm? The young thinker,

who has in his armoury none but dogmatical weapons with which to

resist the attacks of his opponent, and who cannot detect the latent

dialectic which lies in his own opinions as well as in those of the

opposite party, sees the advance of illusory arguments and grounds

of proof which have the advantage of novelty, against as illusory

grounds of proof destitute of this advantage, and which, perhaps,

excite the suspicion that the natural credulity of his youth has

been abused by his instructors. He thinks he can find no better

means of showing that he has out grown the discipline of his

minority than by despising those well-meant warnings, and, knowing

no system of thought but that of dogmatism, he drinks deep draughts of

the poison that is to sap the principles in which his early years were

trained.

  Exactly the opposite of the system here recommended ought to be

pursued in academical instruction. This can only be effected, however,

by a thorough training in the critical investigation of pure reason.

For, in order to bring the principles of this critique into exercise

as soon as possible, and to demonstrate their perfect even in the

presence of the highest degree of dialectical illusion, the student

ought to examine the assertions made on both sides of speculative

questions step by step, and to test them by these principles. It

cannot be a difficult task for him to show the fallacies inherent in

these propositions, and thus he begins early to feel his own power

of securing himself against the influence of such sophistical

arguments, which must finally lose, for him, all their illusory power.

And, although the same blows which overturn the edifice of his

opponent are as fatal to his own speculative structures, if such he

has wished to rear; he need not feel any sorrow in regard to this

seeming misfortune, as he has now before him a fair prospect into

the practical region in which he may reasonably hope to find a more

secure foundation for a rational system.

  There is, accordingly, no proper polemic in the sphere of pure

reason. Both parties beat the air and fight with their own shadows, as

they pass beyond the limits of nature, and can find no tangible

point of attack- no firm footing for their dogmatical conflict.

Fight as vigorously as they may, the shadows which they hew down,

immediately start up again, like the heroes in Walhalla, and renew the

bloodless and unceasing contest.

  But neither can we admit that there is any proper sceptical

employment of pure reason, such as might be based upon the principle

of neutrality in all speculative disputes. To excite reason against

itself, to place weapons in the hands of the party on the one side

as well as in those of the other, and to remain an undisturbed and

sarcastic spectator of the fierce struggle that ensues, seems, from

the dogmatical point of view, to be a part fitting only a malevolent

disposition. But, when the sophist evidences an invincible obstinacy

and blindness, and a pride which no criticism can moderate, there is

no other practicable course than to oppose to this pride and obstinacy

similar feelings and pretensions on the other side, equally well or

ill founded, so that reason, staggered by the reflections thus

forced upon it, finds it necessary to moderate its confidence in

such pretensions and to listen to the advice of criticism. But we

cannot stop at these doubts, much less regard the conviction of our

ignorance, not only as a cure for the conceit natural to dogmatism,

but as the settlement of the disputes in which reason is involved with

itself. On the contrary, scepticism is merely a means of awakening

reason from its dogmatic dreams and exciting it to a more careful

investigation into its own powers and pretensions. But, as

scepticism appears to be the shortest road to a permanent peace in the

domain of philosophy, and as it is the track pursued by the many who

aim at giving a philosophical colouring to their contemptuous

dislike of all inquiries of this kind, I think it necessary to present

to my readers this mode of thought in its true light.



     Scepticism not a Permanent State for Human Reason.



  The consciousness of ignorance- unless this ignorance is

recognized to be absolutely necessary ought, instead of forming the

conclusion of my inquiries, to be the strongest motive to the

pursuit of them. All ignorance is either ignorance of things or of the

limits of knowledge. If my ignorance is accidental and not

necessary, it must incite me, in the first case, to a dogmatical

inquiry regarding the objects of which I am ignorant; in the second,

to a critical investigation into the bounds of all possible knowledge.

But that my ignorance is absolutely necessary and unavoidable, and

that it consequently absolves from the duty of all further

investigation, is a fact which cannot be made out upon empirical

grounds- from observation- but upon critical grounds alone, that is,

by a thoroughgoing investigation into the primary sources of

cognition. It follows that the determination of the bounds of reason

can be made only on a priori grounds; while the empirical limitation

of reason, which is merely an indeterminate cognition of an

ignorance that can never be completely removed, can take place only

a posteriori. In other words, our empirical knowledge is limited by

that which yet remains for us to know. The former cognition of our

ignorance, which is possible only on a rational basis, is a science;

the latter is merely a perception, and we cannot say how far the

inferences drawn from it may extend. If I regard the earth, as it

really appears to my senses, as a flat surface, I am ignorant how

far this surface extends. But experience teaches me that, how far

soever I go, I always see before me a space in which I can proceed

farther; and thus I know the limits- merely visual- of my actual

knowledge of the earth, although I am ignorant of the limits of the

earth itself. But if I have got so far as to know that the earth is

a sphere, and that its surface is spherical, I can cognize a priori

and determine upon principles, from my knowledge of a small part of

this surface- say to the extent of a degree- the diameter and

circumference of the earth; and although I am ignorant of the

objects which this surface contains, I have a perfect knowledge of its

limits and extent.

  The sum of all the possible objects of our cognition seems to us

to be a level surface, with an apparent horizon- that which forms

the limit of its extent, and which has been termed by us the idea of

unconditioned totality. To reach this limit by empirical means is

impossible, and all attempts to determine it a priori according to a

principle, are alike in vain. But all the questions raised by pure

reason relate to that which lies beyond this horizon, or, at least, in

its boundary line.

  The celebrated David Hume was one of those geographers of human

reason who believe that they have given a sufficient answer to all

such questions by declaring them to lie beyond the horizon of our

knowledge- a horizon which, however, Hume was unable to determine. His

attention especially was directed to the principle of causality; and

he remarked with perfect justice that the truth of this principle, and

even the objective validity of the conception of a cause, was not

commonly based upon clear insight, that is, upon a priori cognition.

Hence he concluded that this law does not derive its authority from

its universality and necessity, but merely from its general

applicability in the course of experience, and a kind of subjective

necessity thence arising, which he termed habit. From the inability of

reason to establish this principle as a necessary law for the

acquisition of all experience, he inferred the nullity of all the

attempts of reason to pass the region of the empirical.

  This procedure of subjecting the facta of reason to examination,

and, if necessary, to disapproval, may be termed the censura of

reason. This censura must inevitably lead us to doubts regarding all

transcendent employment of principles. But this is only the second

step in our inquiry. The first step in regard to the subjects of

pure reason, and which marks the infancy of that faculty, is that of

dogmatism. The second, which we have just mentioned, is that of

scepticism, and it gives evidence that our judgement has been improved

by experience. But a third step is necessary- indicative of the

maturity and manhood of the judgement, which now lays a firm

foundation upon universal and necessary principles. This is the period

of criticism, in which we do not examine the facta of reason, but

reason itself, in the whole extent of its powers, and in regard to its

capability of a priori cognition; and thus we determine not merely the

empirical and ever-shifting bounds of our knowledge, but its necessary

and eternal limits. We demonstrate from indubitable principles, not

merely our ignorance in respect to this or that subject, but in regard

to all possible questions of a certain class. Thus scepticism is a

resting place for reason, in which it may reflect on its dogmatical

wanderings and gain some knowledge of the region in which it happens

to be, that it may pursue its way with greater certainty; but it

cannot be its permanent dwelling-place. It must take up its abode only

in the region of complete certitude, whether this relates to the

cognition of objects themselves, or to the limits which bound all

our cognition.

  Reason is not to be considered as an indefinitely extended plane, of

the bounds of which we have only a general knowledge; it ought

rather to be compared to a sphere, the radius of which may be found

from the curvature of its surface- that is, the nature of a priori

synthetical propositions- and, consequently, its circumference and

extent. Beyond the sphere of experience there are no objects which

it can cognize; nay, even questions regarding such supposititious

objects relate only to the subjective principles of a complete

determination of the relations which exist between the

understanding-conceptions which lie within this sphere.

  We are actually in possession of a priori synthetical cognitions, as

is proved by the existence of the principles of the understanding,

which anticipate experience. If any one cannot comprehend the

possibility of these principles, he may have some reason to doubt

whether they are really a priori; but he cannot on this account

declare them to be impossible, and affirm the nullity of the steps

which reason may have taken under their guidance. He can only say:

If we perceived their origin and their authenticity, we should be able

to determine the extent and limits of reason; but, till we can do

this, all propositions regarding the latter are mere random

assertions. In this view, the doubt respecting all dogmatical

philosophy, which proceeds without the guidance of criticism, is

well grounded; but we cannot therefore deny to reason the ability to

construct a sound philosophy, when the way has been prepared by a

thorough critical investigation. All the conceptions produced, and all

the questions raised, by pure reason, do not lie in the sphere of

experience, but in that of reason itself, and hence they must be

solved, and shown to be either valid or inadmissible, by that faculty.

We have no right to decline the solution of such problems, on the

ground that the solution can be discovered only from the nature of

things, and under pretence of the limitation of human faculties, for

reason is the sole creator of all these ideas, and is therefore

bound either to establish their validity or to expose their illusory

nature.

  The polemic of scepticism is properly directed against the

dogmatist, who erects a system of philosophy without having examined

the fundamental objective principles on which it is based, for the

purpose of evidencing the futility of his designs, and thus bringing

him to a knowledge of his own powers. But, in itself, scepticism

does not give us any certain information in regard to the bounds of

our knowledge. All unsuccessful dogmatical attempts of reason are

facia, which it is always useful to submit to the censure of the

sceptic. But this cannot help us to any decision regarding the

expectations which reason cherishes of better success in future

endeavours; the investigations of scepticism cannot, therefore, settle

the dispute regarding the rights and powers of human reason.

  Hume is perhaps the ablest and most ingenious of all sceptical

philosophers, and his writings have, undoubtedly, exerted the most

powerful influence in awakening reason to a thorough investigation

into its own powers. It will, therefore, well repay our labours to

consider for a little the course of reasoning which he followed and

the errors into which he strayed, although setting out on the path

of truth and certitude.

  Hume was probably aware, although he never clearly developed the

notion, that we proceed in judgements of a certain class beyond our

conception if the object. I have termed this kind of judgement

synthetical. As regard the manner in which I pass beyond my conception

by the aid of experience, no doubts can be entertained. Experience

is itself a synthesis of perceptions; and it employs perceptions to

increment the conception, which I obtain by means of another

perception. But we feel persuaded that we are able to proceed beyond a

conception, and to extend our cognition a priori. We attempt this in

two ways- either, through the pure understanding, in relation to

that which may become an object of experience, or, through pure

reason, in relation to such properties of things, or of the

existence of things, as can never be presented in any experience. This

sceptical philosopher did not distinguish these two kinds of

judgements, as he ought to have done, but regarded this augmentation

of conceptions, and, if we may so express ourselves, the spontaneous

generation of understanding and reason, independently of the

impregnation of experience, as altogether impossible. The so-called

a priori principles of these faculties he consequently held to be

invalid and imaginary, and regarded them as nothing but subjective

habits of thought originating in experience, and therefore purely

empirical and contingent rules, to which we attribute a spurious

necessity and universality. In support of this strange assertion, he

referred us to the generally acknowledged principle of the relation

between cause and effect. No faculty of the mind can conduct us from

the conception of a thing to the existence of something else; and

hence he believed he could infer that, without experience, we

possess no source from which we can augment a conception, and no

ground sufficient to justify us in framing a judgement that is to

extend our cognition a priori. That the light of the sun, which shines

upon a piece of wax, at the same time melts it, while it hardens clay,

no power of the understanding could infer from the conceptions which

we previously possessed of these substances; much less is there any

a priori law that could conduct us to such a conclusion, which

experience alone can certify. On the other hand, we have seen in our

discussion of transcendental logic, that, although we can never

proceed immediately beyond the content of the conception which is

given us, we can always cognize completely a priori- in relation,

however, to a third term, namely, possible experience- the law of

its connection with other things. For example, if I observe that a

piece of wax melts, I can cognize a priori that there must have been

something (the sun's heat) preceding, which this law; although,

without the aid of experience, I could not cognize a priori and in a

determinate manner either the cause from the effect, or the effect

from the cause. Hume was, therefore, wrong in inferring, from the

contingency of the determination according to law, the contingency

of the law itself; and the passing beyond the conception of a thing to

possible experience (which is an a priori proceeding, constituting the

objective reality of the conception), he confounded with our synthesis

of objects in actual experience, which is always, of course,

empirical. Thus, too, he regarded the principle of affinity, which has

its seat in the understanding and indicates a necessary connection, as

a mere rule of association, lying in the imitative faculty of

imagination, which can present only contingent, and not objective

connections.

  The sceptical errors of this remarkably acute thinker arose

principally from a defect, which was common to him with the

dogmatists, namely, that he had never made a systematic review of

all the different kinds of a priori synthesis performed by the

understanding. Had he done so, he would have found, to take one

example among many, that the principle of permanence was of this

character, and that it, as well as the principle of causality,

anticipates experience. In this way he might have been able to

describe the determinate limits of the a priori operations of

understanding and reason. But he merely declared the understanding

to be limited, instead of showing what its limits were; he created a

general mistrust in the power of our faculties, without giving us

any determinate knowledge of the bounds of our necessary and

unavoidable ignorance; he examined and condemned some of the

principles of the understanding, without investigating all its

powers with the completeness necessary to criticism. He denies, with

truth, certain powers to the understanding, but he goes further, and

declares it to be utterly inadequate to the a priori extension of

knowledge, although he has not fully examined all the powers which

reside in the faculty; and thus the fate which always overtakes

scepticism meets him too. That is to say, his own declarations are

doubted, for his objections were based upon facta, which are

contingent, and not upon principles, which can alone demonstrate the

necessary invalidity of all dogmatical assertions.

  As Hume makes no distinction between the well-grounded claims of the

understanding and the dialectical pretensions of reason, against

which, however, his attacks are mainly directed, reason does not

feel itself shut out from all attempts at the extension of a priori

cognition, and hence it refuses, in spite of a few checks in this or

that quarter, to relinquish such efforts. For one naturally arms

oneself to resist an attack, and becomes more obstinate in the resolve

to establish the claims he has advanced. But a complete review of

the powers of reason, and the conviction thence arising that we are in

possession of a limited field of action, while we must admit the

vanity of higher claims, puts an end to all doubt and dispute, and

induces reason to rest satisfied with the undisturbed possession of

its limited domain.

  To the uncritical dogmatist, who has not surveyed the sphere of

his understanding, nor determined, in accordance with principles,

the limits of possible cognition, who, consequently, is ignorant of

his own powers, and believes he will discover them by the attempts

he makes in the field of cognition, these attacks of scepticism are

not only dangerous, but destructive. For if there is one proposition

in his chain of reasoning which be he cannot prove, or the fallacy

in which be cannot evolve in accordance with a principle, suspicion

falls on all his statements, however plausible they may appear.

  And thus scepticism, the bane of dogmatical philosophy, conducts

us to a sound investigation into the understanding and the reason.

When we are thus far advanced, we need fear no further

attacks; for the limits of our domain are clearly marked out, and we

can make no claims nor become involved in any disputes regarding the

region that lies beyond these limits. Thus the sceptical procedure

in philosophy does not present any solution of the problems of reason,

but it forms an excellent exercise for its powers, awakening its

circumspection, and indicating the means whereby it may most fully

establish its claims to its legitimate possessions.



    SECTION III. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Hypothesis.



  This critique of reason has now taught us that all its efforts to

extend the bounds of knowledge, by means of pure speculation, are

utterly fruitless. So much the wider field, it may appear, lies open

to hypothesis; as, where we cannot know with certainty, we are at

liberty to make guesses and to form suppositions.

  Imagination may be allowed, under the strict surveillance of reason,

to invent suppositions; but, these must be based on something that

is perfectly certain- and that is the possibility of the object. If we

are well assured upon this point, it is allowable to have recourse

to supposition in regard to the reality of the object; but this

supposition must, unless it is utterly groundless, be connected, as

its ground of explanation, with that which is really given and

absolutely certain. Such a supposition is termed a hypothesis.

  It is beyond our power to form the least conception a priori of

the possibility of dynamical connection in phenomena; and the category

of the pure understanding will not enable us to ex. cogitate any

such connection, but merely helps us to understand it, when we meet

with it in experience. For this reason we cannot, in accordance with

the categories, imagine or invent any object or any property of an

object not given, or that may not be given in experience, and employ

it in a hypothesis; otherwise, we should be basing our chain of

reasoning upon mere chimerical fancies, and not upon conceptions of

things. Thus, we have no right to assume the existence of new

powers, not existing in nature- for example, an understanding with a

non-sensuous intuition, a force of attraction without contact, or some

new kind of substances occupying space, and yet without the property

of impenetrability- and, consequently, we cannot assume that there

is any other kind of community among substances than that observable

in experience, any kind of presence than that in space, or any kind of

duration than that in time. In one word, the conditions of possible

experience are for reason the only conditions of the possibility of

things; reason cannot venture to form, independently of these

conditions, any conceptions of things, because such conceptions,

although not self-contradictory, are without object and without

application.

  The conceptions of reason are, as we have already shown, mere ideas,

and do not relate to any object in any kind of experience. At the same

time, they do not indicate imaginary or possible objects. They are

purely problematical in their nature and, as aids to the heuristic

exercise of the faculties, form the basis of the regulative principles

for the systematic employment of the understanding in the field of

experience. If we leave this ground of experience, they become mere

fictions of thought, the possibility of which is quite indemonstrable;

and they cannot, consequently, be employed as hypotheses in the

explanation of real phenomena. It is quite admissible to cogitate

the soul as simple, for the purpose of enabling ourselves to employ

the idea of a perfect and necessary unity of all the faculties of

the mind as the principle of all our inquiries into its internal

phenomena, although we cannot cognize this unity in concreto. But to

assume that the soul is a simple substance (a transcendental

conception) would be enouncing a proposition which is not only

indemonstrable- as many physical hypotheses are- but a proposition

which is purely arbitrary, and in the highest degree rash. The

simple is never presented in experience; and, if by substance is

here meant the permanent object of sensuous intuition, the possibility

of a simple phenomenon is perfectly inconceivable. Reason affords no

good grounds for admitting the existence of intelligible beings, or of

intelligible properties of sensuous things, although- as we have no

conception either of their possibility or of their impossibility- it

will always be out of our power to affirm dogmatically that they do

not exist. In the explanation of given phenomena, no other things

and no other grounds of explanation can be employed than those which

stand in connection with the given phenomena according to the known

laws of experience. A transcendental hypothesis, in which a mere

idea of reason is employed to explain the phenomena of nature, would

not give us any better insight into a phenomenon, as we should be

trying to explain what we do not sufficiently understand from known

empirical principles, by what we do not understand at all. The

principles of such a hypothesis might conduce to the satisfaction of

reason, but it would not assist the understanding in its application

to objects. Order and conformity to aims in the sphere of nature

must be themselves explained upon natural grounds and according to

natural laws; and the wildest hypotheses, if they are only physical,

are here more admissible than a hyperphysical hypothesis, such as that

of a divine author. For such a hypothesis would introduce the

principle of ignava ratio, which requires us to give up the search for

causes that might be discovered in the course of experience and to

rest satisfied with a mere idea. As regards the absolute totality of

the grounds of explanation in the series of these causes, this can

be no hindrance to the understanding in the case of phenomena;

because, as they are to us nothing more than phenomena, we have no

right to look for anything like completeness in the synthesis of the

series of their conditions.

  Transcendental hypotheses are therefore inadmissible; and we

cannot use the liberty of employing, in the absence of physical,

hyperphysical grounds of explanation. And this for two reasons; first,

because such hypothesis do not advance reason, but rather stop it in

its progress; secondly, because this licence would render fruitless

all its exertions in its own proper sphere, which is that of

experience. For, when the explanation of natural phenomena happens

to be difficult, we have constantly at hand a transcendental ground of

explanation, which lifts us above the necessity of investigating

nature; and our inquiries are brought to a close, not because we

have obtained all the requisite knowledge, but because we abut upon

a principle which is incomprehensible and which, indeed, is so far

back in the track of thought as to contain the conception of the

absolutely primal being.

  The next requisite for the admissibility of a hypothesis is its

sufficiency. That is, it must determine a priori the consequences

which are given in experience and which are supposed to follow from

the hypothesis itself. If we require to employ auxiliary hypotheses,

the suspicion naturally arises that they are mere fictions; because

the necessity for each of them requires the same justification as in

the case of the original hypothesis, and thus their testimony is

invalid. If we suppose the existence of an infinitely perfect cause,

we possess sufficient grounds for the explanation of the conformity to

aims, the order and the greatness which we observe in the universe;

but we find ourselves obliged, when we observe the evil in the world

and the exceptions to these laws, to employ new hypothesis in

support of the original one. We employ the idea of the simple nature

of the human soul as the foundation of all the theories we may form of

its phenomena; but when we meet with difficulties in our way, when

we observe in the soul phenomena similar to the changes which take

place in matter, we require to call in new auxiliary hypotheses. These

may, indeed, not be false, but we do not know them to be true, because

the only witness to their certitude is the hypothesis which they

themselves have been called in to explain.

  We are not discussing the above-mentioned assertions regarding the

immaterial unity of the soul and the existence of a Supreme Being as

dogmata, which certain philosophers profess to demonstrate a priori,

but purely as hypotheses. In the former case, the dogmatist must

take care that his arguments possess the apodeictic certainty of a

demonstration. For the assertion that the reality of such ideas is

probable is as absurd as a proof of the probability of a proposition

in geometry. Pure abstract reason, apart from all experience, can

either cognize nothing at all; and hence the judgements it enounces

are never mere opinions, they are either apodeictic certainties, or

declarations that nothing can be known on the subject. Opinions and

probable judgements on the nature of things can only be employed to

explain given phenomena, or they may relate to the effect, in

accordance with empirical laws, of an actually existing cause. In

other words, we must restrict the sphere of opinion to the world of

experience and nature. Beyond this region opinion is mere invention;

unless we are groping about for the truth on a path not yet fully

known, and have some hopes of stumbling upon it by chance.

  But, although hypotheses are inadmissible in answers to the

questions of pure speculative reason, they may be employed in the

defence of these answers. That is to say, hypotheses are admissible in

polemic, but not in the sphere of dogmatism. By the defence of

statements of this character, I do not mean an attempt at

discovering new grounds for their support, but merely the refutation

of the arguments of opponents. All a priori synthetical propositions

possess the peculiarity that, although the philosopher who maintains

the reality of the ideas contained in the proposition is not in

possession of sufficient knowledge to establish the certainty of his

statements, his opponent is as little able to prove the truth of the

opposite. This equality of fortune does not allow the one party to

be superior to the other in the sphere of speculative cognition; and

it is this sphere, accordingly, that is the proper arena of these

endless speculative conflicts. But we shall afterwards show that, in

relation to its practical exercise, Reason has the right of

admitting what, in the field of pure speculation, she would not be

justified in supposing, except upon perfectly sufficient grounds;

because all such suppositions destroy the necessary completeness of

speculation- a condition which the practical reason, however, does not

consider to be requisite. In this sphere, therefore, Reason is

mistress of a possession, her title to which she does not require to

prove- which, in fact, she could not do. The burden of proof

accordingly rests upon the opponent. But as he has just as little

knowledge regarding the subject discussed, and is as little able to

prove the non-existence of the object of an idea, as the philosopher

on the other side is to demonstrate its reality, it is evident that

there is an advantage on the side of the philosopher who maintains his

proposition as a practically necessary supposition (melior est

conditio possidentis). For he is at liberty to employ, in

self-defence, the same weapons as his opponent makes use of in

attacking him; that is, he has a right to use hypotheses not for the

purpose of supporting the arguments in favour of his own propositions,

but to show that his opponent knows no more than himself regarding the

subject under 'discussion and cannot boast of any speculative

advantage.

  Hypotheses are, therefore, admissible in the sphere of pure reason

only as weapons for self-defence, and not as supports to dogmatical

assertions. But the opposing party we must always seek for in

ourselves. For speculative reason is, in the sphere of

transcendentalism, dialectical in its own nature. The difficulties and

objections we have to fear lie in ourselves. They are like old but

never superannuated claims; and we must seek them out, and settle them

once and for ever, if we are to expect a permanent peace. External

tranquility is hollow and unreal. The root of these contradictions,

which lies in the nature of human reason, must be destroyed; and

this can only be done by giving it, in the first instance, freedom

to grow, nay, by nourishing it, that it may send out shoots, and

thus betray its own existence. It is our duty, therefore, to try to

discover new objections, to put weapons in the bands of our

opponent, and to grant him the most favourable position in the arena

that he can wish. We have nothing to fear from these concessions; on

the contrary, we may rather hope that we shall thus make ourselves

master of a possession which no one will ever venture to dispute.

  The thinker requires, to be fully equipped, the hypotheses of pure

reason, which, although but leaden weapons (for they have not been

steeled in the armoury of experience), are as useful as any that can

be employed by his opponents. If, accordingly, we have assumed, from a

non-speculative point of view, the immaterial nature of the soul,

and are met by the objection that experience seems to prove that the

growth and decay of our mental faculties are mere modifications of the

sensuous organism- we can weaken the force of this objection by the

assumption that the body is nothing but the fundamental phenomenon, to

which, as a necessary condition, all sensibility, and consequently all

thought, relates in the present state of our existence; and that the

separation of soul and body forms the conclusion of the sensuous

exercise of our power of cognition and the beginning of the

intellectual. The body would, in this view of the question, be

regarded, not as the cause of thought, but merely as its restrictive

condition, as promotive of the sensuous and animal, but as a hindrance

to the pure and spiritual life; and the dependence of the animal

life on the constitution of the body, would not prove that the whole

life of man was also dependent on the state of the organism. We

might go still farther, and discover new objections, or carry out to

their extreme consequences those which have already been adduced.

  Generation, in the human race as well as among the irrational

animals, depends on so many accidents- of occasion, of proper

sustenance, of the laws enacted by the government of a country of vice

even, that it is difficult to believe in the eternal existence of a

being whose life has begun under circumstances so mean and trivial,

and so entirely dependent upon our own control. As regards the

continuance of the existence of the whole race, we need have no

difficulties, for accident in single cases is subject to general laws;

but, in the case of each individual, it would seem as if we could

hardly expect so wonderful an effect from causes so insignificant.

But, in answer to these objections, we may adduce the transcendental

hypothesis that all life is properly intelligible, and not subject

to changes of time, and that it neither began in birth, nor will end

in death. We may assume that this life is nothing more than a sensuous

representation of pure spiritual life; that the whole world of sense

is but an image, hovering before the faculty of cognition which we

exercise in this sphere, and with no more objective reality than a

dream; and that if we could intuite ourselves and other things as they

really are, we should see ourselves in a world of spiritual natures,

our connection with which did not begin at our birth and will not

cease with the destruction of the body. And so on.

  We cannot be said to know what has been above asserted, nor do we

seriously maintain the truth of these assertions; and the notions

therein indicated are not even ideas of reason, they are purely

fictitious conceptions. But this hypothetical procedure is in

perfect conformity with the laws of reason. Our opponent mistakes

the absence of empirical conditions for a proof of the complete

impossibility of all that we have asserted; and we have to show him

that be has not exhausted the whole sphere of possibility and that

he can as little compass that sphere by the laws of experience and

nature, as we can lay a secure foundation for the operations of reason

beyond the region of experience. Such hypothetical defences against

the pretensions of an opponent must not be regarded as declarations of

opinion. The philosopher abandons them, so soon as the opposite

party renounces its dogmatical conceit. To maintain a simply

negative position in relation to propositions which rest on an

insecure foundation, well befits the moderation of a true philosopher;

but to uphold the objections urged against an opponent as proofs of

the opposite statement is a proceeding just as unwarrantable and

arrogant as it is to attack the position of a philosopher who advances

affirmative propositions regarding such a subject.

  It is evident, therefore, that hypotheses, in the speculative

sphere, are valid, not as independent propositions, but only

relatively to opposite transcendent assumptions. For, to make the

principles of possible experience conditions of the possibility of

things in general is just as transcendent a procedure as to maintain

the objective reality of ideas which can be applied to no objects

except such as lie without the limits of possible experience. The

judgements enounced by pure reason must be necessary, or they must not

be enounced at all. Reason cannot trouble herself with opinions. But

the hypotheses we have been discussing are merely problematical

judgements, which can neither be confuted nor proved; while,

therefore, they are not personal opinions, they are indispensable as

answers to objections which are liable to be raised. But we must

take care to confine them to this function, and guard against any

assumption on their part of absolute validity, a proceeding which

would involve reason in inextricable difficulties and contradictions.



     SECTION IV. The Discipline of Pure Reason in Relation

                       to Proofs.



  It is a peculiarity, which distinguishes the proofs of

transcendental synthetical propositions from those of all other a

priori synthetical cognitions, that reason, in the case of the former,

does not apply its conceptions directly to an object, but is first

obliged to prove, a priori, the objective validity of these

conceptions and the possibility of their syntheses. This is not merely

a prudential rule, it is essential to the very possibility of the

proof of a transcendental proposition. If I am required to pass, a

priori, beyond the conception of an object, I find that it is

utterly impossible without the guidance of something which is not

contained in the conception. In mathematics, it is a priori

intuition that guides my synthesis; and, in this case, all our

conclusions may be drawn immediately from pure intuition. In

transcendental cognition, so long as we are dealing only with

conceptions of the understanding, we are guided by possible

experience. That is to say, a proof in the sphere of transcendental

cognition does not show that the given conception (that of an event,

for example) leads directly to another conception (that of a cause)-

for this would be a saltus which nothing can justify; but it shows

that experience itself, and consequently the object of experience,

is impossible without the connection indicated by these conceptions.

It follows that such a proof must demonstrate the possibility of

arriving, synthetically and a priori, at a certain knowledge of

things, which was not contained in our conceptions of these things.

Unless we pay particular attention to this requirement, our proofs,

instead of pursuing the straight path indicated by reason, follow

the tortuous road of mere subjective association. The illusory

conviction, which rests upon subjective causes of association, and

which is considered as resulting from the perception of a real and

objective natural affinity, is always open to doubt and suspicion. For

this reason, all the attempts which have been made to prove the

principle of sufficient reason, have, according to the universal

admission of philosophers, been quite unsuccessful; and, before the

appearance of transcendental criticism, it was considered better, as

this principle could not be abandoned, to appeal boldly to the

common sense of mankind (a proceeding which always proves that the

problem, which reason ought to solve, is one in which philosophers

find great difficulties), rather than attempt to discover new

dogmatical proofs.

  But, if the proposition to be proved is a proposition of pure

reason, and if I aim at passing beyond my empirical conceptions by the

aid of mere ideas, it is necessary that the proof should first show

that such a step in synthesis is possible (which it is not), before it

proceeds to prove the truth of the proposition itself. The so-called

proof of the simple nature of the soul from the unity of apperception,

is a very plausible one. But it contains no answer to the objection,

that, as the notion of absolute simplicity is not a conception which

is directly applicable to a perception, but is an idea which must be

inferred- if at all- from observation, it is by no means evident how

the mere fact of consciousness, which is contained in all thought,

although in so far a simple representation, can conduct me to the

consciousness and cognition of a thing which is purely a thinking

substance. When I represent to my mind the power of my body as in

motion, my body in this thought is so far absolute unity, and my

representation of it is a simple one; and hence I can indicate this

representation by the motion of a point, because I have made

abstraction of the size or volume of the body. But I cannot hence

infer that, given merely the moving power of a body, the body may be

cogitated as simple substance, merely because the representation in my

mind takes no account of its content in space, and is consequently

simple. The simple, in abstraction, is very different from the

objectively simple; and hence the Ego, which is simple in the first

sense, may, in the second sense, as indicating the soul itself, be a

very complex conception, with a very various content. Thus it is

evident that in all such arguments there lurks a paralogism. We

guess (for without some such surmise our suspicion would not be

excited in reference to a proof of this character) at the presence

of the paralogism, by keeping ever before us a criterion of the

possibility of those synthetical propositions which aim at proving

more than experience can teach us. This criterion is obtained from the

observation that such proofs do not lead us directly from the

subject of the proposition to be proved to the required predicate, but

find it necessary to presuppose the possibility of extending our

cognition a priori by means of ideas. We must, accordingly, always use

the greatest caution; we require, before attempting any proof, to

consider how it is possible to extend the sphere of cognition by the

operations of pure reason, and from what source we are to derive

knowledge, which is not obtained from the analysis of conceptions, nor

relates, by anticipation, to possible experience. We shall thus

spare ourselves much severe and fruitless labour, by not expecting

from reason what is beyond its power, or rather by subjecting it to

discipline, and teaching it to moderate its vehement desires for the

extension of the sphere of cognition.

  The first rule for our guidance is, therefore, not to attempt a

transcendental proof, before we have considered from what source we

are to derive the principles upon which the proof is to be based,

and what right we have to expect that our conclusions from these

principles will be veracious. If they are principles of the

understanding, it is vain to expect that we should attain by their

means to ideas of pure reason; for these principles are valid only

in regard to objects of possible experience. If they are principles of

pure reason, our labour is alike in vain. For the principles of

reason, if employed as objective, are without exception dialectical

and possess no validity or truth, except as regulative principles of

the systematic employment of reason in experience. But when such

delusive proof are presented to us, it is our duty to meet them with

the non liquet of a matured judgement; and, although we are unable

to expose the particular sophism upon which the proof is based, we

have a right to demand a deduction of the principles employed in it;

and, if these principles have their origin in pure reason alone,

such a deduction is absolutely impossible. And thus it is

unnecessary that we should trouble ourselves with the exposure and

confutation of every sophistical illusion; we may, at once, bring

all dialectic, which is inexhaustible in the production of

fallacies, before the bar of critical reason, which tests the

principles upon which all dialectical procedure is based. The second

peculiarity of transcendental proof is that a transcendental

proposition cannot rest upon more than a single proof. If I am drawing

conclusions, not from conceptions, but from intuition corresponding to

a conception, be it pure intuition, as in mathematics, or empirical,

as in natural science, the intuition which forms the basis of my

inferences presents me with materials for many synthetical

propositions, which I can connect in various modes, while, as it is

allowable to proceed from different points in the intention, I can

arrive by different paths at the same proposition.

  But every transcendental proposition sets out from a conception, and

posits the synthetical condition of the possibility of an object

according to this conception. There must, therefore, be but one ground

of proof, because it is the conception alone which determines the

object; and thus the proof cannot contain anything more than the

determination of the object according to the conception. In our

Transcendental Analytic, for example, we inferred the principle: Every

event has a cause, from the only condition of the objective

possibility of our conception of an event. This is that an event

cannot be determined in time, and consequently cannot form a part of

experience, unless it stands under this dynamical law. This is the

only possible ground of proof; for our conception of an event

possesses objective validity, that is, is a true conception, only

because the law of causality determines an object to which it can

refer. Other arguments in support of this principle have been

attempted- such as that from the contingent nature of a phenomenon;

but when this argument is considered, we can discover no criterion

of contingency, except the fact of an event- of something happening,

that is to say, the existence which is preceded by the non-existence

of an object, and thus we fall back on the very thing to be proved. If

the proposition: "Every thinking being is simple," is to be proved, we

keep to the conception of the ego, which is simple, and to which all

thought has a relation. The same is the case with the transcendental

proof of the existence of a Deity, which is based solely upon the

harmony and reciprocal fitness of the conceptions of an ens

realissimum and a necessary being, and cannot be attempted in any

other manner.

  This caution serves to simplify very much the criticism of all

propositions of reason. When reason employs conceptions alone, only

one proof of its thesis is possible, if any. When, therefore, the

dogmatist advances with ten arguments in favour of a proposition, we

may be sure that not one of them is conclusive. For if he possessed

one which proved the proposition he brings forward to demonstration-

as must always be the case with the propositions of pure reason-

what need is there for any more? His intention can only be similar

to that of the advocate who had different arguments for different

judges; this availing himself of the weakness of those who examine his

arguments, who, without going into any profound investigation, adopt

the view of the case which seems most probable at first sight and

decide according to it.

  The third rule for the guidance of pure reason in the conduct of a

proof is that all transcendental proofs must never be apagogic or

indirect, but always ostensive or direct. The direct or ostensive

proof not only establishes the truth of the proposition to be

proved, but exposes the grounds of its truth; the apagogic, on the

other hand, may assure us of the truth of the proposition, but it

cannot enable us to comprehend the grounds of its possibility. The

latter is, accordingly, rather an auxiliary to an argument, than a

strictly philosophical and rational mode of procedure. In one respect,

however, they have an advantage over direct proofs, from the fact that

the mode of arguing by contradiction, which they employ, renders our

understanding of the question more clear, and approximates the proof

to the certainty of an intuitional demonstration.

  The true reason why indirect proofs are employed in different

sciences is this. When the grounds upon which we seek to base a

cognition are too various or too profound, we try whether or not we

may not discover the truth of our cognition from its consequences. The

modus ponens of reasoning from the truth of its inferences to the

truth of a proposition would be admissible if all the inferences

that can be drawn from it are known to be true; for in this case there

can be only one possible ground for these inferences, and that is

the true one. But this is a quite impracticable procedure, as it

surpasses all our powers to discover all the possible inferences

that can be drawn from a proposition. But this mode of reasoning is

employed, under favour, when we wish to prove the truth of an

hypothesis; in which case we admit the truth of the conclusion-

which is supported by analogy- that, if all the inferences we have

drawn and examined agree with the proposition assumed, all other

possible inferences will also agree with it. But, in this way, an

hypothesis can never be established as a demonstrated truth. The modus

tollens of reasoning from known inferences to the unknown proposition,

is not only a rigorous, but a very easy mode of proof. For, if it

can be shown that but one inference from a proposition is false,

then the proposition must itself be false. Instead, then, of

examining, in an ostensive argument, the whole series of the grounds

on which the truth of a proposition rests, we need only take the

opposite of this proposition, and if one inference from it be false,

then must the opposite be itself false; and, consequently, the

proposition which we wished to prove must be true.

  The apagogic method of proof is admissible only in those sciences

where it is impossible to mistake a subjective representation for an

objective cognition. Where this is possible, it is plain that the

opposite of a given proposition may contradict merely the subjective

conditions of thought, and not the objective cognition; or it may

happen that both propositions contradict each other only under a

subjective condition, which is incorrectly considered to be objective,

and, as the condition is itself false, both propositions may be false,

and it will, consequently, be impossible to conclude the truth of

the one from the falseness of the other.

  In mathematics such subreptions are impossible; and it is in this

science, accordingly, that the indirect mode of proof has its true

place. In the science of nature, where all assertion is based upon

empirical intuition, such subreptions may be guarded against by the

repeated comparison of observations; but this mode of proof is of

little value in this sphere of knowledge. But the transcendental

efforts of pure reason are all made in the sphere of the subjective,

which is the real medium of all dialectical illusion; and thus

reason endeavours, in its premisses, to impose upon us subjective

representations for objective cognitions. In the transcendental sphere

of pure reason, then, and in the case of synthetical propositions,

it is inadmissible to support a statement by disproving the

counter-statement. For only two cases are possible; either, the

counter-statement is nothing but the enouncement of the

inconsistency of the opposite opinion with the subjective conditions

of reason, which does not affect the real case (for example, we cannot

comprehend the unconditioned necessity of the existence of a being,

and hence every speculative proof of the existence of such a being

must be opposed on subjective grounds, while the possibility of this

being in itself cannot with justice be denied); or, both propositions,

being dialectical in their nature, are based upon an impossible

conception. In this latter case the rule applies: non entis nulla sunt

predicata; that is to say, what we affirm and what we deny, respecting

such an object, are equally untrue, and the apagogic mode of

arriving at the truth is in this case impossible. If, for example,

we presuppose that the world of sense is given in itself in its

totality, it is false, either that it is infinite, or that it is

finite and limited in space. Both are false, because the hypothesis is

false. For the notion of phenomena (as mere representations) which are

given in themselves (as objects) is self-contradictory; and the

infinitude of this imaginary whole would, indeed, be unconditioned,

but would be inconsistent (as everything in the phenomenal world is

conditioned) with the unconditioned determination and finitude of

quantities which is presupposed in our conception.

  The apagogic mode of proof is the true source of those illusions

which have always had so strong an attraction for the admirers of

dogmatical philosophy. It may be compared to a champion who

maintains the honour and claims of the party he has adopted by

offering battle to all who doubt the validity of these claims and

the purity of that honour; while nothing can be proved in this way,

except the respective strength of the combatants, and the advantage,

in this respect, is always on the side of the attacking party.

Spectators, observing that each party is alternately conqueror and

conquered, are led to regard the subject of dispute as beyond the

power of man to decide upon. But such an opinion cannot be

justified; and it is sufficient to apply to these reasoners the

remark:



                  Non defensoribus istis

        Tempus eget.



  Each must try to establish his assertions by a transcendental

deduction of the grounds of proof employed in his argument, and thus

enable us to see in what way the claims of reason may be supported. If

an opponent bases his assertions upon subjective grounds, he may be

refuted with ease; not, however to the advantage of the dogmatist, who

likewise depends upon subjective sources of cognition and is in like

manner driven into a corner by his opponent. But, if parties employ

the direct method of procedure, they will soon discover the

difficulty, nay, the impossibility of proving their assertions, and

will be forced to appeal to prescription and precedence; or they will,

by the help of criticism, discover with ease the dogmatical

illusions by which they had been mocked, and compel reason to renounce

its exaggerated pretensions to speculative insight and to confine

itself within the limits of its proper sphere- that of practical

principles.

            CHAPTER II. The Canon of Pure Reason.



  It is a humiliating consideration for human reason that it is

incompetent to discover truth by means of pure speculation, but, on

the contrary, stands in need of discipline to check its deviations

from the straight path and to expose the illusions which it

originates. But, on the other hand, this consideration ought to

elevate and to give it confidence, for this discipline is exercised by

itself alone, and it is subject to the censure of no other power.

The bounds, moreover, which it is forced to set to its speculative

exercise, form likewise a check upon the fallacious pretensions of

opponents; and thus what remains of its possessions, after these

exaggerated claims have been disallowed, is secure from attack or

usurpation. The greatest, and perhaps the only, use of all

philosophy of pure reason is, accordingly, of a purely negative

character. It is not an organon for the extension, but a discipline

for the determination, of the limits of its exercise; and without

laying claim to the discovery of new truth, it has the modest merit of

guarding against error.

  At the same time, there must be some source of positive cognitions

which belong to the domain of pure reason and which become the

causes of error only from our mistaking their true character, while

they form the goal towards which reason continually strives. How

else can we account for the inextinguishable desire in the human

mind to find a firm footing in some region beyond the limits of the

world of experience? It hopes to attain to the possession of a

knowledge in which it has the deepest interest. It enters upon the

path of pure speculation; but in vain. We have some reason, however,

to expect that, in the only other way that lies open to it- the path

of practical reason- it may meet with better success.

  I understand by a canon a list of the a priori principles of the

proper employment of certain faculties of cognition. Thus general

logic, in its analytical department, is a formal canon for the

faculties of understanding and reason. In the same way, Transcendental

Analytic was seen to be a canon of the pure understanding; for it

alone is competent to enounce true a priori synthetical cognitions.

But, when no proper employment of a faculty of cognition is

possible, no canon can exist. But the synthetical cognition of pure

speculative reason is, as has been shown, completely impossible. There

cannot, therefore, exist any canon for the speculative exercise of

this faculty- for its speculative exercise is entirely dialectical;

and, consequently, transcendental logic, in this respect, is merely

a discipline, and not a canon. If, then, there is any proper mode of

employing the faculty of pure reason- in which case there must be a

canon for this faculty- this canon will relate, not to the

speculative, but to the practical use of reason. This canon we now

proceed to investigate.



    SECTION I. Of the Ultimate End of the Pure Use of Reason.



  There exists in the faculty of reason a natural desire to venture

beyond the field of experience, to attempt to reach the utmost

bounds of all cognition by the help of ideas alone, and not to rest

satisfied until it has fulfilled its course and raised the sum of

its cognitions into a self-subsistent systematic whole. Is the

motive for this endeavour to be found in its speculative, or in its

practical interests alone?

  Setting aside, at present, the results of the labours of pure reason

in its speculative exercise, I shall merely inquire regarding the

problems the solution of which forms its ultimate aim, whether reached

or not, and in relation to which all other aims are but partial and

intermediate. These highest aims must, from the nature of reason,

possess complete unity; otherwise the highest interest of humanity

could not be successfully promoted.

  The transcendental speculation of reason relates to three things:

the freedom of the will, the immortality of the soul, and the

existence of God. The speculative interest which reason has in those

questions is very small; and, for its sake alone, we should not

undertake the labour of transcendental investigation- a labour full of

toil and ceaseless struggle. We should be loth to undertake this

labour, because the discoveries we might make would not be of the

smallest use in the sphere of concrete or physical investigation. We

may find out that the will is free, but this knowledge only relates to

the intelligible cause of our volition. As regards the phenomena or

expressions of this will, that is, our actions, we are bound, in

obedience to an inviolable maxim, without which reason cannot be

employed in the sphere of experience, to explain these in the same way

as we explain all the other phenomena of nature, that is to say,

according to its unchangeable laws. We may have discovered the

spirituality and immortality of the soul, but we cannot employ this

knowledge to explain the phenomena of this life, nor the peculiar

nature of the future, because our conception of an incorporeal

nature is purely negative and does not add anything to our

knowledge, and the only inferences to be drawn from it are purely

fictitious. If, again, we prove the existence of a supreme

intelligence, we should be able from it to make the conformity to aims

existing in the arrangement of the world comprehensible; but we should

not be justified in deducing from it any particular arrangement or

disposition, or inferring any where it is not perceived. For it is a

necessary rule of the speculative use of reason that we must not

overlook natural causes, or refuse to listen to the teaching of

experience, for the sake of deducing what we know and perceive from

something that transcends all our knowledge. In one word, these

three propositions are, for the speculative reason, always

transcendent, and cannot be employed as immanent principles in

relation to the objects of experience; they are, consequently, of no

use to us in this sphere, being but the valueless results of the

severe but unprofitable efforts of reason.

  If, then, the actual cognition of these three cardinal

propositions is perfectly useless, while Reason uses her utmost

endeavours to induce us to admit them, it is plain that their real

value and importance relate to our practical, and not to our

speculative interest.

  I term all that is possible through free will, practical. But if the

conditions of the exercise of free volition are empirical, reason

can have only a regulative, and not a constitutive, influence upon it,

and is serviceable merely for the introduction of unity into its

empirical laws. In the moral philosophy of prudence, for example,

the sole business of reason is to bring about a union of all the ends,

which are aimed at by our inclinations, into one ultimate end- that of

happiness- and to show the agreement which should exist among the

means of attaining that end. In this sphere, accordingly, reason

cannot present to us any other than pragmatical laws of free action,

for our guidance towards the aims set up by the senses, and is

incompetent to give us laws which are pure and determined completely a

priori. On the other hand, pure practical laws, the ends of which have

been given by reason entirely a priori, and which are not

empirically conditioned, but are, on the contrary, absolutely

imperative in their nature, would be products of pure reason. Such are

the moral laws; and these alone belong to the sphere of the

practical exercise of reason, and admit of a canon.

  All the powers of reason, in the sphere of what may be termed pure

philosophy, are, in fact, directed to the three above-mentioned

problems alone. These again have a still higher end- the answer to the

question, what we ought to do, if the will is free, if there is a

God and a future world. Now, as this problem relates to our in

reference to the highest aim of humanity, it is evident that the

ultimate intention of nature, in the constitution of our reason, has

been directed to the moral alone.

  We must take care, however, in turning our attention to an object

which is foreign* to the sphere of transcendental philosophy, not to

injure the unity of our system by digressions, nor, on the other hand,

to fail in clearness, by saying too little on the new subject of

discussion. I hope to avoid both extremes, by keeping as close as

possible to the transcendental, and excluding all psychological,

that is, empirical, elements.



  *All practical conceptions relate to objects of pleasure and pain,

and consequently- in an indirect manner, at least- to objects of

feeling. But as feeling is not a faculty of representation, but lies

out of the sphere of our powers of cognition, the elements of our

judgements, in so far as they relate to pleasure or pain, that is, the

elements of our practical judgements, do not belong to

transcendental philosophy, which has to do with pure a priori

cognitions alone.



  I have to remark, in the first place, that at present I treat of the

conception of freedom in the practical sense only, and set aside the

corresponding transcendental conception, which cannot be employed as a

ground of explanation in the phenomenal world, but is itself a problem

for pure reason. A will is purely animal (arbitrium brutum) when it is

determined by sensuous impulses or instincts only, that is, when it is

determined in a pathological manner. A will, which can be determined

independently of sensuous impulses, consequently by motives

presented by reason alone, is called a free will (arbitrium

liberum); and everything which is connected with this free will,

either as principle or consequence, is termed practical. The existence

of practical freedom can be proved from experience alone. For the

human will is not determined by that alone which immediately affects

the senses; on the contrary, we have the power, by calling up the

notion of what is useful or hurtful in a more distant relation, of

overcoming the immediate impressions on our sensuous faculty of

desire. But these considerations of what is desirable in relation to

our whole state, that is, is in the end good and useful, are based

entirely upon reason. This faculty, accordingly, enounces laws,

which are imperative or objective laws of freedom and which tell us

what ought to take place, thus distinguishing themselves from the laws

of nature, which relate to that which does take place. The laws of

freedom or of free will are hence termed practical laws.

  Whether reason is not itself, in the actual delivery of these

laws, determined in its turn by other influences, and whether the

action which, in relation to sensuous impulses, we call free, may not,

in relation to higher and more remote operative causes, really form

a part of nature- these are questions which do not here concern us.

They are purely speculative questions; and all we have to do, in the

practical sphere, is to inquire into the rule of conduct which

reason has to present. Experience demonstrates to us the existence

of practical freedom as one of the causes which exist in nature,

that is, it shows the causal power of reason in the determination of

the will. The idea of transcendental freedom, on the contrary,

requires that reason- in relation to its causal power of commencing

a series of phenomena- should be independent of all sensuous

determining causes; and thus it seems to be in opposition to the law

of nature and to all possible experience. It therefore remains a

problem for the human mind. But this problem does not concern reason

in its practical use; and we have, therefore, in a canon of pure

reason, to do with only two questions, which relate to the practical

interest of pure reason: Is there a God? and, Is there a future

life? The question of transcendental freedom is purely speculative,

and we may therefore set it entirely aside when we come to treat of

practical reason. Besides, we have already discussed this subject in

the antinomy of pure reason.



   SECTION II. Of the Ideal of the Summum Bonum as a Determining

           Ground of the Ultimate End of Pure Reason.



  Reason conducted us, in its speculative use, through the field of

experience and, as it can never find complete satisfaction in that

sphere, from thence to speculative ideas- which, however, in the end

brought us back again to experience, and thus fulfilled the purpose of

reason, in a manner which, though useful, was not at all in accordance

with our expectations. It now remains for us to consider whether

pure reason can be employed in a practical sphere, and whether it will

here conduct us to those ideas which attain the highest ends of pure

reason, as we have just stated them. We shall thus ascertain

whether, from the point of view of its practical interest, reason

may not be able to supply us with that which, on the speculative side,

it wholly denies us.

  The whole interest of reason, speculative as well as practical, is

centred in the three following questions:



               1. WHAT CAN I KNOW?

               2. WHAT OUGHT I TO DO?

               3. WHAT MAY I HOPE?



  The first question is purely speculative. We have, as I flatter

myself, exhausted all the replies of which it is susceptible, and have

at last found the reply with which reason must content itself, and

with which it ought to be content, so long as it pays no regard to the

practical. But from the two great ends to the attainment of which

all these efforts of pure reason were in fact directed, we remain just

as far removed as if we had consulted our ease and declined the task

at the outset. So far, then, as knowledge is concerned, thus much,

at least, is established, that, in regard to those two problems, it

lies beyond our reach.

  The second question is purely practical. As such it may indeed

fall within the province of pure reason, but still it is not

transcendental, but moral, and consequently cannot in itself form

the subject of our criticism.

  The third question: If I act as I ought to do, what may I then

hope?- is at once practical and theoretical. The practical forms a

clue to the answer of the theoretical, and- in its highest form-

speculative question. For all hoping has happiness for its object

and stands in precisely the same relation to the practical and the law

of morality as knowing to the theoretical cognition of things and

the law of nature. The former arrives finally at the conclusion that

something is (which determines the ultimate end), because something

ought to take place; the latter, that something is (which operates

as the highest cause), because something does take place.

  Happiness is the satisfaction of all our desires; extensive, in

regard to their multiplicity; intensive, in regard to their degree;

and protensive, in regard to their duration. The practical law based

on the motive of happiness I term a pragmatical law (or prudential

rule); but that law, assuming such to exist, which has no other motive

than the worthiness of being happy, I term a moral or ethical law. The

first tells us what we have to do, if we wish to become possessed of

happiness; the second dictates how we ought to act, in order to

deserve happiness. The first is based upon empirical principles; for

it is only by experience that I can learn either what inclinations

exist which desire satisfaction, or what are the natural means of

satisfying them. The second takes no account of our desires or the

means of satisfying them, and regards only the freedom of a rational

being, and the necessary conditions under which alone this freedom can

harmonize with the distribution of happiness according to

principles. This second law may therefore rest upon mere ideas of pure

reason, and may be cognized a priori.

  I assume that there are pure moral laws which determine, entirely

a priori (without regard to empirical motives, that is, to happiness),

the conduct of a rational being, or in other words, to use which it

makes of its freedom, and that these laws are absolutely imperative

(not merely hypothetically, on the supposition of other empirical

ends), and therefore in all respects necessary. I am warranted in

assuming this, not only by the arguments of the most enlightened

moralists, but by the moral judgement of every man who will make the

attempt to form a distinct conception of such a law.

  Pure reason, then, contains, not indeed in its speculative, but in

its practical, or, more strictly, its moral use, principles of the

possibility of experience, of such actions, namely, as, in

accordance with ethical precepts, might be met with in the history

of man. For since reason commands that such actions should take place,

it must be possible for them to take place; and hence a particular

kind of systematic unity- the moral- must be possible. We have

found, it is true, that the systematic unity of nature could not be

established according to speculative principles of reason, because,

while reason possesses a causal power in relation to freedom, it has

none in relation to the whole sphere of nature; and, while moral

principles of reason can produce free actions, they cannot produce

natural laws. It is, then, in its practical, but especially in its

moral use, that the principles of pure reason possess objective

reality.

  I call the world a moral world, in so far as it may be in accordance

with all the ethical laws- which, by virtue of the freedom of

reasonable beings, it can be, and according to the necessary laws of

morality it ought to be. But this world must be conceived only as an

intelligible world, inasmuch as abstraction is therein made of all

conditions (ends), and even of all impediments to morality (the

weakness or pravity of human nature). So far, then, it is a mere idea-

though still a practical idea- which may have, and ought to have, an

influence on the world of sense, so as to bring it as far as

possible into conformity with itself. The idea of a moral world has,

therefore, objective reality, not as referring to an object of

intelligible intuition- for of such an object we can form no

conception whatever- but to the world of sense- conceived, however, as

an object of pure reason in its practical use- and to a corpus

mysticum of rational beings in it, in so far as the liberum

arbitrium of the individual is placed, under and by virtue of moral

laws, in complete systematic unity both with itself and with the

freedom of all others.

  That is the answer to the first of the two questions of pure

reason which relate to its practical interest: Do that which will

render thee worthy of happiness. The second question is this: If I

conduct myself so as not to be unworthy of happiness, may I hope

thereby to obtain happiness? In order to arrive at the solution of

this question, we must inquire whether the principles of pure

reason, which prescribe a priori the law, necessarily also connect

this hope with it.

  I say, then, that just as the moral principles are necessary

according to reason in its practical use, so it is equally necessary

according to reason in its theoretical use to assume that every one

has ground to hope for happiness in the measure in which he has made

himself worthy of it in his conduct, and that therefore the system

of morality is inseparably (though only in the idea of pure reason)

connected with that of happiness.

  Now in an intelligible, that is, in the moral world, in the

conception of which we make abstraction of all the impediments to

morality (sensuous desires), such a system of happiness, connected

with and proportioned to morality, may be conceived as necessary,

because freedom of volition- partly incited, and partly restrained

by moral laws- would be itself the cause of general happiness; and

thus rational beings, under the guidance of such principles, would

be themselves the authors both of their own enduring welfare and

that of others. But such a system of self-rewarding morality is only

an idea, the carrying out of which depends upon the condition that

every one acts as he ought; in other words, that all actions of

reasonable beings be such as they would be if they sprung from a

Supreme Will, comprehending in, or under, itself all particular wills.

But since the moral law is binding on each individual in the use of

his freedom of volition, even if others should not act in conformity

with this law, neither the nature of things, nor the causality of

actions and their relation to morality, determine how the consequences

of these actions will be related to happiness; and the necessary

connection of the hope of happiness with the unceasing endeavour to

become worthy of happiness, cannot be cognized by reason, if we take

nature alone for our guide. This connection can be hoped for only on

the assumption that the cause of nature is a supreme reason, which

governs according to moral laws.

  I term the idea of an intelligence in which the morally most perfect

will, united with supreme blessedness, is the cause of all happiness

in the world, so far as happiness stands in strict } relation to

morality (as the worthiness of being happy), the ideal of the

supreme Good. supreme original good, that pure reason can find the

ground of the practically necessary connection of both elements of the

highest derivative good, and accordingly of an intelligible, that

is, moral world. Now since we are necessitated by reason to conceive

ourselves as belonging to such a world, while the senses present to us

nothing but a world of phenomena, we must assume the former as a

consequence of our conduct in the world of sense (since the world of

sense gives us no hint of it), and therefore as future in relation

to us. Thus God and a future life are two hypotheses which,

according to the principles of pure reason, are inseparable from the

obligation which this reason imposes upon us.

  Morality per se constitutes a system. But we can form no system of

happiness, except in so far as it is dispensed in strict proportion to

morality. But this is only possible in the intelligible world, under a

wise author and ruler. Such a ruler, together with life in such a

world, which we must look upon as future, reason finds itself

compelled to assume; or it must regard the moral laws as idle

dreams, since the necessary consequence which this same reason

connects with them must, without this hypothesis, fall to the

ground. Hence also the moral laws are universally regarded as

commands, which they could not be did they not connect a priori

adequate consequences with their dictates, and thus carry with them

promises and threats. But this, again, they could not do, did they not

reside in a necessary being, as the Supreme Good, which alone can

render such a teleological unity possible.

  Leibnitz termed the world, when viewed in relation to the rational

beings which it contains, and the moral relations in which they

stand to each other, under the government of the Supreme Good, the

kingdom of Grace, and distinguished it from the kingdom of Nature,

in which these rational beings live, under moral laws, indeed, but

expect no other consequences from their actions than such as follow

according to the course of nature in the world of sense. To view

ourselves, therefore, as in the kingdom of grace, in which all

happiness awaits us, except in so far as we ourselves limit our

participation in it by actions which render us unworthy of

happiness, is a practically necessary idea of reason.

  Practical laws, in so far as they are subjective grounds of actions,

that is, subjective principles, are termed maxims. The judgements of

moral according to in its purity and ultimate results are framed

according ideas; the observance of its laws, according to according to

maxims.

  The whole course of our life must be subject to moral maxims; but

this is impossible, unless with the moral law, which is a mere idea,

reason connects an efficient cause which ordains to all conduct

which is in conformity with the moral law an issue either in this or

in another life, which is in exact conformity with our highest aims.

Thus, without a God and without a world, invisible to us now, but

hoped for, the glorious ideas of morality are, indeed, objects of

approbation and of admiration, but cannot be the springs of purpose

and action. For they do not satisfy all the aims which are natural

to every rational being, and which are determined a priori by pure

reason itself, and necessary.

  Happiness alone is, in the view of reason, far from being the

complete good. Reason does not approve of it (however much inclination

may desire it), except as united with desert. On the other hand,

morality alone, and with it, mere desert, is likewise far from being

the complete good. To make it complete, he who conducts himself in a

manner not unworthy of happiness, must be able to hope for the

possession of happiness. Even reason, unbiased by private ends, or

interested considerations, cannot judge otherwise, if it puts itself

in the place of a being whose business it is to dispense all happiness

to others. For in the practical idea both points are essentially

combined, though in such a way that participation in happiness is

rendered possible by the moral disposition, as its condition, and

not conversely, the moral disposition by the prospect of happiness.

For a disposition which should require the prospect of happiness as

its necessary condition would not be moral, and hence also would not

be worthy of complete happiness- a happiness which, in the view of

reason, recognizes no limitation but such as arises from our own

immoral conduct.

  Happiness, therefore, in exact proportion with the morality of

rational beings (whereby they are made worthy of happiness),

constitutes alone the supreme good of a world into which we absolutely

must transport ourselves according to the commands of pure but

practical reason. This world is, it is true, only an intelligible

world; for of such a systematic unity of ends as it requires, the

world of sense gives us no hint. Its reality can be based on nothing

else but the hypothesis of a supreme original good. In it

independent reason, equipped with all the sufficiency of a supreme

cause, founds, maintains, and fulfils the universal order of things,

with the most perfect teleological harmony, however much this order

may be hidden from us in the world of sense.

  This moral theology has the peculiar advantage, in contrast with

speculative theology, of leading inevitably to the conception of a

sole, perfect, and rational First Cause, whereof speculative

theology does not give us any indication on objective grounds, far

less any convincing evidence. For we find neither in transcendental

nor in natural theology, however far reason may lead us in these,

any ground to warrant us in assuming the existence of one only

Being, which stands at the head of all natural causes, and on which

these are entirely dependent. On the other band, if we take our

stand on moral unity as a necessary law of the universe, and from this

point of view consider what is necessary to give this law adequate

efficiency and, for us, obligatory force, we must come to the

conclusion that there is one only supreme will, which comprehends

all these laws in itself. For how, under different wills, should we

find complete unity of ends? This will must be omnipotent, that all

nature and its relation to morality in the world may be subject to it;

omniscient, that it may have knowledge of the most secret feelings and

their moral worth; omnipresent, that it may be at hand to supply every

necessity to which the highest weal of the world may give rise;

eternal, that this harmony of nature and liberty may never fail; and

so on.

  But this systematic unity of ends in this world of intelligences-

which, as mere nature, is only a world of sense, but, as a system of

freedom of volition, may be termed an intelligible, that is, moral

world (regnum gratiae)- leads inevitably also to the teleological

unity of all things which constitute this great whole, according to

universal natural laws- just as the unity of the former is according

to universal and necessary moral laws- and unites the practical with

the speculative reason. The world must be represented as having

originated from an idea, if it is to harmonize with that use of reason

without which we cannot even consider ourselves as worthy of reason-

namely, the moral use, which rests entirely on the idea of the supreme

good. Hence the investigation of nature receives a teleological

direction, and becomes, in its widest extension, physico-theology. But

this, taking its rise in moral order as a unity founded on the essence

of freedom, and not accidentally instituted by external commands,

establishes the teleological view of nature on grounds which must be

inseparably connected with the internal possibility of things. This

gives rise to a transcendental theology, which takes the ideal of

the highest ontological perfection as a principle of systematic unity;

and this principle connects all things according to universal and

necessary natural laws, because all things have their origin in the

absolute necessity of the one only Primal Being.

  What use can we make of our understanding, even in respect of

experience, if we do not propose ends to ourselves? But the highest

ends are those of morality, and it is only pure reason that can give

us the knowledge of these. Though supplied with these, and putting

ourselves under their guidance, we can make no teleological use of the

knowledge of nature, as regards cognition, unless nature itself has

established teleological unity. For without this unity we should not

even possess reason, because we should have no school for reason,

and no cultivation through objects which afford the materials for

its conceptions. But teleological unity is a necessary unity, and

founded on the essence of the individual will itself. Hence this will,

which is the condition of the application of this unity in concreto,

must be so likewise. In this way the transcendental enlargement of our

rational cognition would be, not the cause, but merely the effect of

the practical teleology which pure reason imposes upon us.

  Hence, also, we find in the history of human reason that, before the

moral conceptions were sufficiently purified and determined, and

before men had attained to a perception of the systematic unity of

ends according to these conceptions and from necessary principles, the

knowledge of nature, and even a considerable amount of intellectual

culture in many other sciences, could produce only rude and vague

conceptions of the Deity, sometimes even admitting of an astonishing

indifference with regard to this question altogether. But the more

enlarged treatment of moral ideas, which was rendered necessary by the

extreme pure moral law of our religion, awakened the interest, and

thereby quickened the perceptions of reason in relation to this

object. In this way, and without the help either of an extended

acquaintance with nature, or of a reliable transcendental insight (for

these have been wanting in all ages), a conception of the Divine Being

was arrived at, which we now bold to be the correct one, not because

speculative reason convinces us of its correctness, but because it

accords with the moral principles of reason. Thus it is to pure

reason, but only in its practical use, that we must ascribe the

merit of having connected with our highest interest a cognition, of

which mere speculation was able only to form a conjecture, but the

validity of which it was unable to establish- and of having thereby

rendered it, not indeed a demonstrated dogma, but a hypothesis

absolutely necessary to the essential ends of reason.

  But if practical reason has reached this elevation, and has attained

to the conception of a sole Primal Being as the supreme good, it

must not, therefore, imagine that it has transcended the empirical

conditions of its application, and risen to the immediate cognition of

new objects; it must not presume to start from the conception which it

has gained, and to deduce from it the moral laws themselves. For it

was these very laws, the internal practical necessity of which led

us to the hypothesis of an independent cause, or of a wise ruler of

the universe, who should give them effect. Hence we are not entitled

to regard them as accidental and derived from the mere will of the

ruler, especially as we have no conception of such a will, except as

formed in accordance with these laws. So far, then, as practical

reason has the right to conduct us, we shall not look upon actions

as binding on us, because they are the commands of God, but we shall

regard them as divine commands, because we are internally bound by

them. We shall study freedom under the teleological unity which

accords with principles of reason; we shall look upon ourselves as

acting in conformity with the divine will only in so far as we hold

sacred the moral law which reason teaches us from the nature of

actions themselves, and we shall believe that we can obey that will

only by promoting the weal of the universe in ourselves and in others.

Moral theology is, therefore, only of immanent use. It teaches us to

fulfil our destiny here in the world, by placing ourselves in

harmony with the general system of ends, and warns us against the

fanaticism, nay, the crime of depriving reason of its legislative

authority in the moral conduct of life, for the purpose of directly

connecting this authority with the idea of the Supreme Being. For this

would be, not an immanent, but a transcendent use of moral theology,

and, like the transcendent use of mere speculation, would inevitably

pervert and frustrate the ultimate ends of reason.



       SECTION III. Of Opinion, Knowledge, and Belief.



  The holding of a thing to be true is a phenomenon in our

understanding which may rest on objective grounds, but requires, also,

subjective causes in the mind of the person judging. If a judgement is

valid for every rational being, then its ground is objectively

sufficient, and it is termed a conviction. If, on the other hand, it

has its ground in the particular character of the subject, it is

termed a persuasion.

  Persuasion is a mere illusion, the ground of the judgement, which

lies solely in the subject, being regarded as objective. Hence a

judgement of this kind has only private validity- is only valid for

the individual who judges, and the holding of a thing to be true in

this way cannot be communicated. But truth depends upon agreement with

the object, and consequently the judgements of all understandings,

if true, must be in agreement with each other (consentientia uni

tertio consentiunt inter se). Conviction may, therefore, be

distinguished, from an external point of view, from persuasion, by the

possibility of communicating it and by showing its validity for the

reason of every man; for in this case the presumption, at least,

arises that the agreement of all judgements with each other, in

spite of the different characters of individuals, rests upon the

common ground of the agreement of each with the object, and thus the

correctness of the judgement is established.

  Persuasion, accordingly, cannot be subjectively distinguished from

conviction, that is, so long as the subject views its judgement simply

as a phenomenon of its own mind. But if we inquire whether the grounds

of our judgement, which are valid for us, produce the same effect on

the reason of others as on our own, we have then the means, though

only subjective means, not, indeed, of producing conviction, but of

detecting the merely private validity of the judgement; in other

words, of discovering that there is in it the element of mere

persuasion.

  If we can, in addition to this, develop the subjective causes of the

judgement, which we have taken for its objective grounds, and thus

explain the deceptive judgement as a phenomenon in our mind, apart

altogether from the objective character of the object, we can then

expose the illusion and need be no longer deceived by it, although, if

its subjective cause lies in our nature, we cannot hope altogether

to escape its influence.

  I can only maintain, that is, affirm as necessarily valid for

every one, that which produces conviction. Persuasion I may keep for

myself, if it is agreeable to me; but I cannot, and ought not, to

attempt to impose it as binding upon others.

  Holding for true, or the subjective validity of a judgement in

relation to conviction (which is, at the same time, objectively

valid), has the three following degrees: opinion, belief, and

knowledge. Opinion is a consciously insufficient judgement,

subjectively as well as objectively. Belief is subjectively

sufficient, but is recognized as being objectively insufficient.

Knowledge is both subjectively and objectively sufficient.

Subjective sufficiency is termed conviction (for myself); objective

sufficiency is termed certainty (for all). I need not dwell longer

on the explanation of such simple conceptions.

  I must never venture to be of opinion, without knowing something, at

least, by which my judgement, in itself merely problematical, is

brought into connection with the truth- which connection, although not

perfect, is still something more than an arbitrary fiction.

Moreover, the law of such a connection must be certain. For if, in

relation to this law, I have nothing more than opinion, my judgement

is but a play of the imagination, without the least relation to truth.

In the judgements of pure reason, opinion has no place. For, as they

do not rest on empirical grounds and as the sphere of pure reason is

that of necessary truth and a priori cognition, the principle of

connection in it requires universality and necessity, and consequently

perfect certainty- otherwise we should have no guide to the truth at

all. Hence it is absurd to have an opinion in pure mathematics; we

must know, or abstain from forming a judgement altogether. The case is

the same with the maxims of morality. For we must not hazard an action

on the mere opinion that it is allowed, but we must know it to be so.

  In the transcendental sphere of reason, on the other hand, the

term opinion is too weak, while the word knowledge is too strong. From

the merely speculative point of view, therefore, we cannot form a

judgement at all. For the subjective grounds of a judgement, such as

produce belief, cannot be admitted in speculative inquiries,

inasmuch as they cannot stand without empirical support and are

incapable of being communicated to others in equal measure.

  But it is only from the practical point of view that a theoretically

insufficient judgement can be termed belief. Now the practical

reference is either to skill or to morality; to the former, when the

end proposed is arbitrary and accidental, to the latter, when it is

absolutely necessary.

  If we propose to ourselves any end whatever, the conditions of its

attainment are hypothetically necessary. The necessity is

subjectively, but still only comparatively, sufficient, if I am

acquainted with no other conditions under which the end can be

attained. On the other hand, it is sufficient, absolutely and for

every one, if I know for certain that no one can be acquainted with

any other conditions under which the attainment of the proposed end

would be possible. In the former case my supposition- my judgement

with regard to certain conditions- is a merely accidental belief; in

the latter it is a necessary belief. The physician must pursue some

course in the case of a patient who is in danger, but is ignorant of

the nature of the disease. He observes the symptoms, and concludes,

according to the best of his judgement, that it is a case of phthisis.

His belief is, even in his own judgement, only contingent: another man

might, perhaps come nearer the truth. Such a belief, contingent

indeed, but still forming the ground of the actual use of means for

the attainment of certain ends, I term Pragmatical belief.

  The usual test, whether that which any one maintains is merely his

persuasion, or his subjective conviction at least, that is, his firm

belief, is a bet. It frequently happens that a man delivers his

opinions with so much boldness and assurance, that he appears to be

under no apprehension as to the possibility of his being in error. The

offer of a bet startles him, and makes him pause. Sometimes it turns

out that his persuasion may be valued at a ducat, but not at ten.

For he does not hesitate, perhaps, to venture a ducat, but if it is

proposed to stake ten, he immediately becomes aware of the possibility

of his being mistaken- a possibility which has hitherto escaped his

observation. If we imagine to ourselves that we have to stake the

happiness of our whole life on the truth of any proposition, our

judgement drops its air of triumph, we take the alarm, and discover

the actual strength of our belief. Thus pragmatical belief has

degrees, varying in proportion to the interests at stake.

  Now, in cases where we cannot enter upon any course of action in

reference to some object, and where, accordingly, our judgement is

purely theoretical, we can still represent to ourselves, in thought,

the possibility of a course of action, for which we suppose that we

have sufficient grounds, if any means existed of ascertaining the

truth of the matter. Thus we find in purely theoretical judgements

an analogon of practical judgements, to which the word belief may

properly be applied, and which we may term doctrinal belief. I

should not hesitate to stake my all on the truth of the proposition-

if there were any possibility of bringing it to the test of

experience- that, at least, some one of the planets, which we see,

is inhabited. Hence I say that I have not merely the opinion, but

the strong belief, on the correctness of which I would stake even many

of the advantages of life, that there are inhabitants in other worlds.

  Now we must admit that the doctrine of the existence of God

belongs to doctrinal belief. For, although in respect to the

theoretical cognition of the universe I do not require to form any

theory which necessarily involves this idea, as the condition of my

explanation of the phenomena which the universe presents, but, on

the contrary, am rather bound so to use my reason as if everything

were mere nature, still teleological unity is so important a condition

of the application of my reason to nature, that it is impossible for

me to ignore it- especially since, in addition to these

considerations, abundant examples of it are supplied by experience.

But the sole condition, so far as my knowledge extends, under which

this unity can be my guide in the investigation of nature, is the

assumption that a supreme intelligence has ordered all things

according to the wisest ends. Consequently, the hypothesis of a wise

author of the universe is necessary for my guidance in the

investigation of nature- is the condition under which alone I can

fulfil an end which is contingent indeed, but by no means unimportant.

Moreover, since the result of my attempts so frequently confirms the

utility of this assumption, and since nothing decisive can be

adduced against it, it follows that it would be saying far too

little to term my judgement, in this case, a mere opinion, and that,

even in this theoretical connection, I may assert that I firmly

believe in God. Still, if we use words strictly, this must not be

called a practical, but a doctrinal belief, which the theology of

nature (physico-theology) must also produce in my mind. In the

wisdom of a Supreme Being, and in the shortness of life, so inadequate

to the development of the glorious powers of human nature, we may find

equally sufficient grounds for a doctrinal belief in the future life

of the human soul.

  The expression of belief is, in such cases, an expression of modesty

from the objective point of view, but, at the same time, of firm

confidence, from the subjective. If I should venture to term this

merely theoretical judgement even so much as a hypothesis which I am

entitled to assume; a more complete conception, with regard to another

world and to the cause of the world, might then be justly required

of me than I am, in reality, able to give. For, if I assume

anything, even as a mere hypothesis, I must, at least, know so much of

the properties of such a being as will enable me, not to form the

conception, but to imagine the existence of it. But the word belief

refers only to the guidance which an idea gives me, and to its

subjective influence on the conduct of my reason, which forces me to

hold it fast, though I may not be in a position to give a

speculative account of it.

  But mere doctrinal belief is, to some extent, wanting in

stability. We often quit our hold of it, in consequence of the

difficulties which occur in speculation, though in the end we

inevitably return to it again.

  It is quite otherwise with moral belief. For in this sphere action

is absolutely necessary, that is, I must act in obedience to the moral

law in all points. The end is here incontrovertibly established, and

there is only one condition possible, according to the best of my

perception, under which this end can harmonize with all other ends,

and so have practical validity- namely, the existence of a God and

of a future world. I know also, to a certainty, that no one can be

acquainted with any other conditions which conduct to the same unity

of ends under the moral law. But since the moral precept is, at the

same time, my maxim (as reason requires that it should be), I am

irresistibly constrained to believe in the existence of God and in a

future life; and I am sure that nothing can make me waver in this

belief, since I should thereby overthrow my moral maxims, the

renunciation of which would render me hateful in my own eyes.

  Thus, while all the ambitious attempts of reason to penetrate beyond

the limits of experience end in disappointment, there is still

enough left to satisfy us in a practical point of view. No one, it

is true, will be able to boast that he knows that there is a God and a

future life; for, if he knows this, be is just the man whom I have

long wished to find. All knowledge, regarding an object of mere

reason, can be communicated; and I should thus be enabled to hope that

my own knowledge would receive this wonderful extension, through the

instrumentality of his instruction. No, my conviction is not

logical, but moral certainty; and since it rests on subjective grounds

(of the moral sentiment), I must not even say: It is morally certain

that there is a God, etc., but: I am morally certain, that is, my

belief in God and in another world is so interwoven with my moral

nature that I am under as little apprehension of having the former

torn from me as of losing the latter.

  The only point in this argument that may appear open to suspicion is

that this rational belief presupposes the existence of moral

sentiments. If we give up this assumption, and take a man who is

entirely indifferent with regard to moral laws, the question which

reason proposes, becomes then merely a problem for speculation and

may, indeed, be supported by strong grounds from analogy, but not by

such as will compel the most obstinate scepticism to give way.* But in

these questions no man is free from all interest. For though the

want of good sentiments may place him beyond the influence of moral

interests, still even in this case enough may be left to make him fear

the existence of God and a future life. For he cannot pretend to any

certainty of the non-existence of God and of a future life, unless-

since it could only be proved by mere reason, and therefore

apodeictically- he is prepared to establish the impossibility of both,

which certainly no reasonable man would undertake to do. This would be

a negative belief, which could not, indeed, produce morality and

good sentiments, but still could produce an analogon of these, by

operating as a powerful restraint on the outbreak of evil

dispositions.



  *The human mind (as, I believe, every rational being must of

necessity do) takes a natural interest in morality, although this

interest is not undivided, and may not be practically in

preponderance. If you strengthen and increase it, you will find the

reason become docile, more enlightened, and more capable of uniting

the speculative interest with the practical. But if you do not take

care at the outset, or at least midway, to make men good, you will

never force them into an honest belief.



  But, it will be said, is this all that pure reason can effect, in

opening up prospects beyond the limits of experience? Nothing more

than two articles of belief? Common sense could have done as much as

this, without taking the philosophers to counsel in the matter!

  I shall not here eulogize philosophy for the benefits which the

laborious efforts of its criticism have conferred on human reason-

even granting that its merit should turn out in the end to be only

negative- for on this point something more will be said in the next

section. But, I ask, do you require that that knowledge which concerns

all men, should transcend the common understanding, and should only be

revealed to you by philosophers? The very circumstance which has

called forth your censure, is the best confirmation of the correctness

of our previous assertions, since it discloses, what could not have

been foreseen, that Nature is not chargeable with any partial

distribution of her gifts in those matters which concern all men

without distinction and that, in respect to the essential ends of

human nature, we cannot advance further with the help of the highest

philosophy, than under the guidance which nature has vouchsafed to the

meanest understanding.

          CHAPTER III. The Architectonic of Pure Reason.



  By the term architectonic I mean the art of constructing a system.

Without systematic unity, our knowledge cannot become science; it will

be an aggregate, and not a system. Thus architectonic is the

doctrine of the scientific in cognition, and therefore necessarily

forms part of our methodology.

  Reason cannot permit our knowledge to remain in an unconnected and

rhapsodistic state, but requires that the sum of our cognitions should

constitute a system. It is thus alone that they can advance the ends

of reason. By a system I mean the unity of various cognitions under

one idea. This idea is the conception- given by reason- of the form of

a whole, in so far as the conception determines a priori not only

the limits of its content, but the place which each of its parts is to

occupy. The scientific idea contains, therefore, the end and the

form of the whole which is in accordance with that end. The unity of

the end, to which all the parts of the system relate, and through

which all have a relation to each other, communicates unity to the

whole system, so that the absence of any part can be immediately

detected from our knowledge of the rest; and it determines a priori

the limits of the system, thus excluding all contingent or arbitrary

additions. The whole is thus an organism (articulatio), and not an

aggregate (coacervatio); it may grow from within (per

intussusceptionem), but it cannot increase by external additions

(per appositionem). It is, thus, like an animal body, the growth of

which does not add any limb, but, without changing their

proportions, makes each in its sphere stronger and more active.

  We require, for the execution of the idea of a system, a schema,

that is, a content and an arrangement of parts determined a priori

by the principle which the aim of the system prescribes. A schema

which is not projected in accordance with an idea, that is, from the

standpoint of the highest aim of reason, but merely empirically, in

accordance with accidental aims and purposes (the number of which

cannot be predetermined), can give us nothing more than technical

unity. But the schema which is originated from an idea (in which

case reason presents us with aims a priori, and does not look for them

to experience), forms the basis of architectonical unity. A science,

in the proper acceptation of that term. cannot be formed

technically, that is, from observation of the similarity existing

between different objects, and the purely contingent use we make of

our knowledge in concreto with reference to all kinds of arbitrary

external aims; its constitution must be framed on architectonical

principles, that is, its parts must be shown to possess an essential

affinity, and be capable of being deduced from one supreme and

internal aim or end, which forms the condition of the possibility of

the scientific whole. The schema of a science must give a priori the

plan of it (monogramma), and the division of the whole into parts,

in conformity with the idea of the science; and it must also

distinguish this whole from all others, according to certain

understood principles.

  No one will attempt to construct a science, unless he have some idea

to rest on as a proper basis. But, in the elaboration of the

science, he finds that the schema, nay, even the definition which he

at first gave of the science, rarely corresponds with his idea; for

this idea lies, like a germ, in our reason, its parts undeveloped

and hid even from microscopical observation. For this reason, we ought

to explain and define sciences, not according to the description which

the originator gives of them, but according to the idea which we

find based in reason itself, and which is suggested by the natural

unity of the parts of the science already accumulated. For it will

of ten be found that the originator of a science and even his latest

successors remain attached to an erroneous idea, which they cannot

render clear to themselves, and that they thus fail in determining the

true content, the articulation or systematic unity, and the limits

of their science.

  It is unfortunate that, only after having occupied ourselves for a

long time in the collection of materials, under the guidance of an

idea which lies undeveloped in the mind, but not according to any

definite plan of arrangement- nay, only after we have spent much

time and labour in the technical disposition of our materials, does it

become possible to view the idea of a science in a clear light, and to

project, according to architectonical principles, a plan of the whole,

in accordance with the aims of reason. Systems seem, like certain

worms, to be formed by a kind of generatio aequivoca- by the mere

confluence of conceptions, and to gain completeness only with the

progress of time. But the schema or germ of all lies in reason; and

thus is not only every system organized according to its own idea, but

all are united into one grand system of human knowledge, of which they

form members. For this reason, it is possible to frame an

architectonic of all human cognition, the formation of which, at the

present time, considering the immense materials collected or to be

found in the ruins of old systems, would not indeed be very difficult.

Our purpose at present is merely to sketch the plan of the

architectonic of all cognition given by pure reason; and we begin from

the point where the main root of human knowledge divides into two, one

of which is reason. By reason I understand here the whole higher

faculty of cognition, the rational being placed in contradistinction

to the empirical.

  If I make complete abstraction of the content of cognition,

objectively considered, all cognition is, from a subjective point of

view, either historical or rational. Historical cognition is

cognitio ex datis, rational, cognitio ex principiis. Whatever may be

the original source of a cognition, it is, in relation to the person

who possesses it, merely historical, if he knows only what has been

given him from another quarter, whether that knowledge was

communicated by direct experience or by instruction. Thus the Person

who has learned a system of philosophy- say the Wolfian- although he

has a perfect knowledge of all the principles, definitions, and

arguments in that philosophy, as well as of the divisions that have

been made of the system, possesses really no more than an historical

knowledge of the Wolfian system; he knows only what has been told him,

his judgements are only those which he has received from his teachers.

Dispute the validity of a definition, and he is completely at a loss

to find another. He has formed his mind on another's; but the

imitative faculty is not the productive. His knowledge has not been

drawn from reason; and although, objectively considered, it is

rational knowledge, subjectively, it is merely historical. He has

learned this or that philosophy and is merely a plaster cast of a

living man. Rational cognitions which are objective, that is, which

have their source in reason, can be so termed from a subjective

point of view, only when they have been drawn by the individual

himself from the sources of reason, that is, from principles; and it

is in this way alone that criticism, or even the rejection of what has

been already learned, can spring up in the mind.

  All rational cognition is, again, based either on conceptions, or on

the construction of conceptions. The former is termed philosophical,

the latter mathematical. I have already shown the essential difference

of these two methods of cognition in the first chapter. A cognition

may be objectively philosophical and subjectively historical- as is

the case with the majority of scholars and those who cannot look

beyond the limits of their system, and who remain in a state of

pupilage all their lives. But it is remarkable that mathematical

knowledge, when committed to memory, is valid, from the subjective

point of view, as rational knowledge also, and that the same

distinction cannot be drawn here as in the case of philosophical

cognition. The reason is that the only way of arriving at this

knowledge is through the essential principles of reason, and thus it

is always certain and indisputable; because reason is employed in

concreto- but at the same time a priori- that is, in pure and,

therefore, infallible intuition; and thus all causes of illusion and

error are excluded. Of all the a priori sciences of reason, therefore,

mathematics alone can be learned. Philosophy- unless it be in an

historical manner- cannot be learned; we can at most learn to

philosophize.

  Philosophy is the system of all philosophical cognition. We must use

this term in an objective sense, if we understand by it the

archetype of all attempts at philosophizing, and the standard by which

all subjective philosophies are to be judged. In this sense,

philosophy is merely the idea of a possible science, which does not

exist in concreto, but to which we endeavour in various ways to

approximate, until we have discovered the right path to pursue- a path

overgrown by the errors and illusions of sense- and the image we

have hitherto tried in vain to shape has become a perfect copy of

the great prototype. Until that time, we cannot learn philosophy- it

does not exist; if it does, where is it, who possesses it, and how

shall we know it? We can only learn to philosophize; in other words,

we can only exercise our powers of reasoning in accordance with

general principles, retaining at the same time, the right of

investigating the sources of these principles, of testing, and even of

rejecting them.

  Until then, our conception of philosophy is only a scholastic

conception- a conception, that is, of a system of cognition which we

are trying to elaborate into a science; all that we at present know

being the systematic unity of this cognition, and consequently the

logical completeness of the cognition for the desired end. But there

is also a cosmical conception (conceptus cosmicus) of philosophy,

which has always formed the true basis of this term, especially when

philosophy was personified and presented to us in the ideal of a

philosopher. In this view philosophy is the science of the relation of

all cognition to the ultimate and essential aims of human reason

(teleologia rationis humanae), and the philosopher is not merely an

artist- who occupies himself with conceptions- but a lawgiver,

legislating for human reason. In this sense of the word, it would be

in the highest degree arrogant to assume the title of philosopher, and

to pretend that we had reached the perfection of the prototype which

lies in the idea alone.

  The mathematician, the natural philosopher, and the logician- how

far soever the first may have advanced in rational, and the two latter

in philosophical knowledge- are merely artists, engaged in the

arrangement and formation of conceptions; they cannot be termed

philosophers. Above them all, there is the ideal teacher, who

employs them as instruments for the advancement of the essential

aims of human reason. Him alone can we call philosopher; but he

nowhere exists. But the idea of his legislative power resides in the

mind of every man, and it alone teaches us what kind of systematic

unity philosophy demands in view of the ultimate aims of reason.

This idea is, therefore, a cosmical conception.*



  *By a cosmical conception, I mean one in which all men necessarily

take an interest; the aim of a science must accordingly be

determined according to scholastic conceptions, if it is regarded

merely as a means to certain arbitrarily proposed ends.



  In view of the complete systematic unity of reason, there can only

be one ultimate end of all the operations of the mind. To this all

other aims are subordinate, and nothing more than means for its

attainment. This ultimate end is the destination of man, and the

philosophy which relates to it is termed moral philosophy. The

superior position occupied by moral philosophy, above all other

spheres for the operations of reason, sufficiently indicates the

reason why the ancients always included the idea- and in an especial

manner- of moralist in that of philosopher. Even at the present day,

we call a man who appears to have the power of self-government, even

although his knowledge may be very limited, by the name of

philosopher.

  The legislation of human reason, or philosophy, has two objects-

nature and freedom- and thus contains not only the laws of nature, but

also those of ethics, at first in two separate systems, which,

finally, merge into one grand philosophical system of cognition. The

philosophy of nature relates to that which is, that of ethics to

that which ought to be.

  But all philosophy is either cognition on the basis of pure

reason, or the cognition of reason on the basis of empirical

principles. The former is termed pure, the latter empirical

philosophy.

  The philosophy of pure reason is either propaedeutic, that is, an

inquiry into the powers of reason in regard to pure a priori

cognition, and is termed critical philosophy; or it is, secondly,

the system of pure reason- a science containing the systematic

presentation of the whole body of philosophical knowledge, true as

well as illusory, given by pure reason- and is called metaphysic. This

name may, however, be also given to the whole system of pure

philosophy, critical philosophy included, and may designate the

investigation into the sources or possibility of a priori cognition,

as well as the presentation of the a priori cognitions which form a

system of pure philosophy- excluding, at the same time, all

empirical and mathematical elements.

  Metaphysic is divided into that of the speculative and that of the

practical use of pure reason, and is, accordingly, either the

metaphysic of nature, or the metaphysic of ethics. The former contains

all the pure rational principles- based upon conceptions alone (and

thus excluding mathematics)- of all theoretical cognition; the latter,

the principles which determine and necessitate a priori all action.

Now moral philosophy alone contains a code of laws- for the regulation

of our actions- which are deduced from principles entirely a priori.

Hence the metaphysic of ethics is the only pure moral philosophy, as

it is not based upon anthropological or other empirical

considerations. The metaphysic of speculative reason is what is

commonly called metaphysic in the more limited sense. But as pure

moral philosophy properly forms a part of this system of cognition, we

must allow it to retain the name of metaphysic, although it is not

requisite that we should insist on so terming it in our present

discussion.

  It is of the highest importance to separate those cognitions which

differ from others both in kind and in origin, and to take great

care that they are not confounded with those with which they are

generally found connected. What the chemist does in the analysis of

substances, what the mathematician in pure mathematics, is, in a still

higher degree, the duty of the philosopher, that the value of each

different kind of cognition, and the part it takes in the operations

of the mind, may be clearly defined. Human reason has never wanted a

metaphysic of some kind, since it attained the power of thought, or

rather of reflection; but it has never been able to keep this sphere

of thought and cognition pure from all admixture of foreign

elements. The idea of a science of this kind is as old as

speculation itself; and what mind does not speculate- either in the

scholastic or in the popular fashion? At the same time, it must be

admitted that even thinkers by profession have been unable clearly

to explain the distinction between the two elements of our

cognition- the one completely a priori, the other a posteriori; and

hence the proper definition of a peculiar kind of cognition, and

with it the just idea of a science which has so long and so deeply

engaged the attention of the human mind, has never been established.

When it was said: "Metaphysic is the science of the first principles

of human cognition," this definition did not signalize a peculiarity

in kind, but only a difference in degree; these first principles

were thus declared to be more general than others, but no criterion of

distinction from empirical principles was given. Of these some are

more general, and therefore higher, than others; and- as we cannot

distinguish what is completely a priori from that which is known to be

a posteriori- where shall we draw the line which is to separate the

higher and so-called first principles, from the lower and

subordinate principles of cognition? What would be said if we were

asked to be satisfied with a division of the epochs of the world

into the earlier centuries and those following them? "Does the

fifth, or the tenth century belong to the earlier centuries?" it would

be asked. In the same way I ask: Does the conception of extension

belong to metaphysics? You answer, "Yes." Well, that of body too?

"Yes." And that of a fluid body? You stop, you are unprepared to admit

this; for if you do, everything will belong to metaphysics. From

this it is evident that the mere degree of subordination- of the

particular to the general- cannot determine the limits of a science;

and that, in the present case, we must expect to find a difference

in the conceptions of metaphysics both in kind and in origin. The

fundamental idea of metaphysics was obscured on another side by the

fact that this kind of a priori cognition showed a certain

similarity in character with the science of mathematics. Both have the

property in common of possessing an a priori origin; but, in the

one, our knowledge is based upon conceptions, in the other, on the

construction of conceptions. Thus a decided dissimilarity between

philosophical and mathematical cognition comes out- a dissimilarity

which was always felt, but which could not be made distinct for want

of an insight into the criteria of the difference. And thus it

happened that, as philosophers themselves failed in the proper

development of the idea of their science, the elaboration of the

science could not proceed with a definite aim, or under trustworthy

guidance. Thus, too, philosophers, ignorant of the path they ought

to pursue and always disputing with each other regarding the

discoveries which each asserted he had made, brought their science

into disrepute with the rest of the world, and finally, even among

themselves.

  All pure a priori cognition forms, therefore, in view of the

peculiar faculty which originates it, a peculiar and distinct unity;

and metaphysic is the term applied to the philosophy which attempts to

represent that cognition in this systematic unity. The speculative

part of metaphysic, which has especially appropriated this

appellation- that which we have called the metaphysic of nature- and

which considers everything, as it is (not as it ought to be), by means

of a priori conceptions, is divided in the following manner.

  Metaphysic, in the more limited acceptation of the term, consists of

two parts- transcendental philosophy and the physiology of pure

reason. The former presents the system of all the conceptions and

principles belonging to the understanding and the reason, and which

relate to objects in general, but not to any particular given

objects (Ontologia); the latter has nature for its subject-matter,

that is, the sum of given objects- whether given to the senses, or, if

we will, to some other kind of intuition- and is accordingly

physiology, although only rationalis. But the use of the faculty of

reason in this rational mode of regarding nature is either physical or

hyperphysical, or, more properly speaking, immanent or transcendent.

The former relates to nature, in so far as our knowledge regarding

it may be applied in experience (in concreto); the latter to that

connection of the objects of experience, which transcends all

experience. Transcendent physiology has, again, an internal and an

external connection with its object, both, however, transcending

possible experience; the former is the physiology of nature as a

whole, or transcendental cognition of the world, the latter of the

connection of the whole of nature with a being above nature, or

transcendental cognition of God.

  Immanent physiology, on the contrary, considers nature as the sum of

all sensuous objects, consequently, as it is presented to us- but

still according to a priori conditions, for it is under these alone

that nature can be presented to our minds at all. The objects of

immanent physiology are of two kinds: 1. Those of the external senses,

or corporeal nature; 2. The object of the internal sense, the soul,

or, in accordance with our fundamental conceptions of it, thinking

nature. The metaphysics of corporeal nature is called physics; but, as

it must contain only the principles of an a priori cognition of

nature, we must term it rational physics. The metaphysics of

thinking nature is called psychology, and for the same reason is to be

regarded as merely the rational cognition of the soul.

  Thus the whole system of metaphysics consists of four principal

parts: 1. Ontology; 2. Rational Physiology; 3. Rational cosmology; and

4. Rational theology. The second part- that of the rational doctrine

of nature- may be subdivided into two, physica rationalis* and

psychologia rationalis.



  *It must not be supposed that I mean by this appellation what is

generally called physica general is, and which is rather mathematics

than a philosophy of nature. For the metaphysic of nature is

completely different from mathematics, nor is it so rich in results,

although it is of great importance as a critical test of the

application of pure understanding-cognition to nature. For want of its

guidance, even mathematicians, adopting certain common notions-

which are, in fact, metaphysical- have unconsciously crowded their

theories of nature with hypotheses, the fallacy of which becomes

evident upon the application of the principles of this metaphysic,

without detriment, however, to the employment of mathematics in this

sphere of cognition.



  The fundamental idea of a philosophy of pure reason of necessity

dictates this division; it is, therefore, architectonical- in

accordance with the highest aims of reason, and not merely

technical, or according to certain accidentally-observed

similarities existing between the different parts of the whole

science. For this reason, also, is the division immutable and of

legislative authority. But the reader may observe in it a few points

to which he ought to demur, and which may weaken his conviction of its

truth and legitimacy.

  In the first place, how can I desire an a priori cognition or

metaphysic of objects, in so far as they are given a posteriori? and

how is it possible to cognize the nature of things according to a

priori principles, and to attain to a rational physiology? The

answer is this. We take from experience nothing more than is requisite

to present us with an object (in general) of the external or of the

internal sense; in the former case, by the mere conception of matter

(impenetrable and inanimate extension), in the latter, by the

conception of a thinking being- given in the internal empirical

representation, I think. As to the rest, we must not employ in our

metaphysic of these objects any empirical principles (which add to the

content of our conceptions by means of experience), for the purpose of

forming by their help any judgements respecting these objects.

  Secondly, what place shall we assign to empirical psychology,

which has always been considered a part of metaphysics, and from which

in our time such important philosophical results have been expected,

after the hope of constructing an a priori system of knowledge had

been abandoned? I answer: It must be placed by the side of empirical

physics or physics proper; that is, must be regarded as forming a part

of applied philosophy, the a priori principles of which are

contained in pure philosophy, which is therefore connected, although

it must not be confounded, with psychology. Empirical psychology

must therefore be banished from the sphere of metaphysics, and is

indeed excluded by the very idea of that science. In conformity,

however, with scholastic usage, we must permit it to occupy a place in

metaphysics- but only as an appendix to it. We adopt this course

from motives of economy; as psychology is not as yet full enough to

occupy our attention as an independent study, while it is, at the same

time, of too great importance to be entirely excluded or placed

where it has still less affinity than it has with the subject of

metaphysics. It is a stranger who has been long a guest; and we make

it welcome to stay, until it can take up a more suitable abode in a

complete system of anthropology- the pendant to empirical physics.

  The above is the general idea of metaphysics, which, as more was

expected from it than could be looked for with justice, and as these

pleasant expectations were unfortunately never realized, fell into

general disrepute. Our Critique must have fully convinced the reader

that, although metaphysics cannot form the foundation of religion,

it must always be one of its most important bulwarks, and that human

reason, which naturally pursues a dialectical course, cannot do

without this science, which checks its tendencies towards dialectic

and, by elevating reason to a scientific and clear self-knowledge,

prevents the ravages which a lawless speculative reason would

infallibly commit in the sphere of morals as well as in that of

religion. We may be sure, therefore, whatever contempt may be thrown

upon metaphysics by those who judge a science not by its own nature,

but according to the accidental effects it may have produced, that

it can never be completely abandoned, that we must always return to it

as to a beloved one who has been for a time estranged, because the

questions with which it is engaged relate to the highest aims of

humanity, and reason must always labour either to attain to settled

views in regard to these, or to destroy those which others have

already established.

  Metaphysic, therefore- that of nature, as well as that of ethics,

but in an especial manner the criticism which forms the propaedeutic

to all the operations of reason- forms properly that department of

knowledge which may be termed, in the truest sense of the word,

philosophy. The path which it pursues is that of science, which,

when it has once been discovered, is never lost, and never misleads.

Mathematics, natural science, the common experience of men, have a

high value as means, for the most part, to accidental ends- but at

last also, to those which are necessary and essential to the existence

of humanity. But to guide them to this high goal, they require the aid

of rational cognition on the basis of pure conceptions, which, be it

termed as it may, is properly nothing but metaphysics.

  For the same reason, metaphysics forms likewise the completion of

the culture of human reason. In this respect, it is indispensable,

setting aside altogether the influence which it exerts as a science.

For its subject-matter is the elements and highest maxims of reason,

which form the basis of the possibility of some sciences and of the

use of all. That, as a purely speculative science, it is more useful

in preventing error than in the extension of knowledge, does not

detract from its value; on the contrary, the supreme office of

censor which it occupies assures to it the highest authority and

importance. This office it administers for the purpose of securing

order, harmony, and well-being to science, and of directing its

noble and fruitful labours to the highest possible aim- the

happiness of all mankind.

             CHAPTER IV. The History of Pure Reason.



  This title is placed here merely for the purpose of designating a

division of the system of pure reason of which I do not intend to

treat at present. I shall content myself with casting a cursory

glance, from a purely transcendental point of view- that of the nature

of pure reason- on the labours of philosophers up to the present time.

They have aimed at erecting an edifice of philosophy; but to my eye

this edifice appears to be in a very ruinous condition.

  It is very remarkable, although naturally it could not have been

otherwise, that, in the infancy of philosophy, the study of the nature

of God and the constitution of a future world formed the commencement,

rather than the conclusion, as we should have it, of the speculative

efforts of the human mind. However rude the religious conceptions

generated by the remains of the old manners and customs of a less

cultivated time, the intelligent classes were not thereby prevented

from devoting themselves to free inquiry into the existence and nature

of God; and they easily saw that there could be no surer way of

pleasing the invisible ruler of the world, and of attaining to

happiness in another world at least, than a good and honest course

of life in this. Thus theology and morals formed the two chief

motives, or rather the points of attraction in all abstract inquiries.

But it was the former that especially occupied the attention of

speculative reason, and which afterwards became so celebrated under

the name of metaphysics.

  I shall not at present indicate the periods of time at which the

greatest changes in metaphysics took place, but shall merely give a

hasty sketch of the different ideas which occasioned the most

important revolutions in this sphere of thought. There are three

different ends in relation to which these revolutions have taken

place.

  1. In relation to the object of the cognition of reason,

philosophers may be divided into sensualists and intellectualists.

Epicurus may be regarded as the head of the former, Plato of the

latter. The distinction here signalized, subtle as it is, dates from

the earliest times, and was long maintained. The former asserted

that reality resides in sensuous objects alone, and that everything

else is merely imaginary; the latter, that the senses are the

parents of illusion and that truth is to be found in the understanding

alone. The former did not deny to the conceptions of the understanding

a certain kind of reality; but with them it was merely logical, with

the others it was mystical. The former admitted intellectual

conceptions, but declared that sensuous objects alone possessed real

existence. The latter maintained that all real objects were

intelligible, and believed that the pure understanding possessed a

faculty of intuition apart from sense, which, in their opinion, served

only to confuse the ideas of the understanding.

  2. In relation to the origin of the pure cognitions of reason, we

find one school maintaining that they are derived entirely from

experience, and another that they have their origin in reason alone.

Aristotle may be regarded as the bead of the empiricists, and Plato of

the noologists. Locke, the follower of Aristotle in modern times,

and Leibnitz of Plato (although he cannot be said to have imitated him

in his mysticism), have not been able to bring this question to a

settled conclusion. The procedure of Epicurus in his sensual system,

in which he always restricted his conclusions to the sphere of

experience, was much more consequent than that of Aristotle and Locke.

The latter especially, after having derived all the conceptions and

principles of the mind from experience, goes so far, in the employment

of these conceptions and principles, as to maintain that we can

prove the existence of God and the existence of God and the

immortality of them objects lying beyond the soul- both of them of

possible experience- with the same force of demonstration as any

mathematical proposition.

  3. In relation to method. Method is procedure according to

principles. We may divide the methods at present employed in the field

of inquiry into the naturalistic and the scientific. The naturalist of

pure reason lays it down as his principle that common reason,

without the aid of science- which he calls sound reason, or common

sense- can give a more satisfactory answer to the most important

questions of metaphysics than speculation is able to do. He must

maintain, therefore, that we can determine the content and

circumference of the moon more certainly by the naked eye, than by the

aid of mathematical reasoning. But this system is mere misology

reduced to principles; and, what is the most absurd thing in this

doctrine, the neglect of all scientific means is paraded as a peculiar

method of extending our cognition. As regards those who are

naturalists because they know no better, they are certainly not to

be blamed. They follow common sense, without parading their

ignorance as a method which is to teach us the wonderful secret, how

we are to find the truth which lies at the bottom of the well of

Democritus.



            Quod sapio satis est mihi, non ego curo Esse quod

  Arcesilas aerumnosique Solones. PERSIUS*



is their motto, under which they may lead a pleasant and praise worthy

life, without troubling themselves with science or troubling science

with them.



  *[Satirae, iii. 78-79. "What I know is enough for I don't care to be

what Arcesilas was, and the wretched Solons."]



  As regards those who wish to pursue a scientific method, they have

now the choice of following either the dogmatical or the sceptical,

while they are bound never to desert the systematic mode of procedure.

When I mention, in relation to the former, the celebrated Wolf, and as

regards the latter, David Hume, I may leave, in accordance with my

present intention, all others unnamed. The critical path alone is

still open. If my reader has been kind and patient enough to accompany

me on this hitherto untravelled route, he can now judge whether, if he

and others will contribute their exertions towards making this

narrow footpath a high road of thought, that which many centuries have

failed to accomplish may not be executed before the close of the

present- namely, to bring Reason to perfect contentment in regard to

that which has always, but without permanent results, occupied her

powers and engaged her ardent desire for knowledge.


                                -THE END-