Book II
Part 1
The kinds of question we ask are as many as the kinds of things which we
know. They are in fact four:-(1) whether the connexion of an attribute
with a thing is a fact, (2) what is the reason of the connexion, (3) whether
a thing exists, (4) What is the nature of the thing. Thus, when our question
concerns a complex of thing and attribute and we ask whether the thing
is thus or otherwise qualified-whether, e.g. the sun suffers eclipse or
not-then we are asking as to the fact of a connexion. That our inquiry
ceases with the discovery that the sun does suffer eclipse is an indication
of this; and if we know from the start that the sun suffers eclipse, we
do not inquire whether it does so or not. On the other hand, when we know
the fact we ask the reason; as, for example, when we know that the sun
is being eclipsed and that an earthquake is in progress, it is the reason
of eclipse or earthquake into which we inquire.
Where a complex is concerned, then, those are the two questions
we ask; but for some objects of inquiry we have a different kind of question
to ask, such as whether there is or is not a centaur or a God. (By 'is
or is not' I mean 'is or is not, without further qualification'; as opposed
to 'is or is not [e.g.] white'.) On the other hand, when we have ascertained
the thing's existence, we inquire as to its nature, asking, for instance,
'what, then, is God?' or 'what is man?'.
Part 2
These, then, are the four kinds of question we ask, and it is in
the answers to these questions that our knowledge consists.
Now when we ask whether a connexion is a fact, or whether a thing
without qualification is, we are really asking whether the connexion or
the thing has a 'middle'; and when we have ascertained either that the
connexion is a fact or that the thing is-i.e. ascertained either the partial
or the unqualified being of the thing-and are proceeding to ask the reason
of the connexion or the nature of the thing, then we are asking what the
'middle' is.
(By distinguishing the fact of the connexion and the existence
of the thing as respectively the partial and the unqualified being of the
thing, I mean that if we ask 'does the moon suffer eclipse?', or 'does
the moon wax?', the question concerns a part of the thing's being; for
what we are asking in such questions is whether a thing is this or that,
i.e. has or has not this or that attribute: whereas, if we ask whether
the moon or night exists, the question concerns the unqualified being of
a thing.)
We conclude that in all our inquiries we are asking either whether
there is a 'middle' or what the 'middle' is: for the 'middle' here is precisely
the cause, and it is the cause that we seek in all our inquiries. Thus,
'Does the moon suffer eclipse?' means 'Is there or is there not a cause
producing eclipse of the moon?', and when we have learnt that there is,
our next question is, 'What, then, is this cause? for the cause through
which a thing is-not is this or that, i.e. has this or that attribute,
but without qualification is-and the cause through which it is-not is without
qualification, but is this or that as having some essential attribute or
some accident-are both alike the middle'. By that which is without qualification
I mean the subject, e.g. moon or earth or sun or triangle; by that which
a subject is (in the partial sense) I mean a property, e.g. eclipse, equality
or inequality, interposition or non-interposition. For in all these examples
it is clear that the nature of the thing and the reason of the fact are
identical: the question 'What is eclipse?' and its answer 'The privation
of the moon's light by the interposition of the earth' are identical with
the question 'What is the reason of eclipse?' or 'Why does the moon suffer
eclipse?' and the reply 'Because of the failure of light through the earth's
shutting it out'. Again, for 'What is a concord? A commensurate numerical
ratio of a high and a low note', we may substitute 'What ratio makes a
high and a low note concordant? Their relation according to a commensurate
numerical ratio.' 'Are the high and the low note concordant?' is equivalent
to 'Is their ratio commensurate?'; and when we find that it is commensurate,
we ask 'What, then, is their ratio?'.
Cases in which the 'middle' is sensible show that the object of
our inquiry is always the 'middle': we inquire, because we have not perceived
it, whether there is or is not a 'middle' causing, e.g. an eclipse. On
the other hand, if we were on the moon we should not be inquiring either
as to the fact or the reason, but both fact and reason would be obvious
simultaneously. For the act of perception would have enabled us to know
the universal too; since, the present fact of an eclipse being evident,
perception would then at the same time give us the present fact of the
earth's screening the sun's light, and from this would arise the
universal.
Thus, as we maintain, to know a thing's nature is to know the reason
why it is; and this is equally true of things in so far as they are said
without qualification to he as opposed to being possessed of some attribute,
and in so far as they are said to be possessed of some attribute such as
equal to right angles, or greater or less.
Part 3
It is clear, then, that all questions are a search for a 'middle'.
Let us now state how essential nature is revealed and in what way it can
be reduced to demonstration; what definition is, and what things are definable.
And let us first discuss certain difficulties which these questions raise,
beginning what we have to say with a point most intimately connected with
our immediately preceding remarks, namely the doubt that might be felt
as to whether or not it is possible to know the same thing in the same
relation, both by definition and by demonstration. It might, I mean, be
urged that definition is held to concern essential nature and is in every
case universal and affirmative; whereas, on the other hand, some conclusions
are negative and some are not universal; e.g. all in the second figure
are negative, none in the third are universal. And again, not even all
affirmative conclusions in the first figure are definable, e.g. 'every
triangle has its angles equal to two right angles'. An argument proving
this difference between demonstration and definition is that to have scientific
knowledge of the demonstrable is identical with possessing a demonstration
of it: hence if demonstration of such conclusions as these is possible,
there clearly cannot also be definition of them. If there could, one might
know such a conclusion also in virtue of its definition without possessing
the demonstration of it; for there is nothing to stop our having the one
without the other.
Induction too will sufficiently convince us of this difference;
for never yet by defining anything-essential attribute or accident-did
we get knowledge of it. Again, if to define is to acquire knowledge of
a substance, at any rate such attributes are not substances.
It is evident, then, that not everything demonstrable can be defined.
What then? Can everything definable be demonstrated, or not? There is one
of our previous arguments which covers this too. Of a single thing qua
single there is a single scientific knowledge. Hence, since to know the
demonstrable scientifically is to possess the demonstration of it, an impossible
consequence will follow:-possession of its definition without its demonstration
will give knowledge of the demonstrable.
Moreover, the basic premisses of demonstrations are definitions,
and it has already been shown that these will be found indemonstrable;
either the basic premisses will be demonstrable and will depend on prior
premisses, and the regress will be endless; or the primary truths will
be indemonstrable definitions.
But if the definable and the demonstrable are not wholly the same,
may they yet be partially the same? Or is that impossible, because there
can be no demonstration of the definable? There can be none, because definition
is of the essential nature or being of something, and all demonstrations
evidently posit and assume the essential nature-mathematical demonstrations,
for example, the nature of unity and the odd, and all the other sciences
likewise. Moreover, every demonstration proves a predicate of a subject
as attaching or as not attaching to it, but in definition one thing is
not predicated of another; we do not, e.g. predicate animal of biped nor
biped of animal, nor yet figure of plane-plane not being figure nor figure
plane. Again, to prove essential nature is not the same as to prove the
fact of a connexion. Now definition reveals essential nature, demonstration
reveals that a given attribute attaches or does not attach to a given subject;
but different things require different demonstrations-unless the one demonstration
is related to the other as part to whole. I add this because if all triangles
have been proved to possess angles equal to two right angles, then this
attribute has been proved to attach to isosceles; for isosceles is a part
of which all triangles constitute the whole. But in the case before us
the fact and the essential nature are not so related to one another, since
the one is not a part of the other.
So it emerges that not all the definable is demonstrable nor all
the demonstrable definable; and we may draw the general conclusion that
there is no identical object of which it is possible to possess both a
definition and a demonstration. It follows obviously that definition and
demonstration are neither identical nor contained either within the other:
if they were, their objects would be related either as identical or as
whole and part.
Part 4
So much, then, for the first stage of our problem. The next step
is to raise the question whether syllogism-i.e. demonstration-of the definable
nature is possible or, as our recent argument assumed,
impossible.
We might argue it impossible on the following grounds:-(a) syllogism
proves an attribute of a subject through the middle term; on the other
hand (b) its definable nature is both 'peculiar' to a subject and predicated
of it as belonging to its essence. But in that case (1) the subject, its
definition, and the middle term connecting them must be reciprocally predicable
of one another; for if A is to C, obviously A is 'peculiar' to B and B
to C-in fact all three terms are 'peculiar' to one another: and further
(2) if A inheres in the essence of all B and B is predicated universally
of all C as belonging to C's essence, A also must be predicated of C as
belonging to its essence.
If one does not take this relation as thus duplicated-if, that
is, A is predicated as being of the essence of B, but B is not of the essence
of the subjects of which it is predicated-A will not necessarily be predicated
of C as belonging to its essence. So both premisses will predicate essence,
and consequently B also will be predicated of C as its essence. Since,
therefore, both premisses do predicate essence-i.e. definable form-C's
definable form will appear in the middle term before the conclusion is
drawn.
We may generalize by supposing that it is possible to prove the
essential nature of man. Let C be man, A man's essential nature--two-footed
animal, or aught else it may be. Then, if we are to syllogize, A must be
predicated of all B. But this premiss will be mediated by a fresh definition,
which consequently will also be the essential nature of man. Therefore
the argument assumes what it has to prove, since B too is the essential
nature of man. It is, however, the case in which there are only the two
premisses-i.e. in which the premisses are primary and immediate-which we
ought to investigate, because it best illustrates the point under
discussion.
Thus they who prove the essential nature of soul or man or anything
else through reciprocating terms beg the question. It would be begging
the question, for example, to contend that the soul is that which causes
its own life, and that what causes its own life is a self-moving number;
for one would have to postulate that the soul is a self-moving number in
the sense of being identical with it. For if A is predicable as a mere
consequent of B and B of C, A will not on that account be the definable
form of C: A will merely be what it was true to say of C. Even if A is
predicated of all B inasmuch as B is identical with a species of A, still
it will not follow: being an animal is predicated of being a man-since
it is true that in all instances to be human is to be animal, just as it
is also true that every man is an animal-but not as identical with being
man.
We conclude, then, that unless one takes both the premisses as
predicating essence, one cannot infer that A is the definable form and
essence of C: but if one does so take them, in assuming B one will have
assumed, before drawing the conclusion, what the definable form of C is;
so that there has been no inference, for one has begged the
question.
Part 5
Nor, as was said in my formal logic, is the method of division
a process of inference at all, since at no point does the characterization
of the subject follow necessarily from the premising of certain other facts:
division demonstrates as little as does induction. For in a genuine demonstration
the conclusion must not be put as a question nor depend on a concession,
but must follow necessarily from its premisses, even if the respondent
deny it. The definer asks 'Is man animal or inanimate?' and then assumes-he
has not inferred-that man is animal. Next, when presented with an exhaustive
division of animal into terrestrial and aquatic, he assumes that man is
terrestrial. Moreover, that man is the complete formula, terrestrial-animal,
does not follow necessarily from the premisses: this too is an assumption,
and equally an assumption whether the division comprises many differentiae
or few. (Indeed as this method of division is used by those who proceed
by it, even truths that can be inferred actually fail to appear as such.)
For why should not the whole of this formula be true of man, and yet not
exhibit his essential nature or definable form? Again, what guarantee is
there against an unessential addition, or against the omission of the final
or of an intermediate determinant of the substantial
being?
The champion of division might here urge that though these lapses
do occur, yet we can solve that difficulty if all the attributes we assume
are constituents of the definable form, and if, postulating the genus,
we produce by division the requisite uninterrupted sequence of terms, and
omit nothing; and that indeed we cannot fail to fulfil these conditions
if what is to be divided falls whole into the division at each stage, and
none of it is omitted; and that this-the dividendum-must without further
question be (ultimately) incapable of fresh specific division. Nevertheless,
we reply, division does not involve inference; if it gives knowledge, it
gives it in another way. Nor is there any absurdity in this: induction,
perhaps, is not demonstration any more than is division, et it does make
evident some truth. Yet to state a definition reached by division is not
to state a conclusion: as, when conclusions are drawn without their appropriate
middles, the alleged necessity by which the inference follows from the
premisses is open to a question as to the reason for it, so definitions
reached by division invite the same question.
Thus to the question 'What is the essential nature of man?' the
divider replies 'Animal, mortal, footed, biped, wingless'; and when at
each step he is asked 'Why?', he will say, and, as he thinks, proves by
division, that all animal is mortal or immortal: but such a formula taken
in its entirety is not definition; so that even if division does demonstrate
its formula, definition at any rate does not turn out to be a conclusion
of inference.
Part 6
Can we nevertheless actually demonstrate what a thing essentially
and substantially is, but hypothetically, i.e. by premising (1) that its
definable form is constituted by the 'peculiar' attributes of its essential
nature; (2) that such and such are the only attributes of its essential
nature, and that the complete synthesis of them is peculiar to the thing;
and thus-since in this synthesis consists the being of the thing-obtaining
our conclusion? Or is the truth that, since proof must be through the middle
term, the definable form is once more assumed in this minor premiss
too?
Further, just as in syllogizing we do not premise what syllogistic
inference is (since the premisses from which we conclude must be related
as whole and part), so the definable form must not fall within the syllogism
but remain outside the premisses posited. It is only against a doubt as
to its having been a syllogistic inference at all that we have to defend
our argument as conforming to the definition of syllogism. It is only when
some one doubts whether the conclusion proved is the definable form that
we have to defend it as conforming to the definition of definable form
which we assumed. Hence syllogistic inference must be possible even without
the express statement of what syllogism is or what definable form
is.
The following type of hypothetical proof also begs the question.
If evil is definable as the divisible, and the definition of a thing's
contrary-if it has one the contrary of the thing's definition; then, if
good is the contrary of evil and the indivisible of the divisible, we conclude
that to be good is essentially to be indivisible. The question is begged
because definable form is assumed as a premiss, and as a premiss which
is to prove definable form. 'But not the same definable form', you may
object. That I admit, for in demonstrations also we premise that 'this'
is predicable of 'that'; but in this premiss the term we assert of the
minor is neither the major itself nor a term identical in definition, or
convertible, with the major.
Again, both proof by division and the syllogism just described
are open to the question why man should be animal-biped-terrestrial and
not merely animal and terrestrial, since what they premise does not ensure
that the predicates shall constitute a genuine unity and not merely belong
to a single subject as do musical and grammatical when predicated of the
same man.
Part 7
How then by definition shall we prove substance or essential nature?
We cannot show it as a fresh fact necessarily following from the assumption
of premisses admitted to be facts-the method of demonstration: we may not
proceed as by induction to establish a universal on the evidence of groups
of particulars which offer no exception, because induction proves not what
the essential nature of a thing is but that it has or has not some attribute.
Therefore, since presumably one cannot prove essential nature by an appeal
to sense perception or by pointing with the finger, what other method
remains?
To put it another way: how shall we by definition prove essential
nature? He who knows what human-or any other-nature is, must know also
that man exists; for no one knows the nature of what does not exist-one
can know the meaning of the phrase or name 'goat-stag' but not what the
essential nature of a goat-stag is. But further, if definition can prove
what is the essential nature of a thing, can it also prove that it exists?
And how will it prove them both by the same process, since definition exhibits
one single thing and demonstration another single thing, and what human
nature is and the fact that man exists are not the same thing? Then too
we hold that it is by demonstration that the being of everything must be
proved-unless indeed to be were its essence; and, since being is not a
genus, it is not the essence of anything. Hence the being of anything as
fact is matter for demonstration; and this is the actual procedure of the
sciences, for the geometer assumes the meaning of the word triangle, but
that it is possessed of some attribute he proves. What is it, then, that
we shall prove in defining essential nature? Triangle? In that case a man
will know by definition what a thing's nature is without knowing whether
it exists. But that is impossible.
Moreover it is clear, if we consider the methods of defining actually
in use, that definition does not prove that the thing defined exists: since
even if there does actually exist something which is equidistant from a
centre, yet why should the thing named in the definition exist? Why, in
other words, should this be the formula defining circle? One might equally
well call it the definition of mountain copper. For definitions do not
carry a further guarantee that the thing defined can exist or that it is
what they claim to define: one can always ask why.
Since, therefore, to define is to prove either a thing's essential
nature or the meaning of its name, we may conclude that definition, if
it in no sense proves essential nature, is a set of words signifying precisely
what a name signifies. But that were a strange consequence; for (1) both
what is not substance and what does not exist at all would be definable,
since even non-existents can be signified by a name: (2) all sets of words
or sentences would be definitions, since any kind of sentence could be
given a name; so that we should all be talking in definitions, and even
the Iliad would be a definition: (3) no demonstration can prove that any
particular name means any particular thing: neither, therefore, do definitions,
in addition to revealing the meaning of a name, also reveal that the name
has this meaning. It appears then from these considerations that neither
definition and syllogism nor their objects are identical, and further that
definition neither demonstrates nor proves anything, and that knowledge
of essential nature is not to be obtained either by definition or by
demonstration.
Part 8
We must now start afresh and consider which of these conclusions
are sound and which are not, and what is the nature of definition, and
whether essential nature is in any sense demonstrable and definable or
in none.
Now to know its essential nature is, as we said, the same as to
know the cause of a thing's existence, and the proof of this depends on
the fact that a thing must have a cause. Moreover, this cause is either
identical with the essential nature of the thing or distinct from it; and
if its cause is distinct from it, the essential nature of the thing is
either demonstrable or indemonstrable. Consequently, if the cause is distinct
from the thing's essential nature and demonstration is possible, the cause
must be the middle term, and, the conclusion proved being universal and
affirmative, the proof is in the first figure. So the method just examined
of proving it through another essential nature would be one way of proving
essential nature, because a conclusion containing essential nature must
be inferred through a middle which is an essential nature just as a 'peculiar'
property must be inferred through a middle which is a 'peculiar' property;
so that of the two definable natures of a single thing this method will
prove one and not the other.
Now it was said before that this method could not amount to demonstration
of essential nature-it is actually a dialectical proof of it-so let us
begin again and explain by what method it can be demonstrated. When we
are aware of a fact we seek its reason, and though sometimes the fact and
the reason dawn on us simultaneously, yet we cannot apprehend the reason
a moment sooner than the fact; and clearly in just the same way we cannot
apprehend a thing's definable form without apprehending that it exists,
since while we are ignorant whether it exists we cannot know its essential
nature. Moreover we are aware whether a thing exists or not sometimes through
apprehending an element in its character, and sometimes accidentally, as,
for example, when we are aware of thunder as a noise in the clouds, of
eclipse as a privation of light, or of man as some species of animal, or
of the soul as a self-moving thing. As often as we have accidental knowledge
that the thing exists, we must be in a wholly negative state as regards
awareness of its essential nature; for we have not got genuine knowledge
even of its existence, and to search for a thing's essential nature when
we are unaware that it exists is to search for nothing. On the other hand,
whenever we apprehend an element in the thing's character there is less
difficulty. Thus it follows that the degree of our knowledge of a thing's
essential nature is determined by the sense in which we are aware that
it exists. Let us then take the following as our first instance of being
aware of an element in the essential nature. Let A be eclipse, C the moon,
B the earth's acting as a screen. Now to ask whether the moon is eclipsed
or not is to ask whether or not B has occurred. But that is precisely the
same as asking whether A has a defining condition; and if this condition
actually exists, we assert that A also actually exists. Or again we may
ask which side of a contradiction the defining condition necessitates:
does it make the angles of a triangle equal or not equal to two right angles?
When we have found the answer, if the premisses are immediate, we know
fact and reason together; if they are not immediate, we know the fact without
the reason, as in the following example: let C be the moon, A eclipse,
B the fact that the moon fails to produce shadows though she is full and
though no visible body intervenes between us and her. Then if B, failure
to produce shadows in spite of the absence of an intervening body, is attributable
A to C, and eclipse, is attributable to B, it is clear that the moon is
eclipsed, but the reason why is not yet clear, and we know that eclipse
exists, but we do not know what its essential nature is. But when it is
clear that A is attributable to C and we proceed to ask the reason of this
fact, we are inquiring what is the nature of B: is it the earth's acting
as a screen, or the moon's rotation or her extinction? But B is the definition
of the other term, viz. in these examples, of the major term A; for eclipse
is constituted by the earth acting as a screen. Thus, (1) 'What is thunder?'
'The quenching of fire in cloud', and (2) 'Why does it thunder?' 'Because
fire is quenched in the cloud', are equivalent. Let C be cloud, A thunder,
B the quenching of fire. Then B is attributable to C, cloud, since fire
is quenched in it; and A, noise, is attributable to B; and B is assuredly
the definition of the major term A. If there be a further mediating cause
of B, it will be one of the remaining partial definitions of
A.
We have stated then how essential nature is discovered and becomes
known, and we see that, while there is no syllogism-i.e. no demonstrative
syllogism-of essential nature, yet it is through syllogism, viz. demonstrative
syllogism, that essential nature is exhibited. So we conclude that neither
can the essential nature of anything which has a cause distinct from itself
be known without demonstration, nor can it be demonstrated; and this is
what we contended in our preliminary discussions.
Part 9
Now while some things have a cause distinct from themselves, others
have not. Hence it is evident that there are essential natures which are
immediate, that is are basic premisses; and of these not only that they
are but also what they are must be assumed or revealed in some other way.
This too is the actual procedure of the arithmetician, who assumes both
the nature and the existence of unit. On the other hand, it is possible
(in the manner explained) to exhibit through demonstration the essential
nature of things which have a 'middle', i.e. a cause of their substantial
being other than that being itself; but we do not thereby demonstrate
it.
Part 10
Since definition is said to be the statement of a thing's nature,
obviously one kind of definition will be a statement of the meaning of
the name, or of an equivalent nominal formula. A definition in this sense
tells you, e.g. the meaning of the phrase 'triangular character'. When
we are aware that triangle exists, we inquire the reason why it exists.
But it is difficult thus to learn the definition of things the existence
of which we do not genuinely know-the cause of this difficulty being, as
we said before, that we only know accidentally whether or not the thing
exists. Moreover, a statement may be a unity in either of two ways, by
conjunction, like the Iliad, or because it exhibits a single predicate
as inhering not accidentally in a single subject.
That then is one way of defining definition. Another kind of definition
is a formula exhibiting the cause of a thing's existence. Thus the former
signifies without proving, but the latter will clearly be a quasi-demonstration
of essential nature, differing from demonstration in the arrangement of
its terms. For there is a difference between stating why it thunders, and
stating what is the essential nature of thunder; since the first statement
will be 'Because fire is quenched in the clouds', while the statement of
what the nature of thunder is will be 'The noise of fire being quenched
in the clouds'. Thus the same statement takes a different form: in one
form it is continuous demonstration, in the other definition. Again, thunder
can be defined as noise in the clouds, which is the conclusion of the demonstration
embodying essential nature. On the other hand the definition of immediates
is an indemonstrable positing of essential nature.
We conclude then that definition is (a) an indemonstrable statement
of essential nature, or (b) a syllogism of essential nature differing from
demonstration in grammatical form, or (c) the conclusion of a demonstration
giving essential nature.
Our discussion has therefore made plain (1) in what sense and of
what things the essential nature is demonstrable, and in what sense and
of what things it is not; (2) what are the various meanings of the term
definition, and in what sense and of what things it proves the essential
nature, and in what sense and of what things it does not; (3) what is the
relation of definition to demonstration, and how far the same thing is
both definable and demonstrable and how far it is not.
Part 11
We think we have scientific knowledge when we know the cause, and
there are four causes: (1) the definable form, (2) an antecedent which
necessitates a consequent, (3) the efficient cause, (4) the final cause.
Hence each of these can be the middle term of a proof, for (a) though the
inference from antecedent to necessary consequent does not hold if only
one premiss is assumed-two is the minimum-still when there are two it holds
on condition that they have a single common middle term. So it is from
the assumption of this single middle term that the conclusion follows necessarily.
The following example will also show this. Why is the angle in a semicircle
a right angle?-or from what assumption does it follow that it is a right
angle? Thus, let A be right angle, B the half of two right angles, C the
angle in a semicircle. Then B is the cause in virtue of which A, right
angle, is attributable to C, the angle in a semicircle, since B=A and the
other, viz. C,=B, for C is half of two right angles. Therefore it is the
assumption of B, the half of two right angles, from which it follows that
A is attributable to C, i.e. that the angle in a semicircle is a right
angle. Moreover, B is identical with (b) the defining form of A, since
it is what A's definition signifies. Moreover, the formal cause has already
been shown to be the middle. (c) 'Why did the Athenians become involved
in the Persian war?' means 'What cause originated the waging of war against
the Athenians?' and the answer is, 'Because they raided Sardis with the
Eretrians', since this originated the war. Let A be war, B unprovoked raiding,
C the Athenians. Then B, unprovoked raiding, is true of C, the Athenians,
and A is true of B, since men make war on the unjust aggressor. So A, having
war waged upon them, is true of B, the initial aggressors, and B is true
of C, the Athenians, who were the aggressors. Hence here too the cause-in
this case the efficient cause-is the middle term. (d) This is no less true
where the cause is the final cause. E.g. why does one take a walk after
supper? For the sake of one's health. Why does a house exist? For the preservation
of one's goods. The end in view is in the one case health, in the other
preservation. To ask the reason why one must walk after supper is precisely
to ask to what end one must do it. Let C be walking after supper, B the
non-regurgitation of food, A health. Then let walking after supper possess
the property of preventing food from rising to the orifice of the stomach,
and let this condition be healthy; since it seems that B, the non-regurgitation
of food, is attributable to C, taking a walk, and that A, health, is attributable
to B. What, then, is the cause through which A, the final cause, inheres
in C? It is B, the non-regurgitation of food; but B is a kind of definition
of A, for A will be explained by it. Why is B the cause of A's belonging
to C? Because to be in a condition such as B is to be in health. The definitions
must be transposed, and then the detail will become clearer. Incidentally,
here the order of coming to be is the reverse of what it is in proof through
the efficient cause: in the efficient order the middle term must come to
be first, whereas in the teleological order the minor, C, must first take
place, and the end in view comes last in time.
The same thing may exist for an end and be necessitated as well.
For example, light shines through a lantern (1) because that which consists
of relatively small particles necessarily passes through pores larger than
those particles-assuming that light does issue by penetration- and (2)
for an end, namely to save us from stumbling. If then, a thing can exist
through two causes, can it come to be through two causes-as for instance
if thunder be a hiss and a roar necessarily produced by the quenching of
fire, and also designed, as the Pythagoreans say, for a threat to terrify
those that lie in Tartarus? Indeed, there are very many such cases, mostly
among the processes and products of the natural world; for nature, in different
senses of the term 'nature', produces now for an end, now by
necessity.
Necessity too is of two kinds. It may work in accordance with a
thing's natural tendency, or by constraint and in opposition to it; as,
for instance, by necessity a stone is borne both upwards and downwards,
but not by the same necessity.
Of the products of man's intelligence some are never due to chance
or necessity but always to an end, as for example a house or a statue;
others, such as health or safety, may result from chance as
well.
It is mostly in cases where the issue is indeterminate (though
only where the production does not originate in chance, and the end is
consequently good), that a result is due to an end, and this is true alike
in nature or in art. By chance, on the other hand, nothing comes to be
for an end.
Part 12
The effect may be still coming to be, or its occurrence may be past or
future, yet the cause will be the same as when it is actually existent-for
it is the middle which is the cause-except that if the effect actually
exists the cause is actually existent, if it is coming to be so is the
cause, if its occurrence is past the cause is past, if future the cause
is future. For example, the moon was eclipsed because the earth intervened,
is becoming eclipsed because the earth is in process of intervening, will
be eclipsed because the earth will intervene, is eclipsed because the earth
intervenes.
To take a second example: assuming that the definition of ice is
solidified water, let C be water, A solidified, B the middle, which is
the cause, namely total failure of heat. Then B is attributed to C, and
A, solidification, to B: ice when B is occurring, has formed when B has
occurred, and will form when B shall occur.
This sort of cause, then, and its effect come to be simultaneously
when they are in process of becoming, and exist simultaneously when they
actually exist; and the same holds good when they are past and when they
are future. But what of cases where they are not simultaneous? Can causes
and effects different from one another form, as they seem to us to form,
a continuous succession, a past effect resulting from a past cause different
from itself, a future effect from a future cause different from it, and
an effect which is coming-to-be from a cause different from and prior to
it? Now on this theory it is from the posterior event that we reason (and
this though these later events actually have their source of origin in
previous events--a fact which shows that also when the effect is coming-to-be
we still reason from the posterior event), and from the event we cannot
reason (we cannot argue that because an event A has occurred, therefore
an event B has occurred subsequently to A but still in the past-and the
same holds good if the occurrence is future)-cannot reason because, be
the time interval definite or indefinite, it will never be possible to
infer that because it is true to say that A occurred, therefore it is true
to say that B, the subsequent event, occurred; for in the interval between
the events, though A has already occurred, the latter statement will be
false. And the same argument applies also to future events; i.e. one cannot
infer from an event which occurred in the past that a future event will
occur. The reason of this is that the middle must be homogeneous, past
when the extremes are past, future when they are future, coming to be when
they are coming-to-be, actually existent when they are actually existent;
and there cannot be a middle term homogeneous with extremes respectively
past and future. And it is a further difficulty in this theory that the
time interval can be neither indefinite nor definite, since during it the
inference will be false. We have also to inquire what it is that holds
events together so that the coming-to-be now occurring in actual things
follows upon a past event. It is evident, we may suggest, that a past event
and a present process cannot be 'contiguous', for not even two past events
can be 'contiguous'. For past events are limits and atomic; so just as
points are not 'contiguous' neither are past events, since both are indivisible.
For the same reason a past event and a present process cannot be 'contiguous',
for the process is divisible, the event indivisible. Thus the relation
of present process to past event is analogous to that of line to point,
since a process contains an infinity of past events. These questions, however,
must receive a more explicit treatment in our general theory of
change.
The following must suffice as an account of the manner in which
the middle would be identical with the cause on the supposition that coming-to-be
is a series of consecutive events: for in the terms of such a series too
the middle and major terms must form an immediate premiss; e.g. we argue
that, since C has occurred, therefore A occurred: and C's occurrence was
posterior, A's prior; but C is the source of the inference because it is
nearer to the present moment, and the starting-point of time is the present.
We next argue that, since D has occurred, therefore C occurred. Then we
conclude that, since D has occurred, therefore A must have occurred; and
the cause is C, for since D has occurred C must have occurred, and since
C has occurred A must previously have occurred.
If we get our middle term in this way, will the series terminate
in an immediate premiss, or since, as we said, no two events are 'contiguous',
will a fresh middle term always intervene because there is an infinity
of middles? No: though no two events are 'contiguous', yet we must start
from a premiss consisting of a middle and the present event as major. The
like is true of future events too, since if it is true to say that D will
exist, it must be a prior truth to say that A will exist, and the cause
of this conclusion is C; for if D will exist, C will exist prior to D,
and if C will exist, A will exist prior to it. And here too the same infinite
divisibility might be urged, since future events are not 'contiguous'.
But here too an immediate basic premiss must be assumed. And in the world
of fact this is so: if a house has been built, then blocks must have been
quarried and shaped. The reason is that a house having been built necessitates
a foundation having been laid, and if a foundation has been laid blocks
must have been shaped beforehand. Again, if a house will be built, blocks
will similarly be shaped beforehand; and proof is through the middle in
the same way, for the foundation will exist before the
house.
Now we observe in Nature a certain kind of circular process of
coming-to-be; and this is possible only if the middle and extreme terms
are reciprocal, since conversion is conditioned by reciprocity in the terms
of the proof. This-the convertibility of conclusions and premisses-has
been proved in our early chapters, and the circular process is an instance
of this. In actual fact it is exemplified thus: when the earth had been
moistened an exhalation was bound to rise, and when an exhalation had risen
cloud was bound to form, and from the formation of cloud rain necessarily
resulted and by the fall of rain the earth was necessarily moistened: but
this was the starting-point, so that a circle is completed; for posit any
one of the terms and another follows from it, and from that another, and
from that again the first.
Some occurrences are universal (for they are, or come-to-be what
they are, always and in ever case); others again are not always what they
are but only as a general rule: for instance, not every man can grow a
beard, but it is the general rule. In the case of such connexions the middle
term too must be a general rule. For if A is predicated universally of
B and B of C, A too must be predicated always and in every instance of
C, since to hold in every instance and always is of the nature of the universal.
But we have assumed a connexion which is a general rule; consequently the
middle term B must also be a general rule. So connexions which embody a
general rule-i.e. which exist or come to be as a general rule-will also
derive from immediate basic premisses.
Part 13
We have already explained how essential nature is set out in the
terms of a demonstration, and the sense in which it is or is not demonstrable
or definable; so let us now discuss the method to be adopted in tracing
the elements predicated as constituting the definable
form.
Now of the attributes which inhere always in each several thing
there are some which are wider in extent than it but not wider than its
genus (by attributes of wider extent mean all such as are universal attributes
of each several subject, but in their application are not confined to that
subject). while an attribute may inhere in every triad, yet also in a subject
not a triad-as being inheres in triad but also in subjects not numbers
at all-odd on the other hand is an attribute inhering in every triad and
of wider application (inhering as it does also in pentad), but which does
not extend beyond the genus of triad; for pentad is a number, but nothing
outside number is odd. It is such attributes which we have to select, up
to the exact point at which they are severally of wider extent than the
subject but collectively coextensive with it; for this synthesis must be
the substance of the thing. For example every triad possesses the attributes
number, odd, and prime in both senses, i.e. not only as possessing no divisors,
but also as not being a sum of numbers. This, then, is precisely what triad
is, viz. a number, odd, and prime in the former and also the latter sense
of the term: for these attributes taken severally apply, the first two
to all odd numbers, the last to the dyad also as well as to the triad,
but, taken collectively, to no other subject. Now since we have shown above'
that attributes predicated as belonging to the essential nature are necessary
and that universals are necessary, and since the attributes which we select
as inhering in triad, or in any other subject whose attributes we select
in this way, are predicated as belonging to its essential nature, triad
will thus possess these attributes necessarily. Further, that the synthesis
of them constitutes the substance of triad is shown by the following argument.
If it is not identical with the being of triad, it must be related to triad
as a genus named or nameless. It will then be of wider extent than triad-assuming
that wider potential extent is the character of a genus. If on the other
hand this synthesis is applicable to no subject other than the individual
triads, it will be identical with the being of triad, because we make the
further assumption that the substance of each subject is the predication
of elements in its essential nature down to the last differentia characterizing
the individuals. It follows that any other synthesis thus exhibited will
likewise be identical with the being of the subject.
The author of a hand-book on a subject that is a generic whole
should divide the genus into its first infimae species-number e.g. into
triad and dyad-and then endeavour to seize their definitions by the method
we have described-the definition, for example, of straight line or circle
or right angle. After that, having established what the category is to
which the subaltern genus belongs-quantity or quality, for instance-he
should examine the properties 'peculiar' to the species, working through
the proximate common differentiae. He should proceed thus because the attributes
of the genera compounded of the infimae species will be clearly given by
the definitions of the species; since the basic element of them all is
the definition, i.e. the simple infirma species, and the attributes inhere
essentially in the simple infimae species, in the genera only in virtue
of these.
Divisions according to differentiae are a useful accessory to this
method. What force they have as proofs we did, indeed, explain above, but
that merely towards collecting the essential nature they may be of use
we will proceed to show. They might, indeed, seem to be of no use at all,
but rather to assume everything at the start and to be no better than an
initial assumption made without division. But, in fact, the order in which
the attributes are predicated does make a difference--it matters whether
we say animal-tame-biped, or biped-animal-tame. For if every definable
thing consists of two elements and 'animal-tame' forms a unity, and again
out of this and the further differentia man (or whatever else is the unity
under construction) is constituted, then the elements we assume have necessarily
been reached by division. Again, division is the only possible method of
avoiding the omission of any element of the essential nature. Thus, if
the primary genus is assumed and we then take one of the lower divisions,
the dividendum will not fall whole into this division: e.g. it is not all
animal which is either whole-winged or split-winged but all winged animal,
for it is winged animal to which this differentiation belongs. The primary
differentiation of animal is that within which all animal falls. The like
is true of every other genus, whether outside animal or a subaltern genus
of animal; e.g. the primary differentiation of bird is that within which
falls every bird, of fish that within which falls every fish. So, if we
proceed in this way, we can be sure that nothing has been omitted: by any
other method one is bound to omit something without knowing
it.
To define and divide one need not know the whole of existence.
Yet some hold it impossible to know the differentiae distinguishing each
thing from every single other thing without knowing every single other
thing; and one cannot, they say, know each thing without knowing its differentiae,
since everything is identical with that from which it does not differ,
and other than that from which it differs. Now first of all this is a fallacy:
not every differentia precludes identity, since many differentiae inhere
in things specifically identical, though not in the substance of these
nor essentially. Secondly, when one has taken one's differing pair of opposites
and assumed that the two sides exhaust the genus, and that the subject
one seeks to define is present in one or other of them, and one has further
verified its presence in one of them; then it does not matter whether or
not one knows all the other subjects of which the differentiae are also
predicated. For it is obvious that when by this process one reaches subjects
incapable of further differentiation one will possess the formula defining
the substance. Moreover, to postulate that the division exhausts the genus
is not illegitimate if the opposites exclude a middle; since if it is the
differentia of that genus, anything contained in the genus must lie on
one of the two sides.
In establishing a definition by division one should keep three
objects in view: (1) the admission only of elements in the definable form,
(2) the arrangement of these in the right order, (3) the omission of no
such elements. The first is feasible because one can establish genus and
differentia through the topic of the genus, just as one can conclude the
inherence of an accident through the topic of the accident. The right order
will be achieved if the right term is assumed as primary, and this will
be ensured if the term selected is predicable of all the others but not
all they of it; since there must be one such term. Having assumed this
we at once proceed in the same way with the lower terms; for our second
term will be the first of the remainder, our third the first of those which
follow the second in a 'contiguous' series, since when the higher term
is excluded, that term of the remainder which is 'contiguous' to it will
be primary, and so on. Our procedure makes it clear that no elements in
the definable form have been omitted: we have taken the differentia that
comes first in the order of division, pointing out that animal, e.g. is
divisible exhaustively into A and B, and that the subject accepts one of
the two as its predicate. Next we have taken the differentia of the whole
thus reached, and shown that the whole we finally reach is not further
divisible-i.e. that as soon as we have taken the last differentia to form
the concrete totality, this totality admits of no division into species.
For it is clear that there is no superfluous addition, since all these
terms we have selected are elements in the definable form; and nothing
lacking, since any omission would have to be a genus or a differentia.
Now the primary term is a genus, and this term taken in conjunction with
its differentiae is a genus: moreover the differentiae are all included,
because there is now no further differentia; if there were, the final concrete
would admit of division into species, which, we said, is not the
case.
To resume our account of the right method of investigation: We
must start by observing a set of similar-i.e. specifically identical-individuals,
and consider what element they have in common. We must then apply the same
process to another set of individuals which belong to one species and are
generically but not specifically identical with the former set. When we
have established what the common element is in all members of this second
species, and likewise in members of further species, we should again consider
whether the results established possess any identity, and persevere until
we reach a single formula, since this will be the definition of the thing.
But if we reach not one formula but two or more, evidently the definiendum
cannot be one thing but must be more than one. I may illustrate my meaning
as follows. If we were inquiring what the essential nature of pride is,
we should examine instances of proud men we know of to see what, as such,
they have in common; e.g. if Alcibiades was proud, or Achilles and Ajax
were proud, we should find on inquiring what they all had in common, that
it was intolerance of insult; it was this which drove Alcibiades to war,
Achilles wrath, and Ajax to suicide. We should next examine other cases,
Lysander, for example, or Socrates, and then if these have in common indifference
alike to good and ill fortune, I take these two results and inquire what
common element have equanimity amid the vicissitudes of life and impatience
of dishonour. If they have none, there will be two genera of pride. Besides,
every definition is always universal and commensurate: the physician does
not prescribe what is healthy for a single eye, but for all eyes or for
a determinate species of eye. It is also easier by this method to define
the single species than the universal, and that is why our procedure should
be from the several species to the universal genera-this for the further
reason too that equivocation is less readily detected in genera than in
infimae species. Indeed, perspicuity is essential in definitions, just
as inferential movement is the minimum required in demonstrations; and
we shall attain perspicuity if we can collect separately the definition
of each species through the group of singulars which we have established
e.g. the definition of similarity not unqualified but restricted to colours
and to figures; the definition of acuteness, but only of sound-and so proceed
to the common universal with a careful avoidance of equivocation. We may
add that if dialectical disputation must not employ metaphors, clearly
metaphors and metaphorical expressions are precluded in definition: otherwise
dialectic would involve metaphors.
Part 14
In order to formulate the connexions we wish to prove we have to
select our analyses and divisions. The method of selection consists in
laying down the common genus of all our subjects of investigation-if e.g.
they are animals, we lay down what the properties are which inhere in every
animal. These established, we next lay down the properties essentially
connected with the first of the remaining classes-e.g. if this first subgenus
is bird, the essential properties of every bird-and so on, always characterizing
the proximate subgenus. This will clearly at once enable us to say in virtue
of what character the subgenera-man, e.g. or horse-possess their properties.
Let A be animal, B the properties of every animal, C D E various species
of animal. Then it is clear in virtue of what character B inheres in D-namely
A-and that it inheres in C and E for the same reason: and throughout the
remaining subgenera always the same rule applies.
We are now taking our examples from the traditional class-names,
but we must not confine ourselves to considering these. We must collect
any other common character which we observe, and then consider with what
species it is connected and what.properties belong to it. For example,
as the common properties of horned animals we collect the possession of
a third stomach and only one row of teeth. Then since it is clear in virtue
of what character they possess these attributes-namely their horned character-the
next question is, to what species does the possession of horns
attach?
Yet a further method of selection is by analogy: for we cannot
find a single identical name to give to a squid's pounce, a fish's spine,
and an animal's bone, although these too possess common properties as if
there were a single osseous nature.
Part 15
Some connexions that require proof are identical in that they possess
an identical 'middle' e.g. a whole group might be proved through 'reciprocal
replacement'-and of these one class are identical in genus, namely all
those whose difference consists in their concerning different subjects
or in their mode of manifestation. This latter class may be exemplified
by the questions as to the causes respectively of echo, of reflection,
and of the rainbow: the connexions to be proved which these questions embody
are identical generically, because all three are forms of repercussion;
but specifically they are different.
Other connexions that require proof only differ in that the 'middle'
of the one is subordinate to the 'middle' of the other. For example: Why
does the Nile rise towards the end of the month? Because towards its close
the month is more stormy. Why is the month more stormy towards its close?
Because the moon is waning. Here the one cause is subordinate to the
other.
Part 16
The question might be raised with regard to cause and effect whether
when the effect is present the cause also is present; whether, for instance,
if a plant sheds its leaves or the moon is eclipsed, there is present also
the cause of the eclipse or of the fall of the leaves-the possession of
broad leaves, let us say, in the latter case, in the former the earth's
interposition. For, one might argue, if this cause is not present, these
phenomena will have some other cause: if it is present, its effect will
be at once implied by it-the eclipse by the earth's interposition, the
fall of the leaves by the possession of broad leaves; but if so, they will
be logically coincident and each capable of proof through the other. Let
me illustrate: Let A be deciduous character, B the possession of broad
leaves, C vine. Now if A inheres in B (for every broad-leaved plant is
deciduous), and B in C (every vine possessing broad leaves); then A inheres
in C (every vine is deciduous), and the middle term B is the cause. But
we can also demonstrate that the vine has broad leaves because it is deciduous.
Thus, let D be broad-leaved, E deciduous, F vine. Then E inheres in F (since
every vine is deciduous), and D in E (for every deciduous plant has broad
leaves): therefore every vine has broad leaves, and the cause is its deciduous
character. If, however, they cannot each be the cause of the other (for
cause is prior to effect, and the earth's interposition is the cause of
the moon's eclipse and not the eclipse of the interposition)-if, then,
demonstration through the cause is of the reasoned fact and demonstration
not through the cause is of the bare fact, one who knows it through the
eclipse knows the fact of the earth's interposition but not the reasoned
fact. Moreover, that the eclipse is not the cause of the interposition,
but the interposition of the eclipse, is obvious because the interposition
is an element in the definition of eclipse, which shows that the eclipse
is known through the interposition and not vice versa.
On the other hand, can a single effect have more than one cause?
One might argue as follows: if the same attribute is predicable of more
than one thing as its primary subject, let B be a primary subject in which
A inheres, and C another primary subject of A, and D and E primary subjects
of B and C respectively. A will then inhere in D and E, and B will be the
cause of A's inherence in D, C of A's inherence in E. The presence of the
cause thus necessitates that of the effect, but the presence of the effect
necessitates the presence not of all that may cause it but only of a cause
which yet need not be the whole cause. We may, however, suggest that if
the connexion to be proved is always universal and commensurate, not only
will the cause be a whole but also the effect will be universal and commensurate.
For instance, deciduous character will belong exclusively to a subject
which is a whole, and, if this whole has species, universally and commensurately
to those species-i.e. either to all species of plant or to a single species.
So in these universal and commensurate connexions the 'middle' and its
effect must reciprocate, i.e. be convertible. Supposing, for example, that
the reason why trees are deciduous is the coagulation of sap, then if a
tree is deciduous, coagulation must be present, and if coagulation is present-not
in any subject but in a tree-then that tree must be
deciduous.
Part 17
Can the cause of an identical effect be not identical in every
instance of the effect but different? Or is that impossible? Perhaps it
is impossible if the effect is demonstrated as essential and not as inhering
in virtue of a symptom or an accident-because the middle is then the definition
of the major term-though possible if the demonstration is not essential.
Now it is possible to consider the effect and its subject as an accidental
conjunction, though such conjunctions would not be regarded as connexions
demanding scientific proof. But if they are accepted as such, the middle
will correspond to the extremes, and be equivocal if they are equivocal,
generically one if they are generically one. Take the question why proportionals
alternate. The cause when they are lines, and when they are numbers, is
both different and identical; different in so far as lines are lines and
not numbers, identical as involving a given determinate increment. In all
proportionals this is so. Again, the cause of likeness between colour and
colour is other than that between figure and figure; for likeness here
is equivocal, meaning perhaps in the latter case equality of the ratios
of the sides and equality of the angles, in the case of colours identity
of the act of perceiving them, or something else of the sort. Again, connexions
requiring proof which are identical by analogy middles also
analogous.
The truth is that cause, effect, and subject are reciprocally predicable
in the following way. If the species are taken severally, the effect is
wider than the subject (e.g. the possession of external angles equal to
four right angles is an attribute wider than triangle or are), but it is
coextensive with the species taken collectively (in this instance with
all figures whose external angles are equal to four right angles). And
the middle likewise reciprocates, for the middle is a definition of the
major; which is incidentally the reason why all the sciences are built
up through definition.
We may illustrate as follows. Deciduous is a universal attribute
of vine, and is at the same time of wider extent than vine; and of fig,
and is of wider extent than fig: but it is not wider than but coextensive
with the totality of the species. Then if you take the middle which is
proximate, it is a definition of deciduous. I say that, because you will
first reach a middle next the subject, and a premiss asserting it of the
whole subject, and after that a middle-the coagulation of sap or something
of the sort-proving the connexion of the first middle with the major: but
it is the coagulation of sap at the junction of leaf-stalk and stem which
defines deciduous.
If an explanation in formal terms of the inter-relation of cause
and effect is demanded, we shall offer the following. Let A be an attribute
of all B, and B of every species of D, but so that both A and B are wider
than their respective subjects. Then B will be a universal attribute of
each species of D (since I call such an attribute universal even if it
is not commensurate, and I call an attribute primary universal if it is
commensurate, not with each species severally but with their totality),
and it extends beyond each of them taken separately.
Thus, B is the cause of A's inherence in the species of D: consequently
A must be of wider extent than B; otherwise why should B be the cause of
A's inherence in D any more than A the cause of B's inherence in D? Now
if A is an attribute of all the species of E, all the species of E will
be united by possessing some common cause other than B: otherwise how shall
we be able to say that A is predicable of all of which E is predicable,
while E is not predicable of all of which A can be predicated? I mean how
can there fail to be some special cause of A's inherence in E, as there
was of A's inherence in all the species of D? Then are the species of E,
too, united by possessing some common cause? This cause we must look for.
Let us call it C.
We conclude, then, that the same effect may have more than one
cause, but not in subjects specifically identical. For instance, the cause
of longevity in quadrupeds is lack of bile, in birds a dry constitution-or
certainly something different.
Part 18
If immediate premisses are not reached at once, and there is not
merely one middle but several middles, i.e. several causes; is the cause
of the property's inherence in the several species the middle which is
proximate to the primary universal, or the middle which is proximate to
the species? Clearly the cause is that nearest to each species severally
in which it is manifested, for that is the cause of the subject's falling
under the universal. To illustrate formally: C is the cause of B's inherence
in D; hence C is the cause of A's inherence in D, B of A's inherence in
C, while the cause of A's inherence in B is B itself.
Part 19
As regards syllogism and demonstration, the definition of, and
the conditions required to produce each of them, are now clear, and with
that also the definition of, and the conditions required to produce, demonstrative
knowledge, since it is the same as demonstration. As to the basic premisses,
how they become known and what is the developed state of knowledge of them
is made clear by raising some preliminary problems.
We have already said that scientific knowledge through demonstration
is impossible unless a man knows the primary immediate premisses. But there
are questions which might be raised in respect of the apprehension of these
immediate premisses: one might not only ask whether it is of the same kind
as the apprehension of the conclusions, but also whether there is or is
not scientific knowledge of both; or scientific knowledge of the latter,
and of the former a different kind of knowledge; and, further, whether
the developed states of knowledge are not innate but come to be in us,
or are innate but at first unnoticed. Now it is strange if we possess them
from birth; for it means that we possess apprehensions more accurate than
demonstration and fail to notice them. If on the other hand we acquire
them and do not previously possess them, how could we apprehend and learn
without a basis of pre-existent knowledge? For that is impossible, as we
used to find in the case of demonstration. So it emerges that neither can
we possess them from birth, nor can they come to be in us if we are without
knowledge of them to the extent of having no such developed state at all.
Therefore we must possess a capacity of some sort, but not such as to rank
higher in accuracy than these developed states. And this at least is an
obvious characteristic of all animals, for they possess a congenital discriminative
capacity which is called sense-perception. But though sense-perception
is innate in all animals, in some the sense-impression comes to persist,
in others it does not. So animals in which this persistence does not come
to be have either no knowledge at all outside the act of perceiving, or
no knowledge of objects of which no impression persists; animals in which
it does come into being have perception and can continue to retain the
sense-impression in the soul: and when such persistence is frequently repeated
a further distinction at once arises between those which out of the persistence
of such sense-impressions develop a power of systematizing them and those
which do not. So out of sense-perception comes to be what we call memory,
and out of frequently repeated memories of the same thing develops experience;
for a number of memories constitute a single experience. From experience
again-i.e. from the universal now stabilized in its entirety within the
soul, the one beside the many which is a single identity within them all-originate
the skill of the craftsman and the knowledge of the man of science, skill
in the sphere of coming to be and science in the sphere of
being.
We conclude that these states of knowledge are neither innate in
a determinate form, nor developed from other higher states of knowledge,
but from sense-perception. It is like a rout in battle stopped by first
one man making a stand and then another, until the original formation has
been restored. The soul is so constituted as to be capable of this
process.
Let us now restate the account given already, though with insufficient
clearness. When one of a number of logically indiscriminable particulars
has made a stand, the earliest universal is present in the soul: for though
the act of sense-perception is of the particular, its content is universal-is
man, for example, not the man Callias. A fresh stand is made among these
rudimentary universals, and the process does not cease until the indivisible
concepts, the true universals, are established: e.g. such and such a species
of animal is a step towards the genus animal, which by the same process
is a step towards a further generalization.
Thus it is clear that we must get to know the primary premisses
by induction; for the method by which even sense-perception implants the
universal is inductive. Now of the thinking states by which we grasp truth,
some are unfailingly true, others admit of error-opinion, for instance,
and calculation, whereas scientific knowing and intuition are always true:
further, no other kind of thought except intuition is more accurate than
scientific knowledge, whereas primary premisses are more knowable than
demonstrations, and all scientific knowledge is discursive. From these
considerations it follows that there will be no scientific knowledge of
the primary premisses, and since except intuition nothing can be truer
than scientific knowledge, it will be intuition that apprehends the primary
premisses-a result which also follows from the fact that demonstration
cannot be the originative source of demonstration, nor, consequently, scientific
knowledge of scientific knowledge.If, therefore, it is the only other kind
of true thinking except scientific knowing, intuition will be the originative
source of scientific knowledge. And the originative source of science grasps
the original basic premiss, while science as a whole is similarly related
as originative source to the whole body of fact.