Indian Philosophy: Historical development of Indian philosophy: FURTHER DEVELOPMENTS OF THE SYSTEM: Nyaya-Vaishesika.: The new school. The founder of the school of Navya-(New) Nyaya, with an exclusive emphasis on the pramanas, was Gangesha Upadhyaya (13th century), whose Tattvacintamani ("The Jewel of Thought on the Nature of Things") is the basic text for all later developments. The logicians of this school were primarily interested in defining their terms and concepts and for this purpose developed an elaborate technical vocabulary and logical apparatus that came to be used by, other than philosophers, writers on law, poetics, aesthetics, and ritualistic liturgy. The school may broadly be divided into two subschools: the Mithila school represented by Vardhamana (Gangesha's son), Paksadhara or Jayadeva (author of Aloka gloss), and Shankara Mishra (author of Upaskara); and the Navadvipa school, whose chief representatives were Vasudeva Sarvabhauma (1450-1525), Raghunatha Shiromani (c. 1475-c. 1550), Mathuranatha Tarkavagisha (fl. c. 1570), Jagadisha Tarkalankara (fl. c. 1625), and Gadadhara Bhattacarya (fl. c. 1650). By means of a new technique of analyzing knowledge, judgmental knowledge can be analyzed into three kinds of epistemological entities in their interrelations: "qualifiers" (prakara); "qualificandum," or that which must be qualified (vishesya); and "relatedness" (samsarga). There also are corresponding abstract entities: qualifierness, qualificandumness, and relatedness. The knowledge expressed by the judgment "This is a blue pot" may then be analyzed into the following form: "The knowledge that has a qualificandumness in what is denoted by 'this' is conditioned by a qualifierness in blue and also conditioned by another qualifierness in potness." A central concept in the Navya-Nyaya logical apparatus is that of "limiterness" (avacchedakata), which has many different uses. If a mountain possesses fire in one region and not in another, it can be said, in the Navya-Nyaya language, "The mountain, as limited by the region r, possesses fire, but as limited by the region r' possesses the absence of fire." The same mode of speech may be extended to limitations of time, property, and relation, particularly when one is in need of constructing a description that is intended to suit exactly some specific situation and none other. Inference is defined by Vatsayana as the "posterior" knowledge of an object (e.g., fire) with the help of knowledge of its mark (e.g., smoke). For Navya-Nyaya, inference is definable as the knowledge caused by the knowledge that the minor term (paksa, "the hill") "possesses" the middle term (hetu, "smoke"), which is recognized as "pervaded by" the major (sadhya, "fire"). The relation of invariable connection, or "pervasion," between the middle (smoke) and the major (fire)--"Wherever there is smoke, there is fire"--is called vyapti. The logicians developed the notion of negation to a great degree
of sophistication. Apart from the efforts to specify a negation with references
to its limiting counterpositive (pratiyogi), limiting relation, and limiting
locus, they were constrained to discuss and debate such typical issues
as the following: Is one to recognize, as a significant negation, the absence
of a thing x so that the limiter of the counterpositive x is not x-ness
but y-ness?
Though the philosophers of this school did not directly write on metaphysics, they nevertheless did tend to introduce many new kinds of abstract entities into their discourse. These entities are generally epistemological, though sometimes they are relational. Chief of these are entities called "qualifierness," "qualificandumness," and "limiterness." Various relations were introduced, such as direct and indirect temporal relations, paryapti relation (in which a number reside, in sets rather than in individual members of those sets), svarupa relation (which holds, for example, between an absence and its locus), and relation between a knowledge and its object. Among the Navya-Nyaya philosophers, Raghunatha Shiromani in Padarthatattvanirupana
undertook a bold revision of the traditional categorial scheme by (1) identifying
"time," "space," and "ether" with God; (2) eliminating the category of
mind by reducing it to matter; (3) denying atoms (paramanu) and dyadic
(paired) combinations of them (dvyanuka), (4) eliminating "number," "separateness,"
"remoteness," and "proximity" from the list of qualities; and (5) rejecting
ultimate particularities (vishesa) on the grounds that it is more rational
to suppose that the eternal substances are by nature distinct. He added
some new categories, however, such as causal power (shakti) and the moment
(ksana), and recognized that there are as many instances of the relation
of inherence as there are cases of it (as contrasted with the older view
that there is only one inherence that is itself present in all cases of
inherence).
38
Texts and commentaries until Vacaspati and the "Samkhya-sutras."
The Yoga-sutras were commented upon by Vyasa in his Vyasa-bhasya
(5th century), which again has two excellent subcommentaries: Vacaspati's
Tattvavaisharadi and Vijnanabhiksu's Yogavarttika, besides the vrtti by
Bhoja (c. 1000).
39
For Vacaspati, creation was viewed in terms of the mere presence of
the selves and the mere presentation to them of Matter (the undifferentiated
primeval stuff). Such a view has obvious difficulties, for it would make
creation eternal, because the selves and Matter are eternally copresent.
Vijnanabhiksu considered the relation between the selves and Matter to
be a real relation that affects Matter but leaves the selves unaffected.
Creation, in accordance with Bhiksu's theism, is due to the influence of
the chief self--i.e., God. Furthermore, whereas the earlier Samkhya authors,
including Vacaspati, did not consider the question about the ontological
status of the gunas, Bhiksu regards them as real, as extremely subtle substances--so
that each guna is held to be infinite in number. In general, the Samkhya-sutras
show a greater Brahmanical influence, and there is a clear tendency to
explain away the points of difference between the Samkhya and the Vedanta.
The author of the sutras tried to show that the Samkhya doctrines are consistent
with theism or even with the Upanisadic conception of Brahman. Vijnanabhiksu
made use of such contexts to emphasize that the atheism of Samkhya is taught
only to discourage men to try to be God, that originally the Samkhya was
theistic, and that the original Vedanta also was theistic. The Upanisadic
doctrine of the unity of selves is interpreted by him to mean an absence
of difference of kind among selves, which is consistent with the Samkhya.
Maya (illusion) for Bhiksu means nothing but the prakrti (Matter) of the
Samkhya.
In epistemology the idea of reflection of the spirit in the organs of knowing, particularly in the buddhi, or intelligence, comes to the forefront. Every cognition ( jnana) is a modification of the buddhi, with consciousness reflected in it. Though this is Vacaspati's account, it does not suffice according to Bhiksu. If there is the mere reflection of the self in the state of the buddhi, this can only account for the fact that the state of cognition seems to be a conscious state; it cannot account for the fact that the self considers itself to be the owner and experiencer of that state. Accounting for this latter fact, Bhiksu postulated a real contact between the self and buddhi as a reflection of the buddhi state back in the self. Vacaspati, taking over a notion emphasized in Indian epistemology for the first time by Kumarila, introduced into the Samkhya theory of knowledge a distinction between two stages of perceptual knowledge. In the first, a stage of nonconceptualized (nirvikalpaka) perception, the object of perception is apprehended vaguely and in a most general manner. In the second stage, this vague knowledge (alocanamatram) is then interpreted and conceptualized by the mind. The interpretation is not so much synthesis as analysis of the vaguely presented totality into its parts. Bhiksu, however, ascribed to the senses the ability to apprehend determinate properties, even independently of the aid of manas. For Samkhya, in general, error is partial truth; there is no negation of error, only supplementation, though later Samkhya authors tended to ascribe error to wrong interpretation. An important contribution to epistemology was made by the writers on the Yoga: this concerns the key notion of vikalpa, which stands for mental states referring to pseudo-objects posited only by words. Such mental states are neither "valid" nor "invalid" and are said to be unavoidable accompaniments of one's use of language. 40
Because the self is not truly an agent acting in the world, neither
merit nor demerit, arising from one's actions, attaches to the self. Morality
has empirical significance. In the long run, what really matters is knowledge.
Nonattached performance of one's duties is an aid toward purifying intelligence
so that it may be conducive to the attainment of knowledge: hence the importance
of the restraints and observances laid down in the Yoga-sutras. The greatest
good is freedom--i.e., aloofness (kaivalya) from matter.
41
Though Patanjali's yoga is known as Raja Yoga (that in which one attains
to self-rule), Hatha Yoga (hatha = "violence," "violent effort": ha = "sun,"
tha = "moon," hatha = "sun and moon," breaths, or breaths travelling through
the right and left nostrils) emphasizes bodily postures, regulation of
breathing, and cleansing processes as means to spiritual perfection. A
basic text on Hatha Yoga is the Hatha-yoga-pradipika ("Light on the Hatha
Yoga"; c. 15th century). As to the relation between the two yogas, a well-known
maxim lays down that "No raja without hatha, and no hatha without raja."
42
The one religious consequence of the Samkhya-Yoga is an emphasis on
austere asceticism and a turning away from the ritualistic elements of
Hinduism deriving from the Brahmanical sources. Though they continue to
remain as an integral part of the Hindu faith, no major religious order
thrived on the basis of these philosophies.
43
Fragments from the Mandukya-karika until Shankara.
Gaudapada's karikas are divided into four parts: the first part
is an explanation of the Upanisad itself, the second part establishes the
unreality of the world, the third part defends the oneness of reality,
and the fourth part, called Alatasanti ("Extinction of the Burning Coal"),
deals with the state of release from suffering. It is not accidental that
Gaudapada used as the title of the fourth part of his work a phrase in
common usage among Buddhist authors. His philosophical views show a considerable
influence of Madhyamika Buddhism, particularly of the Yogacara school,
and one of his main purposes probably was to demonstrate that the teachings
of the Upanisads are compatible with the main doctrines of the Buddhist
idealists. Among his principal philosophical theses were the following:
All things are as unreal as those seen in a dream, for waking experience
and dream are on a par in this regard. In reality, there is no production
and no destruction. His criticisms of the categories of change and causality
are reminiscent of Nagarjuna's.
44
Though Vedanta is frequently referred to as one darshana (viewpoint),
there are, in fact, radically different schools of Vedanta; what binds
them together is common adherence to a common set of texts. These texts
are the Upanisads, the Vedanta-sutras, and the Bhagavadgita--known as the
three prasthanas (the basic scriptures, or texts) of the Vedanta. The founders
of the various schools of Vedanta have all substantiated their positions
by commenting on these three source books. The problems and issues around
which their differences centre are the nature of Brahman; the status of
the phenomenal world; the relation of finite individuals to the Brahman;
and the nature and the means to moksa, or liberation. The main schools
are: Shankara's unqualified nondualism (shuddhadvaita); Ramanuja's qualified
nondualism (vishistadvaita), Madhva's dualism (dvaita); Bhaskara's doctrine
of identity and difference (bhedabheda); and the schools of Nimbarka and
Vallabha, which assert both identity and difference though with different
emphasis on either of the two aspects. From the religious point of view,
Shankara extolled metaphysical knowledge as the sole means to liberation
and regarded even the concept of God as false; Ramanuja recommended the
path of bhakti combined with knowledge and showed a more tolerant attitude
toward the tradition of Vedic ritualism; and Madhva, Nimbarka, and Vallabha
all propounded a personalistic theism in which love and devotion to a personal
God are rated highest. Although Shankara's influence on Indian philosophy
could not be matched by these other schools of Vedanta, in actual religious
life the theistic Vedanta schools have exercised a much greater influence
than the abstract metaphysics of Shankara.
45
Shankara's philosophy is one among a number of other nondualistic philosophies: Bhartrhari's shabdadvaita, the Buddhist's vijnanadvaita, and Gaudapada's ajativada. Shankara's system may then be called atmadvaita--the thesis that the one, universal, eternal, and self-illuminating self whose essence is pure consciousness without a subject (ashraya) and without an object (visaya) from a transcendental point of view alone is real. The phenomenal world and finite individuals, though empirically real, are--from the higher point of view--merely false appearances. In substantiating this thesis Shankara relied as much on the interpretation of scriptural texts as on reasoning. He set down a methodological principle that reason should be used only to justify truths revealed in the scriptures. His own use of reasoning was primarily negative; he showed great logical skill in refuting his opponents' theories. Shankara's followers, however, supplied what is missed in his works--i.e., a positive rational support for his thesis. Shankara's metaphysics is based on a criterion of reality, which
may be briefly formulated as follows: the real is that whose negation is
not possible. It is then argued that the only thing that satisfies this
criterion is consciousness, because denial of consciousness presupposes
the consciousness that denies. It is conceivable that any object is not
existent, but the absence of consciousness is not conceivable. Negation
may be either mutual negation (of difference) or absence. The latter is
either absence of a thing prior to its origination or after its destruction
or absence of a thing in a place other than where it is present. If the
negation of consciousness is not conceivable, then none of these various
kinds of negations can be predicated of consciousness. If difference cannot
be predicated of it, then consciousness is the only reality and anything
different from it would be unreal. If the other three kinds of absence
are not predicable of it, then consciousness should be beginningless, without
end, and ubiquitous. Consequently, it would be without change. Furthermore,
consciousness is self-intimating; all objects depend upon consciousness
for their manifestation. Difference may be either among members of the
same class or of one individual from another of a different class or among
parts of one entity. None of these is true of consciousness. In other words,
there are not many consciousnesses; the plurality of many centres of consciousness
should be viewed as an appearance. There is no reality other than consciousness--i.e.,
no real prakrti; such a thing would only be an unreal other. Also, consciousness
does not have internal parts; there are not many conscious states. The
distinction between consciousness of blue and consciousness of yellow is
not a distinction within consciousness but one superimposed on it by a
distinction among its objects, blue and yellow. With this, the Samkhya,
Vijnanavadin Buddhist, and Nyaya-Vaishesika pluralism are refuted. Reality
is one, infinite, eternal, and self-shining spirit; it is without any determination,
for all determination is negation.
|